The Linguistic Review 2015; Aop

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Linguistic Review 2015; Aop The Linguistic Review 2015; aop Željko Bošković* Introduction DOI 10.1515/tlr-2015-0012 The operation Merge, which combines two elements X and Y into {X,Y}, is minimally required for language. A long-standing assumption of the generative grammar has been that the nature of the resulting object needs to be specified. To take a concrete example, when a verbal and a nominal element are merged, as in the ergative structure in (1), information needs to be provided regarding whether the resulting object is verbal or nominal in nature. In the case of (1), the resulting object is verbal in nature. In slightly more technical terms, arrive projects in (1), labeling the resulting object. (1) {arrive, John} Syntactic representations are then taken to be hierarchical structures involving labeled objects. In the Government and Binding framework (GB), labels were essentially provided by the X-bar theory, i.e. they were part of structure building. The early minimalism has kept the gist of this approach. The Inclusiveness Condition, which states that the computational system can only manipulate the lexical items entering the computation–it cannot introduce anything new – is a fundamental principle of Minimalism. The Inclusiveness Condition is essentially a ban on creationism in the syntax. Under the Inclusiveness Condition, syntactic representations are bare in that they cannot include bar level distinctions, which are not present in the lexicon. Still, the early minimalism kept the gist of the GB approach to labeling, adapting it to the Bare Phrase Structure system. Thus, for Chomsky (1995), labeling is part of the definition of Merge: when X and Y are merged, either X or Y projects, i.e. labels the resulting object.1 This can be represented as in (2), where X is the label of the syntactic object formed by merging XandY.2 1 See, however, Citko (2008) on the possibility of both X and Y projecting. 2 Interestingly, Chomsky (1995: 396) suggests that it is the interfaces that require the informa- tion provided by labeling, anticipating in this respect Chomsky’s (2013, 2015) conclusions discussed below. *Corresponding author: Željko Bošković, Department of Linguistics, University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT 06269, USA, E-mail: [email protected] Authenticated | [email protected] author's copy Download Date | 12/25/15 5:39 AM 2 Željko Bošković (2) Merge(X,Y) = {X, {X,Y}} One question that immediately arose is how to determine whether X or Y projects. For movement (i.e. external Merge), it was assumed that the target projects (see for example Chomsky 1995: 256); for non-movement cases (i.e. internal Merge), the issue was left open in Chomsky (1995), the implicit assump- tion being that in principle, either X or Y can project, though in many cases something would go wrong if one of the two projects. This would for example be the case if in the transitive structure in (3), John projects after merging with kiss, as in (3a), instead of kiss, as in (3b). (3) a. {Peter, {John, {kiss, John}}} b. {Peter, {kiss, {kiss, John}}} The assumption that with movement, the target projects has been questioned. Thus, Donati (2006) argues that in free relatives like (4), the moved wh-element projects after it moves, merging with the clause, this being the reason why free relatives are nominal in nature with respect to a number of properties (see also Cecchetto and Donati 2015; Citko 2008). (4) John ate what I cooked. A more fundamental proposal was made in Collins (2002), who argues that labels themselves can be, hence should be, eliminated (for a more recent discussion, see Collins 2014). Collins (2002) thus argues for a label-free theory, simplifying (2) as in (5), where structure building through Merge takes place without recourse to labels. (5) Merge(X,Y) = {X,Y} Collins discusses how various mechanisms that were previously assumed to involve recourse to labels, like various generalizations of the traditional X-bar theory and the Minimal Link Condition, can be implemented in a label-free theory.3 (For much relevant discussion, the reader is also referred to Seely 2006, who observes that the postulation of labels as part of the syntactic object 3 Collins also examines how selection (i.e. subcategorization) would work in a label-free theory, though, as discussed in Seely (2006), this mechanism does raise non-trivial issues in this respect. Authenticated | [email protected] author's copy Download Date | 12/25/15 5:39 AM Introduction 3 formed by Merge raises several questions which trivially dissolve in a label-free theory; Seely also observes that the elimination of labels requires a derivational approach to c-command (see Epstein 1999), the label-free theory being incom- patible with the standard representational approach to c-command). Chomsky (2013), which is the starting point for the articles in this volume, also assumes that labels are not encoded in the output of Merge, i.e. that labeling is not part of the definition of Merge, thus adopting (5) rather than (2), Merge being a set-formation operation that combines two syntactic objects (SOs) without label projection. However, Chomsky keeps the traditional assump- tion that when X and Y are merged, the nature of the resulting object needs to be specified. Taking a concrete case again, it needs to be specified that the object resulting from the merge operation in (1) is verbal in nature. Crucially, Chomsky argues that syntax itself does not require this information; the information is required by the interfaces so that syntactic objects can be intepreted. In other words, Chomsky assumes that although there is nothing wrong with unlabeled objects in the syntax, such objects are uninterpretable. Chomsky then provides an algorithm that specifies labels (more informally, the nature of an object formed by Merge), which applies at the point of transfer to the interfaces, given that labeling is interface-driven. Under this view, labeling does not apply as part of Merge, as in Chomsky (1995). In this respect, Chomsky (2013) follows Collins (2002) and Seely (2006). However, syntax is still not fully label- free, as in Collins (2002), and Seely (2006), labeling taking place at the phasal level, when the syntactic structure is sent to the interfaces. It should, however, be noted that it is not obvious that labels are indeed needed for interpretation. In fact, formal semantics models typically do not make recourse to labels. Even if labels are needed for intepretation, a question arises if they are needed in all cases, which opens up a potentially interesting avenue for further research. In this respect, Chametzky (2000), Hornstein and Nunes (2008), Hunter (2010), and Bošković (in press) argue that adjunction does not require labeling for interpretation, which under Chomsky (2013) would entail that the result of adjunction is not labeled at all. In fact, Bošković (in press) suggests that not labeling should be taken as the defining property of what is referred to as adjunction, segmentation being dispensable (for a different label- ing-based perspective on adjunction, see Yoo 2015). The claim that labels are needed for interpretation should then be taken as programmatic, to be subjected to careful investigation. This, however, should not be considered a weakness of the overall system. On the contrary, that the system opens up new areas of research only contri- butes to its inherent interest. Previous approaches to labeling essentially stipu- lated that labeling was necessary to permit further applications of Merge, with Authenticated | [email protected] author's copy Download Date | 12/25/15 5:39 AM 4 Željko Bošković Merge applying only to labeled structures. If labeling is not part of Merge, a number of interesting questions arise. There are essentially three positions here: (i) labeling as part of Merge, as in Chomsky (1995), where labeling is always triggered immediately by the Merge operation itself; (ii) label-free system, as in Collins (2002), and Seely (2006), where labels are eliminated; and (iii), what I will call “label-or-not” system, where labeling is not triggered by Merge itself but labels are not (completely) eliminated. From a strictly research perspective, (iii) is the most interesting situation, due to a host of intriguing questions that it raises. As noted above, Chomsky (2013) suggests that labels are needed for interpretation. Questions arise here whether this is indeed the case and whether this holds uniformly for all cases (cf. the above suggestion about adjunction). Chomsky’s interpretation-driven approach to labeling leads to labeling taking place at the phasal level. Phases are taken to determine the points of spell-out, i.e. when the structure is sent to the interfaces. If labeling occurs strictly for interpretative reasons, we would expect it to occur at this point. As noted in Bošković (this volume), a serious chicken-or-the-egg style question then arises: Bošković (2015) argues that phase- hood determination requires labeling, i.e. phases do not really exist prior to labeling: to know whether something is a phase we need to know its label (see Bošković 2015 for evidence that unlabeled elements cannot be phases; it is shown in that work that the well-known ban on movement out of moved elements can be deduced given that unlabeled objects cannot be phases). Since phases determine the points of spell-out, without any labeling structure cannot be sent to the interfaces, which in turn is necessary for labeling under a purely interpretative approach to labeling. Bošković (this volume) observes that this problem dissolves if head-complement merger is labeled immediately since this is actually all that is needed to determine the points of spell-out. However, there would then need to be a syntactic reason for labeling in this particular case, assuming position (iii) from above, rather than position (i), where labeling is automatic.
Recommended publications
  • Modeling Language Variation and Universals: a Survey on Typological Linguistics for Natural Language Processing
    Modeling Language Variation and Universals: A Survey on Typological Linguistics for Natural Language Processing Edoardo Ponti, Helen O ’Horan, Yevgeni Berzak, Ivan Vulic, Roi Reichart, Thierry Poibeau, Ekaterina Shutova, Anna Korhonen To cite this version: Edoardo Ponti, Helen O ’Horan, Yevgeni Berzak, Ivan Vulic, Roi Reichart, et al.. Modeling Language Variation and Universals: A Survey on Typological Linguistics for Natural Language Processing. 2018. hal-01856176 HAL Id: hal-01856176 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01856176 Preprint submitted on 9 Aug 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Modeling Language Variation and Universals: A Survey on Typological Linguistics for Natural Language Processing Edoardo Maria Ponti∗ Helen O’Horan∗∗ LTL, University of Cambridge LTL, University of Cambridge Yevgeni Berzaky Ivan Vuli´cz Department of Brain and Cognitive LTL, University of Cambridge Sciences, MIT Roi Reichart§ Thierry Poibeau# Faculty of Industrial Engineering and LATTICE Lab, CNRS and ENS/PSL and Management, Technion - IIT Univ. Sorbonne nouvelle/USPC Ekaterina Shutova** Anna Korhonenyy ILLC, University of Amsterdam LTL, University of Cambridge Understanding cross-lingual variation is essential for the development of effective multilingual natural language processing (NLP) applications.
    [Show full text]
  • Universals in Phonology This Article A
    UC Berkeley Phonology Lab Annual Report (2007) (Commissioned for special issue of The Linguistic Review, 2008, Harry van der Hulst, ed.) Universals in Phonology ABSTRACT This article asks what is universal about phonological systems. Beginning with universals of segment inventories, a distinction is drawn between descriptive universals (where the effect of different theoretical frameworks is minimized) vs. analytic universals (which are specific-theory- dependent). Since there are few absolute universals such as “all languages have stops” and “all languages have at least two degrees of vowel height”, theory-driven or “architectural” universals concerning distinctive features and syllable structure are also considered. Although several near- universals are also mentioned, the existence of conflicting “universal tendencies” and contradictory resolutions naturally leads into questions concerning the status of markedness and synchronic explanation in phonology. While diachrony is best at accounting for typologically unusual and language-specific phonological properties, the absolute universals discussed in this study are clearly grounded in synchrony. 1. Introduction My colleague John Ohala likes to tell the following mythical story about a lecture that the legendary Roman Jakobson gives upon arrival at Harvard University some time in the 1940s. The topic is child language and phonological universals, a subject which Prof. Jakobson addresses in his Kindersprache, Aphasie und allgemeine Lautgesetze (1941). In his also legendary strong Russian accent, Jakobson makes the pronouncement, “In all languages, first utterance of child, [pa]!” 1 He goes on to explain that it is a matter of maximal opposition: “[p] is the consonant most consonant, and [a] is the vowel most vowel.” As the joke continues, a very concerned person in the audience raises his hand and is called on: “But, professor, my child’s first utterance was [tSik].” Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • The Linguistic Review 2019; 36(1): 117–150
    The Linguistic Review 2019; 36(1): 117–150 Sun-Ah Jun* and Xiannu Jiang Differences in prosodic phrasing in marking syntax vs. focus: Data from Yanbian Korean https://doi.org/10.1515/tlr-2018-2009 Abstract: In studying the effect of syntax and focus on prosodic phrasing, the main issue of investigation has been to explain and predict the location of a prosodic boundary, and not much attention has been given to the nature of prosodic phrasing. In this paper, we offer evidence from intonation patterns of utterances that prosodic phrasing can be formed differently phonologically and phonetically due to its function of marking syntactic structure vs. focus (promi- nence) in Yanbian Korean, a lexical pitch accent dialect of Korean spoken in the northeastern part of China, just above North Korea. We show that the location of a H tone in syntax-marking Accentual Phrase (AP) is determined by the type of syntactic head, noun or verb (a VP is marked by an AP-initial H while an NP is marked by an AP-final H), while prominence-marking accentual phrasing is cued by AP-initial H. The difference in prosodic phrasing due to its dual function in Yanbian Korean is compared with that of Seoul Korean, and a prediction is made on the possibility of finding such difference in other languages based on the prosodic typology proposed in (Jun, Sun-Ah. 2014b. Prosodic typology: by prominence type, word prosody, and macro-rhythm. In Sun-Ah Jun (ed.), Prosodic Typology II: The Phonology of Intonation and Phrasing. 520–539. Oxford: Oxford University Press).
    [Show full text]
  • Margaret Thomas Department of Slavic & Eastern Languages
    CURRICULUM VITAE Margaret Thomas Department of Slavic & Eastern Languages & Literatures Boston College 24 Hemlock Road Chestnut Hill, MA 02467 Newton, MA 02464 (617) 552-3697 (617) 244-3105 [email protected] Education Ph.D. 1991 Harvard University Linguistics A.M. 1985 Harvard University Linguistics M.Ed. 1983 Boston University Teaching English to Speakers of Other Languages B.A. 1974 Yale University Japanese Language and Literature Employment 2006– Professor, Slavic and Eastern Languages and Literatures, Boston College 1996–06 Associate Professor, Slavic and Eastern Languages Department, Boston College 1992–96 Assistant Professor, Slavic and Eastern Languages Department, Boston College 1991–92 Visiting Assistant Professor, Slavic and Eastern Languages, Boston College 1986–90 Teaching Fellow, Linguistics Department, Harvard University Publications 2013 ‘Air writing’ and second language learners’ knowledge of Japanese kanji. Japanese Language and Literature, 47: 59–92. Otto Jespersen and ‘The Woman’, then and now. Historiographia Linguistica, 40: 377–208. The doctorate in second language acquisition: An institutional history. Linguistic Approaches to Bilingualism, 3: 509–531. History of the study of second language acquisition. In Martha Young-Scholten and Julia Herschensohn (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Second Language Acquisition, 26–45. Cambridge University Press.. 2011 Fifty Key Thinkers on Language and Linguistics, pp. xvii + 306. Routledge Press. Gender and the language scholarship of the Summer Institute of Linguistics in the context of mid twentieth-century American linguistics. In Gerda Hassler (Ed.), History of Linguistics 2008: Selected Papers from the XI International Conference on the History of the Language Margaret Thomas 2 Sciences (ICHOLS XI), Potsdam, 28 August–2 September 2008, 389–397.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 11: Introduction to Pragmatics. Formal Semantics and Formal Pragmatics
    Formal Semantics and Semantic Universals, Lecture 11 Barbara H. Partee, RGGU, April 28, 2011 Lecture 11: Introduction to Pragmatics. Formal Semantics and Formal Pragmatics. Possible Pragmatic Universals 0. Syntax, Semantics, Pragmatics. ....................................................................................................................................1 1. Grice’s Conversational Implicatures. ...........................................................................................................................2 1.1. Motivation. Questions about the meanings of logical words.................................................................................2 1.2. Truth-conditional content (semantics) vs. Conversational Implicatures (pragmatics)..........................................2 1.3. Conversational maxims. (“Gricean maxims”.)......................................................................................................3 1.4. Generating implicatures. General principles. Examples......................................................................................4 1.5. Are Gricean implicatures universal?......................................................................................................................5 2. How a better understanding of conversational implicatures helps semantics. .............................................................5 3. At the borderline of semantics and pragmatics: presuppositions. ................................................................................6 3.1
    [Show full text]
  • RUTH KRAMER Department of Linguistics Office
    RUTH KRAMER Department of Linguistics Office: Poulton 247 Georgetown University [email protected] Washington, DC 20057 Phone: 202-687-5753 EMPLOYMENT 2009- Assistant Professor, Department of Linguistics, Georgetown University 2012- Associate Director for Afroasiatic Languages, The Afranaph Project (PI: Ken Safir), Rutgers University. 2011- Adjunct Researcher, Center for the Advanced Study of Language, University of Maryland, College Park. EDUCATION 2003-2009 University of California, Santa Cruz Ph.D. in Linguistics, 2009 Dissertation: Definite Markers, Phi Features and Agreement: A Morphosyntactic Investigation of the Amharic DP Committee: Sandra Chung, Jorge Hankamer (co-chairs), James McCloskey 2007 Summer Cooperative African Language Institute (University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign). Intensive course in Elementary Amharic. 1999-2003 Brown University, B.A. in Linguistics (Honors) and Egyptology Magna cum laude, Phi Beta Kappa Thesis: (Virtual) Relative Clauses in Middle Egyptian Advisors: Pauline Jacobson and Leo Depuydt PUBLICATIONS MONOGRAPH AND EDITED VOLUMES Zsiga, Elizabeth, One Boyer and Ruth Kramer, eds. In press. Languages in Africa: Multilingualism, Language Policy, and Education. Georgetown University Press. Kramer, Ruth. Under contract. The Morphosyntax of Gender: Evidence from Amharic. Oxford University Press. Kramer, Ruth, Elizabeth Zsiga and One Boyer, eds. Under contract. Selected Proceedings of the 44th Annual Conference of African Linguistics. Cascadilla Press. Page 1 of 8 RUTH KRAMER : C.V. REFEREED ARTICLES, BOOK CHAPTERS AND PROCEEDINGS PAPERS Kramer, Ruth. In press. The position of numerals in Middle Egyptian: Evidence from universals of word order. Lingua Aegyptia. Chacón, Dustin, Jen Johnson, Ruth Kramer, Chris LaTerza, Morgan Rood. To appear. New puzzles for shifting indexicals: an Amharic case study. In Selected Proceedings of the 44th Annual Conference on African Linguistics (ACAL 44), eds.
    [Show full text]
  • The SPE-Heritage of Optimality Theory
    The SPE-heritage of Optimality Theory HARRY VAN DER HÜLST AND NANCY A. RITTER Abstract In this article, we start out discussing the issue of how many phonological levels one might like to distinguish. In addition, we discuss how each level is charac- terized and how the mapping between levels is handled. Then, against the back- ground of a more general discussion of constraint-based approaches to phonol- ogy, we assess phonological Optimality Theory (OT), arguing that this theory is formulated within the conceptual framework of Standard Generative Phonology (SGP) and thus has not freed itself from its SPE-heritage. By implicitly adopting many aspects ofSPE (such as an intra-lavel input/output distinction and one holis- tic mechanism), OT compares unfavorably with other available constraint-based models in needing the notion of extrinsic ordering and failing to characterize the notion of what a possible language is. 1. Introduction The purpose of this article is to assess phonological Optimality Theory (OT) in the context of a broad discussion of both other constraint-based phonological theories as well as the preceding derivational theories that stem from the tradition of The Sound Pattern of English (SPE; Chomsky and Halle 1968). Our main conclusion will be that OT is closer in its basic design to SPE than to the other constraint-based models that are its contemporaries. In section 2 of this article, we first discuss different views of phonological lev- els of representation, converging on a view that acknowledges more than one level, while lacking the notion of an intra-level input/output distinction.
    [Show full text]
  • Pauline Jacobson-Cv, 7/21
    Pauline Jacobson CURRICULUM VITAE updated: July, 2021 Department of Cognitive. Linguistic, and Psychological Sciences Box 1821 Brown University, Providence, RI 02912 phone: (401)-863-3037; (401)-863-2727 fax: 401-863-2255 e-mail: [email protected] Primary Areas of Specialization: formal (compositional) semantics, syntactic theory, the interaction of syntax and semantics Secondary Areas: pragmatics; the interface of pragmatics and semantics; lexical semantics; language processing and linguistic theory Area of 'expertise' for the purposes of teaching (only!): Linguistic Relativity hypothesis Education A.B. (Anthropology), University of California at Berkeley, 1968. M.A. (Linguistics), University of California at Berkeley, 1972. Masters thesis: Crossover and Some Related Phenomena. Ph.D. (Linguistics), University of California at Berkeley, 1977. Dissertation: The Syntax of Crossing Coreference Sentences. Teaching and Research Positions Visiting teaching and research positions: Visiting Professor, Harvard, Semester I, 2004-5. Visiting Professor, UCLA, May, 2001. Visiting Professor, Institute for Maschinelle Sprachverarbeitung (Institute for Computational Linguistics), University of Stuttgart, Germany, May- June, 1998. Fellow, Institute for Advanced Study, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, August- December, 1997. Visiting Associate Professor, Ohio State University; January-June, 1990. Summer Institutes: (courses at Linguistic Society of America Institutes were by invitation of the host institution; courses at the European Summer School in Language, Logic and Information were by invitation of the organizing committee or refereed proposal submission; others by invitation of the organizing committee) Second Annual East Asian Summer School in Language, Logic, and Information, Southwest University, Chongqing, China, August, 2012. "The Syntax-Semantic Interface: Compositionality Issues". Pauline Jacobson - cv - 2021 2 European Summer School in Language, Logic, and Information, Copenhagen, August, 2010.
    [Show full text]
  • Ellipsis: Licensing, Structure and Identity
    The Linguistic Review 2016; 33(4): 445–452 Evelyn Gandón-Chapela* and Javier Pérez-Guerra Ellipsis: licensing, structure and identity DOI 10.1515/tlr-2016-0010 Abstract: Following an introduction to ellipsis and its consequences both for communication and for the theory of grammar, this paper addresses a number of issues which have been debated in the linguistic literature on ellipsis, namely structure, identity and licensing. This study brings to the readers’ attention the effects which such conditions have for the study of ellipsis in different lan- guages as well as their constraints within the generative framework. As case studies on the conditions and the characterisation of the linguistic strategy under scrutiny, this paper also summarises the main approaches to ellipsis in the studies embodied in this special issue. Keywords: ellipsis, antecedent, identity, licensing, mismatch 1 Introduction In a communication exchange speakers may omit information when the latter can be inferred from the linguistic or extralinguistic context. Therefore, addressees will need to decipher not only what has been said but also what has not in order to reach a full and correct interpretation. This syntactic strategy is known as ‘ellipsis’ in the linguistic literature and it refers to cases in which expected, that is, subcategorised (or syntactically relevant) syntactic elements, have been left unpronounced. Elliptical constructions thus illustrate a mismatch between meaning (the intended message) and sound (what is actually uttered). For example, in (1), although part of the sentence has undergone ellipsis, its meaning can still be understood and retrieved from the surrounding linguistic context: (1) Michael keeps on telling me I won’t pass the exam, but I believe I will pass the exam.1 1 Strikethrough words represent elided material in this paper, but they are not intended to represent a syntactic or semantic analysis of ellipsis.
    [Show full text]
  • 2020 Proceedings
    请领导们放心 2020 Proceedings Flying in English -ketun L2 intonation mweo haesseyo HOUSELESSHOMELESS natural language acquisition Subtitles 24th Annual Graduate Student Conference Edited by Victoria Lee College of Languages, Denis Melik Tangiyev Linguistics & Literature Chau Truong 2020 Proceedings Selected papers from the 24th Annual Graduate Student Conference College of Languages, Linguistics & Literature Edited by Victoria Lee Denis Melik Tangiyev Chau Truong Published by 1859 East-West Road #106 Honolulu, HI 96822-2322 nflrc.hawaii.edu cbna 2021 College of Languages, Linguistics & Literature, University of Hawai‘i at Mānoa. Some rights reserved. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons. org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/. Past proceedings in this series are archived in http://scholarspace.manoa.hawaii.edu/handle/10125/9195 The contents of this publication were developed in part under a grant from the U.S. Department of Education (CFDA 84.229, P229A180026). However, the contents do not necessarily represent the policy of the Department of Education, and one should not assume endorsement by the Federal Government. CONTENTS PREFACE ii PLENARY HIGHLIGHTS iii 2020 LLL EXCELLENCE IN RESEARCH AWARD PRESENTATIONS iv HOMELESS OR HOUSELESS: TERMINOLOGY CHANGES FOR HOME OWNER 2 AGENCY Jenniefer Corpuz, Department of English POSITING A HYBRID EXEMPLAR MODEL FOR L2 INTONATION 8 Bonnie J. Fox, Department of East Asian Languages
    [Show full text]
  • Empirical Assessment of Stimulus Poverty Arguments1
    Empirical assessment of stimulus poverty arguments1 GEOFFREY K. PULLUM AND BARBARA C. SCHOLZ Abstract This article examines a type of argument for linguistic nativism that takes the following form: (i) a fact about some natural language is exhibited that al- legedly could not be learned from experience without access to a certain kind of (positive) data; (ii) it is claimed that data of the type in question are not found in normal linguistic experience; hence (iii) it is concluded that people cannot be learning the language from mere exposure to language use. We ana- lyze the components of this sort of argument carefully, and examine four exem- plars, none of which hold up. We conclude that linguists have some additional work to do if they wish to sustain their claims about having provided support for linguistic nativism, and we offer some reasons for thinking that the relevant kind of future work on this issue is likely to further undermine the linguistic nativist position. 1. This work was partially supported by grants from the Humanities Division at the University of California, Santa Cruz. Some of the material was presented in an earlier form by Pul- lum in the Parasession on Learnability at the Berkeley Linguistics Society’s annual meeting in February 1996, and appeared as Pullum (1996). Early versions of some of the research were also presented to the Australasian Association for Philosophy (July 1996), a graduate seminar on learnability at UCSC (fall 1996), and the TABU Day conference at the Rijksuni- versiteit Groningen, Holland
    [Show full text]
  • Journal Name (As of 1/5/2021) 'Āfāq Al-Thaqāfah Wa Al-Turāth 0 13Th Moon
    Journal Name (as of 1/5/2021) ’Āfāq al-thaqāfah wa al-turāth 0 13th Moon 1611 1616 1650-1850 17th and 18th Century Theatre Research 1895 19 19th Century Music 2000 2004 20th Century Studies 21st Century Afro Review 27: Centro Cultural de la Generacion del 27 3224 e-CRIT 3L 452°F 49th Parallel 4th Floor/4 Kat 88 91.9 (a) AABS Newsletter AAHE Bulletin AALA Journal Aarboger For Nordisk Oldkyndighed og Historie AATI AATSEEL Newsletter A/B AB Bookman's Weekly ABA ABAC Journal L'Abaco Abafazi Abant İzzet Baysal Üniversitesi Sosyal Bilimler EnstitüsüDergisi / Abant İzzet Baysal University Graduate School of SocialSciences Journal of Social Sciences Abbia ABC Cultural ABC (Internat. Ed.) ABC Literario AbeÁfrica ABEI Journal Aberdeen University Review Abhandlungen der Sächsischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Leipzig. Philosophisch-Historischen Klasse Abhandlungen und Berichte des Staatlichen Museums fur Volkerkunde Dresden Abhath The Abiko Annual with James Joyce Finnegans Wake Studies Abiko Quarterly with James Joyce Studies Abiko's Literary Quarterly Rag ABM ABO About Campus The ABP Journal Abr-Nahrain Abraham Lincoln Quarterly Abraka Quarterly Abraxas Abril Abril Nepa UFF Abriu Abruzzo Abside Abstract of Bryn Mawr College Thesis Abstracts of Dissertations, Stanford University Abstracts of Dissertations, University of California Abstracts of Dissertations, University of Southern California Abstracts of Dissertations, University of Virginia Abstracts of Doctoral Dissertations, Ohio State University Abstracts of Doctoral Dissertations, Pennsylvania
    [Show full text]