Vesa Hirvonen Mental Disorders in Late Medieval Philosophy and Theology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Vesa Hirvonen Mental Disorders in Late Medieval Philosophy and Theology Vesa Hirvonen Mental Disorders in Late Medieval Philosophy and Theology 1. Introduction There was a time when it was quite commonly believed that the medieval discussions on mental disorders were dominated by witchcraft and demonology. As a matter of fact, this view survived until the 1980s, especially in general histories of medicine.1 This is despite the fact that, since the 1930s, there have been a lengthy series of studies concentrating on various aspects of medieval theories of mental disorders, giving much more balanced view of them. With respect to medieval philosophers and theologians, Thomas Aquinas’s theory of mental disorders has been investigated in at least two monographs: E.E. Krapf’s Thomas de Aquino y la psicopatologia,2 and Jacques Simonnet’s Du concept de maladie mentale chez saint Thomas d’Aquin.3 In addition, there have been several articles dealing with it: Paul Kopp’s “Psychiatrisches bei Thomas von Aquin. Beiträge zur Psychiatrie der Scholastik II” (1935),4 Gottfried Roth’s “Thomas von Aquin in der neueren und neuesten Psychiatrie” (1960),5 and Jacques Simonnet’s “Folie et notations psychopathologiques dans l’oeuvre de Saint Thomas d’Aquin” (1983).6 Albert the Great’s conception of mental disorders has been studied in Paul Kopp’s article “Psychiatrisches bei Albertus Magnus. Beiträge zur Psychiatrie der Scholastik I” (1933),7 and Peter of Spain’s conception in Heinrich Schipperges’s article “Zur Psychologie und Psychiatrie des Petrus Hispanus” (1961).8 Medieval philosophical and theological theories of mental disorders have also been discussed in larger monographs giving an overall view of medieval madness theories, for example, Thomas F. Graham’s Medieval Minds. Mental Health in the Middle Ages (1967),9 H.H. Beek’s De geestesgestoorde in de Middeleeuwen: beeld en bemoeienis (1969),10 1 Discussion on this, see Kroll (1973); Kroll & Bachrach (1984), (1986); Kemp (1990) 112–114. 2 Krapf (1943). See also Kraus (1971). 3 Simonnet (1971). 4 Kopp (1935). 5 Roth (1960). 6 Simonnet (1983). 7 Kopp (1933). 8 Schipperges (1961). 9 Graham (1967). 10 Beek (1969), 2nd ed., see Beek (1974). Vesa Hirvonen, Toivo J. Holopainen & Miira Tuominen (eds.), Mind and Modality: Studies in the History of Philosophy in Honour of Simo Knuuttila. Leiden: Brill, 2006. 172 vesa hirvonen Basil Clarke’s Mental Disorder in Earlier Britain: Exploratory Studies (1975),11 Judith S. Neaman’s Suggestion of the Devil. The Origins of Madness (1975),12 Muriel Laharie’s La folie au Moyen Age XIe–XIIIe siècles (1991),13 and Jean Marie Fritz’s La folie au Moyen Age XIe–XIIIe siècles (1992).14 There are also studies of particular theological questions linked with madness, such as investigations into demonic possession15 and sacred folly.16 Various theological and philosophical questions have also been dealt with in studies of medieval juridical madness-theories,17 and in the studies of medieval medical theories of madness.18 Almost all of the studies dealing with medieval discussions on mental disorders concentrate on the Early or High Middle Ages. This is particularly true in the case of philosophical and theological discussions. A reason for this is that the most of the late medieval philosophers and theologians do not seem to have written systematically on mental disorders. Many of them, however, remarked on them in various contexts. Despite the lack of scholarly work concerning late medieval madness-conceptions, there have been rather pointed interpretations of them. Sometimes even those who have defended the rational character of the early or high medieval approaches to madness have claimed that, after Thomas Aquinas, the rational attitude changed. Thomas F. Graham wrote in his book Medieval minds. Mental health in the Middle Ages (1967) that philosophers after Thomas, such as Scotus and his followers, had “resistence to progress in learning,” and they “failed to grasp the objective spirit of Aristotle and Aquinas”: John Duns Scotus opposed the views of Aquinas and emphatically linked mental disorders with Satan. The uncompromising Scotus and his hair-splitting Dunsers 11 Clarke (1975). 12 Neaman (1975). 13 Laharie (1991). 14 Fritz (1992). 15 Kemp & Williams (1987); Kemp (1989), (1990) 135–146. 16 Saward (1980), esp. 31–103;Kinsman(1974), esp. 277–278. There are remarks concerning theological folly also in Swain (1932). For Nicholas of Cusa’s conception of folly, see Rice (1957); Billington (1984) 23–24. 17 For madness in Canon Law and in the revived Roman Law, see Pickett (1952); Kuttner (1935) 85–110;Neaman(1975) 70–106;Dols(1992) 431–433;Midelfort(1999) 188–191.Formadness in English Law, see Neaman (1975) 106–110;Kemp(1990) 125–128. 18 For articles dealing with medieval medical approaches to madness, see Jackson (1972); Kroll (1973); Mora (1978), (1980); Neugebauer (1979); Kroll & Bachrach (1982), (1984), (1986); Jacquart (1983); Pablo (1994). See also Kemp (1990) 114–125. The Peter of Spain -study and the Aquinas-studies mentioned above also belong partly to this group. For overall monographs, see Graham (1967); Beek (1969); Clarke (1975); Neaman (1975); Laharie (1991); Fritz (1992). For other relevant studies, see Schipperges (1990) 111–130..
Recommended publications
  • Index Nominum
    Index Nominum Abualcasim, 50 Alfred of Sareshal, 319n Achillini, Alessandro, 179, 294–95 Algazali, 52n Adalbertus Ranconis de Ericinio, Ali, Ismail, 8n, 132 205n Alkindi, 304 Adam, 313 Allan, Mowbray, 276n Adam of Papenhoven, 222n Alne, Robert, 208n Adamson, Melitta Weiss, 136n Alonso, Manual, 46 Adenulf of Anagni, 301, 384 Alphonse of Poitiers, 193, 234 Adrian IV, pope, 108 Alverny, Marie-Thérèse d’, 35, 46, Afonso I Henriques, king of Portu- 50, 53n, 93, 147, 177, 264n, 303, gal, 35 308n Aimery, archdeacon of Tripoli, Alvicinus de Cremona, 368 105–6 Amadaeus VIII, duke of Savoy, Alberic of Trois Fontaines, 100–101 231 Albert de Robertis, bishop of Ambrose, 289 Tripoli, 106 Anastasius IV, pope, 108 Albert of Rizzato, patriarch of Anti- Anatoli, Jacob, 113 och, 73, 77n, 86–87, 105–6, 122, Andreas the Jew, 116 140 Andrew of Cornwall, 201n Albert of Schmidmüln, 215n, 269 Andrew of Sens, 199, 200–202 Albertus Magnus, 1, 174, 185, 191, Antonius de Colell, 268 194, 212n, 227, 229, 231, 245–48, Antweiler, Wolfgang, 70n, 74n, 77n, 250–51, 271, 284, 298, 303, 310, 105n, 106 315–16, 332 Aquinas, Thomas, 114, 256, 258, Albohali, 46, 53, 56 280n, 298, 315, 317 Albrecht I, duke of Austria, 254–55 Aratus, 41 Albumasar, 36, 45, 50, 55, 59, Aristippus, Henry, 91, 329 304 Arnald of Villanova, 1, 156, 229, 235, Alcabitius, 51, 56 267 Alderotti, Taddeo, 186 Arnaud of Verdale, 211n, 268 Alexander III, pope, 65, 150 Ashraf, al-, 139n Alexander IV, pope, 82 Augustine (of Hippo), 331 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 311, Augustine of Trent, 231 336–37 Aulus Gellius,
    [Show full text]
  • Approaches to the Extramission Postulate in 13Th Century Theories of Vision Lukáš Lička
    The Visual Process: Immediate or Successive? Approaches to the Extramission Postulate in 13th Century Theories of Vision Lukáš Lička [Penultimate draft. For the published version, see L. Lička, “The Visual Process: Immediate or Successive? Approaches to the Extramission Postulate in 13th Century Theories of Vision”, in Medieval Perceptual Puzzles: Theories of Sense-Perception in the 13th and 14th Centuries, edited by E. Băltuță, Leiden: Brill, 2020, pp. 73–110.] Introduction Is vision merely a state of the beholder’s sensory organ which can be explained as an immediate effect caused by external sensible objects? Or is it rather a successive process in which the observer actively scanning the surrounding environment plays a major part? These two general attitudes towards visual perception were both developed already by ancient thinkers. The former is embraced by natural philosophers (e.g., atomists and Aristotelians) and is often labelled “intromissionist”, based on their assumption that vision is an outcome of the causal influence exerted by an external object upon a sensory organ receiving an entity from the object. The latter attitude to vision as a successive process is rather linked to the “extramissionist” theories of the proponents of geometrical optics (such as Euclid or Ptolemy) who suggest that an entity – a visual ray – is sent forth from the eyes to the object.1 The present paper focuses on the contributions to this ancient controversy proposed by some 13th-century Latin thinkers. In contemporary historiography of medieval Latin philosophy, the general narrative is that whereas thinkers in the 12th century held various (mostly Platonic) versions of the extramission theory, the situation changes during the first half of the 13th century when texts by Avicenna, Aristotle (with the commentaries by Averroes), and especially Alhacen, who all favour the intromissionist paradigm, were gradually assimilated.2 It is assumed that, as a result, 1 For an account of the ancient theories of vision based on this line of conflict see especially D.
    [Show full text]
  • Scholastic Manuscripts of the Physician Peter of Spain (13Th Century)
    Acta Scientiarum http://periodicos.uem.br/ojs/acta ISSN on-line: 2178-5201 Doi: 10.4025/actascieduc.v41i1.48131 HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION Scholastic manuscripts of the physician Peter of Spain (13th century) Dulce Oliveira Amarante dos Santos Programa de Pós-Graduação em História, Faculdade de História, Universidade Federal de Goiás, Av. Esperança, s/n, Campus Samambaia, 74690-900, Goiânia, Goiás, Brasil. E-mail: [email protected] ABSTRACT. This paper discusses the education of physicians in the Schools of Medicine of the urban Studia Generalia in the 13th century. The Education methodology was the same for all four fields of knowledge: Arts, Theology, Roman and Canon Law and Medicine. It included reading by the scholars and scholastic commentaries and questions elaborated by the masters, The manuscript sources and print editions of the writings of the Portuguese physician Petrus Hispanus (?1220-1277), when he taught at Siena (1246-1252) are in the National Libraries of France and Spain and the Vatican Apostolic Library. Keywords: Studia Generalia; Articella, Medicine, physician; Paris; Siena. Manuscritos escolásticos do físico Pedro Hispano (século XIII) RESUMO. O presente texto busca problematizar a educação e a formação dos físicos nas faculdades de Medicina dos Estudos Gerais urbanos, no século XIII. A metodologia de ensino era comum à todas as quatro áreas do conhecimento universitário, Artes, Teologia, Direito Canônico e Romano e Medicina. Consistia em leitura pelos escolares e comentários e questões pelos mestres acerca dos textos das autoridades antigas e medievais. Em três bibliotecas nacionais europeias encontram-se as fontes manuscritas e edições impressas dos comentários e questões escritos pelo físico português Pedro Hispano (?1220-1277), quando atuou como mestre na Faculdade de Medicina de Siena entre 1246-1252.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Renaissance and Modern Logic from 1400 to 1850
    History of Renaissance and Modern Logic from 1400 to 1850 https://www.historyoflogic.com/logic-modern.htm History of Logic from Aristotle to Gödel by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] History of Renaissance and Modern Logic from 1400 to 1850 INTRODUCTION: LOGIC IN CONTINENTAL EUROPE "At the end of the fourteenth century there were roughly three categories of work available to those studying logic. The first category is that of commentaries on Aristotle's 'Organon'. The most comprehensive of these focussed either on the books of the Logica Vetus, which included Porphyry's Isagoge along with the Categories and De Interpretatione; or on the books of the Logica Nova, the remaining works of the 'Organon' which had become known to the West only during the twelfth century. In addition there were, of course, numerous commentaries on individual books of the 'Organon'. The second category is that of works on non-Aristotelian topics. These include the so-called Parva logicalia, or treatises on supposition, relative terms, ampliation, appellation, restriction and distribution. To these could be added tracts on exponibles and on syncategorematic terms. Peter of Spain is now the best-known author of parva logicalia, but such authors as Thomas Maulvelt and Marsilius of Inghen were almost as influential in the late fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. Another group of works belonging to the second category consists of the so-called 'tracts of the moderns', namely treatises on consequences, obligations and insolubles. A third group includes treatises on sophisms, on the composite and divided senses, and on proofs of terms, especially the well-known Speculum puerorum by Richard Billingham.
    [Show full text]
  • The Condemnations of 1270 and 1277
    BISHOPS, THEOLOGIANS, AND PHILOSOPHERS IN CONFLICT AT THE UNIVERSITIES OF PARIS AND OXFORD: THE CONDEMNATIONS OF 1270 AND 1277 In one of his letters from prison Dietrich Bonhoeffer wrote: The movement beginning about the thirteenth century (I am not going to get involved in any arguments about the exact date) towards the autonomy of man (un- der which I place the discovery of the laws by which the world lives and manages in science, social and political affairs, art, ethics and religion) has in our time reached a certain completion. Man has learned to cope with all questions of importance without recourse to God as a working hypothesis. In questions concerning science, art, and even ethics, this has become an understood thing which one scarcely dares to tilt at any more. But for the last hundred years or so it has been increasingly true of religious questions also: it is becoming evident that everything gets along without "God," and just as well as before.' Bonhoeffer's perceptive remark shows how important it is to examine our me- dieval past as well as other pasts if we are to understand our present. His allusion to the medieval movement towards human autonomy directs our attention to a number of conflicts between churchmen and theologians from the eleventh cen- tury on. We shall examine the most dramatic of these—the condemnations in 1270 and 1277 at the University of Paris by Etienne Tempier, bishop of Paris, and an almost simultaneous condemnation in 1277 at Oxford University by the Arch- bishop of Canterbury, Robert Kilwardby.
    [Show full text]
  • Amer Dardağan Neoplatonic
    Amer Dardağan STANAK, Society for Research of Bosnian Medieval History adardagan @aubih.edu.ba Neoplatonic "Tree of Life" (Arbor Porphyriana: A diagram of logic and mystical theology) Abstract In several versions of „Introduction to Aristotle's Categories“ („The Isagoge“) we find very intriguing diagram of the "Tree of Porphyry". This diagram is closely linked with the square of opposition (logical square), natural tree with vegetative ornaments and the anthropomorphic figure. Porphyry took over Aristotle's division into five predicables (quinque praedicabilia) and defined them through five classes (species, genus, differentia, propria, accidentia) and from them he created scala praedicamentalis (Arbor Porphyriana). The Neoplatonic- Aristotelianism of Porphyry influenced the return of interest in Aristotle's logic in the Middle Ages through translations of Boethius and Al-Farabi. Their works of logic were the basis for the study of many topics, especially those related to theology. Later diagrams with the natural tree and human figure (syndesmos) are found in the 13th century in "Tractatus" („Summulae Logicales“) written by Peter of Spain under different names such as: Tree of Love, Tree of Life, Tree of Science, Tree of Knowledge etc. Christian mysticism (Mystical theology), Islamic mysticism (Sufism) and Jewish mysticism (Kabbalah) was deeply influenced by Neoplatonic philosophy and within these mystical traditions we find different variations of the diagram aswell. Under the influence of the concept of Neoplatonic procession and reversion, mystic should be simultaneously involved in both Cataphatic and Apophatic theology to truly understand God. In other words, a spiritual person has to oscillate between affirming claims about the Tree of Life (the Being) and negation of those same claims to be able to have real knowledge of God.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    CURRICULUM VITAE 1. Name: Gyula Klima 2. Contact: Department of Philosophy, Fordham University, 441 E. Fordham road New York, NY 10458 Phone: (718) 817-3286 Fax: (914) 355-4026 E-mail: [email protected] Web: http://faculty.fordham.edu/klima 3. Education: MA 1982, Ph.D. 1986, Eötvös Lóránd University, Budapest 4. Positions held: 1982, Research Assistant, Inst. of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy 1986, Research Fellow, Institute of Philosophy, Hungarian Academy 1989-1990, 1991, Visiting Fellow, Academy of Finland 1990, Gifford Visiting Fellow, University of St. Andrews, Scotland 1991, Visiting Fellow, University of Copenhagen, Denmark 1991-92, Visiting Lecturer, Yale University 1992-95, Assistant Professor, Yale University 1993-97 Senior Research Fellow, Inst. of Philosophy, Hung. Acad. 1994-95, Morse Fellow, Yale University 1995-99 Assoc. Professor, Philosophy, University of Notre Dame 1999-2003 Associate Professor, Philosophy, Fordham University 2002-2003 ACLS Fellow/UCLA Visiting Scholar 2003 - Professor, Philosophy, Fordham University 2009 - Doctor of the Hungarian Academy 5. Major grants: 1994-95 Morse Fellowship, Yale University, $40,000 1995-97 NEH grant for “Buridan’s Summulae”, YUP, $50,000 2002-2003 ACLS, “John Buridan”, OUP, $40,000 2005: Earhart Foundation, “Medieval Philosophy”, $21,000 2009-2012 NEH, “Buridan’s Questions on the Soul”, $195,000 2012-2013 NEH “Questions on the Soul by John Buridan and Others”, $55,000 6. Professional American Catholic Philosophical Association (exec. comm. 2006) memberships: American Philosophical
    [Show full text]
  • HINDSIGHT Journal of Optometry History
    HINDSIGHT Journal of Optometry History October, 2007 Volume 38, Number 4 Official Publication of the Optometric Historical Society Hindsight: Journal of Optometry History publishes material on the history of optometry and related topics. As the official publication of the Optometric Historical Society, Hindsight: Journal of Optometry History supports the purposes and functions of the Optometric Historical Society. The purposes of the Optometric Historical Society, according to its by-laws, are: • to encourage the collection and preservation of materials relating to the history of optometry, • to assist in securing and documenting the recollections of those who participated in the development of optometry, • to encourage and assist in the care of archives of optometric interest, • to identify and mark sites, landmarks, monuments, and structures of significance in optometric development, and • to shed honor and recognition on persons, groups, and agencies making notable contributions toward the goals of the society. Officers and Board of Trustees of the Optometric Historical Society for 2007: President: Melvin Wolfberg, 3095 Buckinghammock Trl., Vero Beach FL 32960-4968, [email protected] Vice-President: Jerome J. Abrams Secretary-Treasurer: Bridget Kowalczyk, International Library, Archives, and Museum of Optometry, 243 North Lindbergh Boulevard, St. Louis, MO 63141; [email protected] Trustees: Walter W. Chase Jay M. Enoch Chuck Haine Douglas K. Penisten The official publication of the Optometric Historical Society was previously titled: Newsletter of the Optometric Historical Society, 1970-1991 (volumes 1-22), and Hindsight: Newsletter of the Optometric Historical Society, 1992-2006 (volumes 23-37). Hindsight: Journal of Optometry History began in 2007 with volume 38, number 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fate of the Flying Man Medieval Reception of Avicenna’S Thought Experiment
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 9/5/2015, SPi The Fate of the Flying Man Medieval Reception of Avicenna’s Thought Experiment Juhana Toivanen 1. INTRODUCTION Thought experiments are nowadays an important part of philosophical discourse. They are used to illuminate theoretical arguments and to reveal philosophically significant features of an argument or a problem in a way that aspires to precision. Although the phrase ‘thought experiment’ itself is quite recent, the use of imagined counterfactual cases which are designed to have a role in philosophical argument can be traced back to Antiquity, and the technique was widely employed in the Middle Ages.1 One of the most well-known medieval thought experiments is the so-called ‘flying man’ of Avicenna. The flying man is an imaginary person whose senses do not provide any input but who nevertheless admits his own existence, or the existence of his soul. Avicenna’s idea was that this thought experiment helps us to understand that the soul is not identical to the body but an immaterial entity. Modern scholarship has discussed the Latin reception of this thought experiment to some extent,2 but there are a couple of issues that have not 1 For the role of thought experiments in the history of Western philosophy, see Katerina Ierodiakonou and Sophie Roux (eds), Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts, History of Science and Medicine Library 19 (Leiden: Brill, 2011), 1–142. 2 Dag Nikolaus Hasse, Avicenna’s De anima in the Latin West: The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul, 1160–1300 (London: The Warburg Institute, 2000), 80–92 and 236; Deborah J.
    [Show full text]
  • José Meirinhos* a Project on Petrus Hispanus
    José Meirinhos* A Project on Petrus Hispanus: Edition and Study of the Attributed Works The name of Petrus Hispanus is surely the most important one in connection with medieval Portuguese culture. According to the tradition he was active in the mid-13th century, with an extensive corpus of attributed works, including ones on Logic, Natural Philosophy, Psychology, Zoology, Medicine, Alchemy, and Mysticism, as well as Sermons. During the Middle Ages and the early modern period, some of these works had an extraordinary influence and wide diffusion. Among other works attributed to Petrus Hispanus are: the first Latin Commentary on Aristotle’s De anima; the most extensive and detailed treatise on the soul written in Latin; one of the earliest commentaries, if not the very first, on the core zoological works of Aristotle, the De animalibus; the most popular Logic textbook ever written, with hundreds of manuscripts and editions, used in almost all continental universities from the 14th to the 16th centuries; the most popular medical prescriptions book, still in use by the end of the 17th century; one of the most extensive commentaries on the Articella, a changing set of Greek and Arabic works that were of key importance in medical university education from the 13th century onwards. According to the historiographical tradition, the philosopher and scientist credited with such a vast and influential work, after a political and ecclesiastical career in Portugal and at the papal curia, ended his days in the * Faculdade de Letras da Universidade do Porto, Via Panorâmica s/n; 4150-564 Porto. This paper is part of the project described in note 7, funded by FCT (2016-2019).
    [Show full text]
  • Translating Disease: the Vernacular Medical Treatise in the Late Medieval Kingdom of Aragon
    Translating Disease: The Vernacular Medical Treatise in the Late Medieval Kingdom of Aragon Michae/ Solomon Emory Univ., At/anta During the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries the Kingdom of Aragon experienced a remarkable upsurge in the amount of practical medical advice available to readers in the vernacular. Translations of health compendiums, herbals, treatises on the plague, and gynecological manual s provided for nonprofessionals the basic principies of health preservation. In 1305 Arnau de Vilanova wrote an abbreviated version of his Liber de regimine sanitatis (1299) for the king of Aragon, Jaume 11, which was subsequently translated into Catalan at the request of the king's wife, Blanca who could not read Latin. In 1339 with the plague virtually knocking on the door of Catalunya, Jacme d'Agramont wrote his Regiment de preservacio de pestilencia, recognized as one of the first treatises in the vernacular to inform citizens of the threat of pestilence and epidemic. Later during the early 15th century an anonymous Catalan or Valencian writer translated and emended a 13th century Latin treatise on sexual hygiene, Liber minor de coitu, which he named, perhaps scandalously from modern standards, the Specu/um a/ foderi. In that same century an unidentified physician named Mestre Joan translated one of 91 the Trotula taxts on female hygiene, gynecology, and cosrnetics.' We have today fifteenth-century translations of Galen's treatise on urina, De coneixensa de les orines and his work on foods Trectet de les viandes. We have translations of Arabic medical works such as the Llibre d'Almassor and several Catalan translations of Peter of Spain's enormously popular Tesar de pobre, a work orginally written to guide the sick who could not afford professional medical attention.
    [Show full text]
  • Signification and Modes of Signifying in Thirteenth-Century Logic: a Preface to Aquinas on Analogy
    Signification and Modes of Signifying in Thirteenth-Century Logic: A Preface to Aquinas on Analogy E. J. ASH WORTH In 1935 M. D. Chenu wrote, "Preoccupied as we are with such leading figures as Thomas Aquinas and Bonaventure, we all too easily lose sight of the massive dialectical learning which provided the foundation for both the teaching and the general thought-patterns of thirteenth-century masters."1 Unfortunately, Chenu's words have not been well heeded, and one of the outstanding features of the extensive literature on Aquinas's doctrine of analogy is the complete absence of any attempt to set him in the context of contemporary logic.2 Some attempt has been made to read him in terms of specula- 1. M. D. Chenu, "Grammaire et theologie aux Xlle et XIHe siecles," AHDLMA 10 (1935-1936): 7: "Tout occupes que nous sommes par les grandes figures d'un Thomas d'Aquin et d'un Bonaventure, nous perdons de vue trop facilement la massive culture dialectique qui constitue la base de l'enseignement et la mentalite generate des maΐtres du XΠIe siecle." Chenu's paper is still well worth reading. 2. An exception to this remark is provided by a paper which has just appeared: Alain de Libera, "Les sources greco-arabes de la theorie medievale de Γanalogie de 39 4O E- J. ASHWORTH tive grammar,3 but this is unhelpful so far as equivocation and analogy are concerned, since speculative grammarians did not usually take up these topics,4 So far as logicians are concerned, the most frequently cited figure is Cajetan, who was writing over two centuries later, and who discussed these matters from a perspective that is far removed from that of the thirteenth century, particularly with respect to gen- eral theories of signification.
    [Show full text]