Natural Law and Natural Rights Second Edition
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Ia Q. 79 A. 12 Whether Synderesis Is a Special Power of the Soul Distinct
Whether synderesis is a special power of the soul distinct from the others? Ia q. 79 a. 12 Objection 1. It would seem that “synderesis” is a proceeds from the understanding of certain things— special power, distinct from the others. For those things namely, those which are naturally known without any which fall under one division, seem to be of the same investigation on the part of reason, as from an im- genus. But in the gloss of Jerome on Ezech. 1:6, “syn- movable principle—and ends also at the understand- deresis” is divided against the irascible, the concupisci- ing, inasmuch as by means of those principles naturally ble, and the rational, which are powers. Therefore “syn- known, we judge of those things which we have discov- deresis” is a power. ered by reasoning. Now it is clear that, as the specula- Objection 2. Further, opposite things are of the tive reason argues about speculative things, so that prac- same genus. But “synderesis” and sensuality seem to tical reason argues about practical things. Therefore we be opposed to one another because “synderesis” always must have, bestowed on us by nature, not only specu- incites to good; while sensuality always incites to evil: lative principles, but also practical principles. Now the whence it is signified by the serpent, as is clear from first speculative principles bestowed on us by nature do Augustine (De Trin. xii, 12,13). It seems, therefore, not belong to a special power, but to a special habit, that ‘synderesis’ is a power just as sensuality is. -
Sanctification, Homosexuality, and God's Triune Life Iod
itficult to sort out these distinctions. See , 'Psychology and the Church's Teaching pp. 6-23. msibility trans. H. T. Willetts (New York: rrice Vaticana/Paulist Press, 1994), $2357. 'l Children and Suggestions for Pastoral Sanctifi catioil, Homosexuality, and God's Triune Life Eugene F. Rogers, Jr. While Christians have always debated "practical" issues like ordination of women, freeing of slaves, and marriage-like unions for gay and lesbian people,l they have also always treated embodiment as one of the "highest" concerns of their intellectual discourse, from the election of Israel to the incarnation of God and the resurrection of the dead. Put another way, theology has used one set of terms - creation, election, incarnition, resurrection - while ethically charged post-modern discourse uses another - embodiment, race, gender, orientation. Theologians such as Karl Barth tell us that ethics and high theology ought to be closely related,z and anthropologists of religion such as Clifford Geertz tell us similar things about ethos and worldview, or social and intellectual practices.3 Yet only too rarely do Christian ethicists connect doctrines such as incarnation, election, and resurrection with race, gender, and orientation.a My constructive proposals attempt to renegotiate ethos and worldview in Christianity by reference to the central symbols that connect them - where ethos includes the practices of marriage (or lack thereof) for straight, gay, and lesbian people; worldview includes what Christians believe about the world, signally dogmatics ("a critical native model"s); and the central symbol is the body of Christ enacted in the sacraments. Marriage and the Eucharist (as well as baptism and monastic vows) tell Christians what bodies are for before God, or what they mean, by incorporating them into the body of Christ. -
Catholic Legal Thought's Response to Legal Realism John M
Marquette Law Review Volume 98 Article 5 Issue 3 Spring 2015 The orF gotten Jurisprudential Debate: Catholic Legal Thought's Response to Legal Realism John M. Breen Lee J. Strang Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr Part of the Jurisdiction Commons, Public Law and Legal Theory Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Repository Citation John M. Breen and Lee J. Strang, The Forgotten Jurisprudential Debate: Catholic Legal Thought's Response to Legal Realism, 98 Marq. L. Rev. 1203 (2015). Available at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr/vol98/iss3/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Marquette Law Review by an authorized administrator of Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE FORGOTTEN JURISPRUDENTIAL DEBATE: CATHOLIC LEGAL THOUGHT’S RESPONSE TO LEGAL REALISM* JOHN M. BREEN** LEE J. STRANG*** I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................. 1205 II. THE RECEIVED WISDOM IN AMERICAN LEGAL HISTORY: WE’RE ALL REALISTS NOW, AND RIGHTLY SO .......................... 1209 A. The Dominant Narrative: The Triumph of Legal Realism ... 1209 B. The Nonexistent or Weak Rejoinder to Legal Realism by Catholic Legal Scholars ....................................... 1210 III. THE RISE OF LEGAL REALISM AND CATHOLIC LEGAL THOUGHT’S RESPONSE ................................................................... -
A Response to Leonid Sirota and Mark Mancini Stéphane Sérafin, Kerry Sun, and Xavier Foccroulle Ménard*
39 The Common Good and Legal Interpretation: A Response to Leonid Sirota and Mark Mancini Stéphane Sérafin, Kerry Sun, and Xavier Foccroulle Ménard* I. Introduction A renewed interest in the moral foundations of legal interpretation in the United States is increasingly reverberating in Canada. For example, on February 22, 2021, Leonid Sirota and Mark Mancini published a post on the Double Aspect Blog entitled “Interpretation and the Value of Law” (“IVL I”).1 Although the post itself merely claimed to show “[w]hy the inter- pretation of law must strive for objectivity, not pre-determined outcomes,”2 the timing of the piece implies that it was meant to respond specifically to Josh Hammer, the Newsweek cor- respondent and constitutional lawyer, who has recently proposed a framework of “common good originalism”3 to correct the perceived failures of the originalist framework applied by Justice Gorsuch of the US Supreme Court in Bostock.4 This is an argument that Sirota and * Stéphane Sérafin is Assistant Professor, Faculty of Law, Common Law Section, University of Ottawa. Kerry Sun is a graduate of the University of Toronto, Faculty of Law, and a former clerk at the Court of Appeal of Alberta and to Justice Sheilah L. Martin at the Supreme Court of Canada. Xavier Foccroulle Ménard is a graduate of McGill University, Faculty of Law and the University of Toronto, Faculty of Law, and he works at Norton Rose Fulbright LLP. 1 Leonid Sirota & Mark Mancini, “Interpretation and the Value of Law” (22 February 2021), online (blog): Double Aspect <https://doubleaspect.blog/2021/02/22/interpretation-and-the-value-of-law/> [IVL I]. -
Haworthpeter.Pdf (1.4MB)
Community and Federalism in the American Political Tradition A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Georgetown University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Government By Peter Daniel Haworth, M.A. Washington, D.C. December 11, 2008 Community and Federalism in the American Political Tradition Peter Daniel Haworth, M.A. Thesis Advisor: George W. Carey, Ph.D. ABSTRACT Aside from the various minor issues, there are two major questions that are addressed in this dissertation: (1) Can socially cohesive community be attributed to the local and/or federal levels of the American system in the colonial and founding periods? (2) How has the political centralization of the twentieth century affected socially cohesive community and public policy for “sensitive” issues, which require such cohesion to become settled? The author attempts to answer these questions via articulating and defending the following thesis: Socially cohesive community (i.e., a mode of intrinsically valuable friendship community that can develop around shared thick-level values and that is often associated with political activity and local interaction) was a possibility for local- level communities during the colonial and founding periods of American history; whereas, when the colonies/States were grouped together as an aggregate union, they did not constitute a true nation or single community of individuals. Hence, such “union” lacked a common good (and, a fortiori , it lacked a thick-level common good necessary for social cohesion). Through the course of American history, the political system has been centralized or transformed from a federal system into a de facto unitary system, and this change has undermined the possibility of social cohesion at the local level. -
Why Conscience Likes Dogmatic Definitions*
Why Conscience Likes Dogmatic Definitions* T. L.SUTTOR OR us, the word "theology" implies method and system, analysis and Fsynthesis, Greek terms, all of them. Now it is extremely interesting that Aquinas, who more than any other Christian writer might be expected to value the qualities in question, in fact largely avoids using such terms and others like them, including the word "theology" itself. He prefers the strictly scriptural terms: wisdom, understanding, knowledge, doctrine. The "system" and "-ology" words are our words, modem post-renaissance words, Descartes-Kant-Hegel words. This modem desire to discipline linguistic usage in all fields, including religious experience, is no doubt a fine thing, and we are not wrong to attribute such a desire to Aquinas and his heirs. But what is the unifying principle of theological system, guiding methodical analysis of the mysteries of Christianity? How can we make sure that the system we get into print is in truth the wisdom and spiritual understanding which Paul prayed down on the Colossians? The unifying principle, the universal font of theological illumination, is simply purity of conscience. The pure of heart see God; the unseen world is in a certain manner evident to their faith; the objects of their Christian hope have body and substance. John 8: 12 reads: "He that follows me does not walk in darkness." St. Thomas paraphrases: As the gift of love is in all who have the grace that makes men acceptable to God, so too is the gift of understanding ( Ila-Ilae, 8, 4c) . And theology, in this sense of spiritual understanding, is inseparable from the process of Christian salavation. -
Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure
The Force of Union: Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Davis, Robert. 2012. The Force of Union: Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure. Doctoral dissertation, Harvard University. Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:9385627 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA © 2012 Robert Glenn Davis All rights reserved. iii Amy Hollywood Robert Glenn Davis The Force of Union: Affect and Ascent in the Theology of Bonaventure Abstract The image of love as a burning flame is so widespread in the history of Christian literature as to appear inevitable. But as this dissertation explores, the association of amor with fire played a precise and wide-ranging role in Bonaventure’s understanding of the soul’s motive power--its capacity to love and be united with God, especially as that capacity was demonstrated in an exemplary way through the spiritual ascent and death of St. Francis. In drawing out this association, Bonaventure develops a theory of the soul and its capacity for transformation in union with God that gives specificity to the Christian desire for self-abandonment in God and the annihilation of the soul in union with God. Though Bonaventure does not use the language of the soul coming to nothing, he describes a state of ecstasy or excessus mentis that is possible in this life, but which constitutes the death and transformation of the soul in union with God. -
Law, Natural Law, and Human Intelligence: Living the Correlation
Catholic University Law Review Volume 55 Issue 3 Spring 2006 Article 8 2006 Law, Natural Law, and Human Intelligence: Living the Correlation Patrick McKinley Brennan Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.edu/lawreview Recommended Citation Patrick M. Brennan, Law, Natural Law, and Human Intelligence: Living the Correlation, 55 Cath. U. L. Rev. 731 (2006). Available at: https://scholarship.law.edu/lawreview/vol55/iss3/8 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by CUA Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Catholic University Law Review by an authorized editor of CUA Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LAW, NATURAL LAW, AND HUMAN INTELLIGENCE: LIVING THE CORRELATION PatrickMcKinley Brennan' "'Of Law there can be no less acknowledged, than that her seat is the bosom of God, her voice the harmony of the world."" I. WIT AND THE NATURAL LAW, THE QUARTUM QUID We are created "to serve [God] wittily, in the tangle of [our] mind[s]," Sir Thomas More declares in Robert Bolt's play A Man for All Seasons.2 More began his adult life of service of God in the self-imposed silence of the London Charterhouse, and that same life was ended for him, of course, in the isolation of the Tower of London and through the violence of Tower Hill, on account of a self-imposed silence of different inspiration. Between Charterhouse and Tower, Thomas More was as cunning as a serpent to use what considerable wit he could muster to serve God, Church, family, and state, including through law. -
On Finnis's Way In
Volume 57 Issue 5 Article 4 2012 On Finnis's Way In Michelle Madden Dempsey [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr Part of the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Michelle M. Dempsey, On Finnis's Way In, 57 Vill. L. Rev. 827 (2012). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr/vol57/iss5/4 This Symposia is brought to you for free and open access by Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Villanova Law Review by an authorized editor of Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. Dempsey: On Finnis's Way In \\jciprod01\productn\V\VLR\57-5\VLR504.txt unknown Seq: 1 27-DEC-12 13:54 2012] ON FINNIS’S WAY IN MICHELLE MADDEN DEMPSEY* I. PRELUDE TO A SPEECH HAT follows is the text of a speech I delivered at Villanova Univer- Wsity School of Law on the occasion of the sixth Annual John F. Scarpa Conference, honoring the work of Professor John Finnis. The speech as presented was accompanied by a rather elaborate and occasion- ally ridiculous PowerPoint presentation, in which animated stick figures of John Finnis, John Gardner and others moved to and fro, illustrating differ- ent methodological starting points and varying “ways in” to thinking about law.1 My topic concerned methodological issues in general jurisprudence. My goals were three-fold: (1) to put to rest any lingering methodological debates between Finnis and John Gardner; (2) to clarify the distinctions between Finnis’s methodology and that articulated by Julie Dickson and reflected in the work of Joseph Raz; and (3) to outline a more critical approach to thinking about the law, by drawing on what is most appealing in Finnis’s methodology and yet rejecting Finnis’s view regarding the pre- sumptive obligation to obey law. -
Grand Jury Refonn: a Review of Key Issues
If you have issues viewing or accessing this file contact us at NCJRS.gov. U.S. Department of JU5ti,ce •• National Institute of Justice ny Office of Det:eiopmellt, Testillg ami Dissemillatioll lIN II .W , . Grand Jury Refonn: A Review of Key Issues A publication of the National Institute of Justice About the National Institute of Justice Grand Jury Reform: The National Institute of Justice is a research branch of the U.S. Department of Justice. The Institute's A Review of Key Issues mission is to develop knowledge about crime. its causes and control. Priority is given to policy-relevant research that can yield approaches and information State and local agencies can use in preventing and reducing crime. Established in 1979 by the Justice System Improvement Act. :'-JIJ builds upon the foundation laid by the former National Institute of Law Enforcement and Criminal Justice. the first major Federal U.S. Department of Justice 87645 research program on crime and justice. Nat/anal Institute of JUstice Carrying out the mandate assigned by Congress. the National Institute of Justice: This document has been re r d person or orgamzdhon ongln~lI~g~~e~ exact:y as received from the In this document are those of th olnts 0 view or Gil,mons stated • Sponsors research and development to improve and strengthen the criminal justice system and related represent the official POSlllon or pe ,authors and do not necessanly civil justice aspects. with a balanced program of basic and applied research. Jusllce olcles 0 f the National Institute of Permission to reproduce this • Evaluates the effectiveness of federally funded justice improvement programs and identifies programs granted by ~ed matenat has been that promise to be successful if continued or repeated. -
The Conceptions of Self-Evidence in the Finnis Reconstruction of Natural Law
St. Mary's Law Journal Volume 51 Number 2 Article 4 4-2020 The Conceptions of Self-Evidence in the Finnis Reconstruction of Natural Law Kevin P. Lee Campbell University School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.stmarytx.edu/thestmaryslawjournal Part of the Catholic Studies Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Philosophy Commons, Legal History Commons, Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Commons, Natural Law Commons, Other Philosophy Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Kevin P. Lee, The Conceptions of Self-Evidence in the Finnis Reconstruction of Natural Law, 51 ST. MARY'S L.J. 413 (2020). Available at: https://commons.stmarytx.edu/thestmaryslawjournal/vol51/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the St. Mary's Law Journals at Digital Commons at St. Mary's University. It has been accepted for inclusion in St. Mary's Law Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Commons at St. Mary's University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Lee: Self-Evidence in the Finnis Reconstruction of Natural Law ESSAY THE CONCEPTIONS OF SELF-EVIDENCE IN THE FINNIS RECONSTRUCTION OF NATURAL LAW KEVIN P. LEE* I. Introduction ........................................................................................... 414 A. Locating Finnis’ Claim to Self-Evidence .................................... 416 1. The Separation of Fact and Value ........................................ 416 2. The First Principles of Practical Reason ............................. 419 a. Basic Goods are the First Principles of Practical Reason ................................................................................ 421 b. Basic Goods are Dispositions ........................................ 421 c. Basic Goods are Apodictic ............................................. 422 II. Two Conceptions of Self-Evidence ................................................... 426 A. Finnis and Leonine Thomism ..................................................... -
John Finnis's Contribution to the Rediscovery of Aristotelian Ethical Methodology in Aquinas's Moral Philosophy: a Personal Account
Volume 57 Issue 5 Article 7 2012 Practical Reason, Human Nature, and the Epistemology of Ethics: John Finnis's Contribution to the Rediscovery of Aristotelian Ethical Methodology in Aquinas's Moral Philosophy: A Personal Account Martin Rhonheimer Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr Part of the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Martin Rhonheimer, Practical Reason, Human Nature, and the Epistemology of Ethics: John Finnis's Contribution to the Rediscovery of Aristotelian Ethical Methodology in Aquinas's Moral Philosophy: A Personal Account, 57 Vill. L. Rev. 873 (2012). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.villanova.edu/vlr/vol57/iss5/7 This Symposia is brought to you for free and open access by Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Villanova Law Review by an authorized editor of Villanova University Charles Widger School of Law Digital Repository. Rhonheimer: Practical Reason, Human Nature, and the Epistemology of Ethics: J \\jciprod01\productn\V\VLR\57-5\VLR507.txt unknown Seq: 1 27-DEC-12 11:19 2012] PRACTICAL REASON, HUMAN NATURE, AND THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF ETHICS JOHN FINNIS’S CONTRIBUTION TO THE REDISCOVERY OF ARISTOTELIAN ETHICAL METHODOLOGY IN AQUINAS’S MORAL PHILOSOPHY: A PERSONAL ACCOUNT REVEREND MARTIN RHONHEIMER* HEN in 1986, exactly twenty five years ago, I first met John Finnis by Wlistening to a paper he delivered at a Congress in Rome I did this with feelings of admiration and gratitude. At that time I was finishing a book on natural law in Aquinas.1 This book was the fruit of a methodolog- ical turn for which I found confirmation and an important source of fur- ther inspiration in John Finnis’s work on Natural Law2 and on what, in a second book, he called the Fundamentals of Ethics.3 The following, there- fore, is both an account of some aspects of my intellectual biography and an homage to Professor Finnis whom we have come together in this con- ference to honor.