Prospect Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Prospect Theory Prospect Theory Warwick Economics Summer School Prospect Theory Eugenio Proto University of Warwick, Department of Economics July 19, 2016 Prospect Theory, 1 of 44 Prospect Theory Outline 1 General Introduction 2 The Expected Utility Theory 3 Main Departures from Expected Utility 4 Prospect Theory 5 Empirical Evidence Finance Economic Development Housing Markets Labor Market Domestic Violence 6 Summary Prospect Theory, 2 of 44 Prospect Theory General Introduction Behavioral Economics Economics and Psychology were not separated Adam Smith: The theory of Moral Sentiments Jeremy Bentham, the psychological underpinnings of Utility Francis Edgeworth, concept of envy in Utility Functions Prospect Theory, 3 of 44 Prospect Theory General Introduction Behavioral Economics, cont'd Neoclassical Revolution separated clearly Psychology and Economics Economics like a natural (and not a social) science Psychology has too unsteady foundations Utility can be defined as an ordinal (and not a cardinal) object Rejection of the hedonistic assumptions of Benthamite Utility Neoclassical economists expunged the psychology from economics Prospect Theory, 4 of 44 Prospect Theory General Introduction Behavioral Economics, cont'd Some early Criticism to the neoclassical economy from Irwing Fisher, J.M. Keynes,, Herbert Simon More from Allais (1953), Ellsberg (1961), Markowitz (1952), Strotz (1955), following the Expected Utility Theory and the discounted utility models Kahneman and Tversky (1979) on expected utility, Thaler (1981) and Loewenstain and Prelec (1992) (on discounted utility), Happiness Economics on Hedonic foundations of Utility Neuroscience looks for the bases of Individual Behavior Neuroscience gives steadier foundations to psychology Toward a unique discipline? Prospect Theory, 5 of 44 Prospect Theory The Expected Utility Theory Outline 1 General Introduction 2 The Expected Utility Theory 3 Main Departures from Expected Utility 4 Prospect Theory 5 Empirical Evidence Finance Economic Development Housing Markets Labor Market Domestic Violence 6 Summary Prospect Theory, 6 of 44 Prospect Theory The Expected Utility Theory Expected Utility Individuals generally, ceteris paribus, prefer certainty to uncertainty a prospect is a vector of probabilities and Consequences (q = (x1; p1; :::; xn; pn)) they take decision over a prospect H; p; L; (1 − p), following a utility function Eu = pu(H) + (1 − p)u(L) (1) 1 is defined Expected Utility Individuals prefer r1 = (800; 1) to r2 = (1000; 0:85; 0; 0:15) note that E(r1) < E(r2). Prospect Theory, 7 of 44 Prospect Theory The Expected Utility Theory Main Tenets of EU 1 The overall Utility of a prospect is the expected Utility, Eu 2 The Utility is defined over final wealth rather than gain and losses 3 Risk aversion: u is concave (u00 < 0) 4 Preferences are independent on the manner the prospects are described Prospect Theory, 8 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Outline 1 General Introduction 2 The Expected Utility Theory 3 Main Departures from Expected Utility 4 Prospect Theory 5 Empirical Evidence Finance Economic Development Housing Markets Labor Market Domestic Violence 6 Summary Prospect Theory, 9 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Main Departures from EU 1 Non Linear Decision Weights 2 Individuals reason in terms of loss and gains rather than final outcome 3 Loss aversion 4 Framing Effects Prospect Theory, 10 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Non Linear Decision Weights Expected Utility requires a linear response to variation of probability Experimentally: raising the probability from 0.39 to 0.40 has much less impact than increasing the probability from 0.99 to 1, or 0 to 0.01 (certainty effect) Prospect Theory, 11 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Non Linear Decision Weights: Allais Paradox Problem 1: A = (2500; 0:33; 2400; 0:66; 0; 0:01) or B = (2400; 1) Problem 2: C = (2500; 0:33; 0; 0:67) or D = (2400; 0:34; 0; 0:66) choosing B and C is not consistent with EU theory, u(2400) > 0:33u(2500) + 0:66u(2400) or 0:34u(2400) > 0:33u(2500) The second inequality is inconsistent with C > D (assume u(0) = 0) Problem 2 is obtained from Problem 1, by eliminating .66 of winning 2400 Eliminating a large chance of winning alters the ordering Prospect Theory, 12 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Non Linear Decision Weights: Allais Paradox; cont'd Problem 3: A = (4000;:80) or B = (3000; 1) Problem 4: C = (4000; 0:20) or D = (3000; 0:25) choosing B and C is not consistent with EU theory, Problem 4 is obtained from Problem 3, by dividing all probabilities of a positive outcome by 4 Reducing the probability of winning from 1 to .25 has a greater effect than reducing it from .8 to .2 Certainty effect Prospect Theory, 13 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Non Linear Decision Weights Problem 7: A = (6000; 0:45) or B = (3000; 0:90) Problem 8: C = (6000; 0:001) or D = (3000; 0:002) choosing B and C is not consistent with EU theory, Problem 8 is obtained from Problem 7, by dividing all probabilities of a positive outcome by 45 Violation of the Independence axiom With high probability of winning individuals are risk averse with low individuals are more risk seekers Prospect Theory, 14 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Willingness to Pay vs Willingness to Accept (Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler 1990) Markets for: Tokens and Mugs Willingness to Pay is the maximum price an individuals want to pay a good Willingness to Accept is the minimum compensation demanded by the owner to sell a good Standard Assumptions imply that WTA ≈ WTP Prospect Theory, 15 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Willingness to Pay vs Willingness to Accept Market for Tokens and Mugs (6 USD) in an experiment involving the exchange of a mug (6 USD value), some individuals were endowed with a mug, some other with the money to buy this mug at a price 8.75 I will sell I will not sell at a price 8.25 I will sell I will not sell For the token: WTP = WTA for the mug the Median WTP = 2.75 and the Median WTA = 5.25 Similar Experiments were conducted with pens, folding binoculars, lottery tickets etc. Prospect Theory, 16 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Willingness to Pay vs Willingness to Accept Why WTA > WTP? Endowment Effect Mugs belong to sellers' endowment but not to the Buyers' endowment A manifestation of Loss aversion Prospect Theory, 17 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Framing Effects and status quo The EU theory implies that choices are invariant to the way options are described. An outbreak of a disease is expected to kill 600 people. Program A : 200 people will be saved (72%) Program B : 1/3 probability to save 600 people, 2/3 probability that no people will be saved (28%) Program A (reframed) : 400 people will die (22%) Program B (reframed) : 1/3 probability that nobody will die, 2/3 that no people will be saved (78%) In the first version the reference is:\everybody will die". In the second version is \nobody will die". Individuals prefer the status quo. Prospect Theory, 18 of 44 Prospect Theory Main Departures from Expected Utility Framing of Gains and Losses Decision frames: Individuals evaluates outcome separately rather than jointly Hedonic Frames: Individuals aggregate losses and segregate gains : who is happier someone who win 50 and 25 in two lotteries (64%) or someone that wins 75 in one lottery (36%)? Prospect Theory, 19 of 44 Prospect Theory Prospect Theory Outline 1 General Introduction 2 The Expected Utility Theory 3 Main Departures from Expected Utility 4 Prospect Theory 5 Empirical Evidence Finance Economic Development Housing Markets Labor Market Domestic Violence 6 Summary Prospect Theory, 20 of 44 Prospect Theory Prospect Theory Prospect Theory \Transforming" the EU theory to accommodate some of the above anomalies V = pu(x) + (1 − p)u(y) is the value function for the Expected Utility V = π(p)v(x) + (1 − π(p))v(y) where π(p) is a decision weight which reflect the overall impact of p on the value of the prospect v is a function different from utility u Prospect Theory, 21 of 44 Prospect Theory Prospect Theory Prospect Theory: the function v Individuals reason in terms of loss and gains, they are risk averse in gains and risk lovers in losses, A difference between a gain of 100 to 200 appears larger than a difference between 1100 and 1200 The difference between a loss of -100 and -200 appears larger than difference between -1100 and -1200 The effect of a change diminishes with the distance to the reference point: principle of diminishing sensitivity Hence v 00(x) < 0 for x > 0 and v 00(x) > 0 for x < 0 Prospect Theory, 22 of 44 Prospect Theory Prospect Theory Prospect Theory : the function v cont'd Prospect Theory, 23 of 44 Prospect Theory Prospect Theory Prospect Theory : the weighting function π(p) the principle principle of diminishing sensitivity applies to π(p) The natural reference for p are certainty p = 1 and impossibility p = 0 an increase of 0.1 in the probability of winning a prize has more impact when it changes to probability from 0.9 to 1 or from 0 to 0.1 than from 0.5 to 0.6 diminishing sensitivity gives rise to a weighting function π(p) concave near 0 and convex near 1 implies subadditivity for unlikely event and superadditivity near certainty Prospect Theory, 24 of 44 Prospect Theory : the weighting function π(p) Prospect Theory Empirical Evidence Outline 1 General Introduction 2 The Expected Utility Theory 3 Main Departures from Expected Utility 4 Prospect Theory 5 Empirical Evidence Finance Economic Development Housing Markets Labor Market Domestic Violence 6 Summary Prospect Theory, 26 of 44 Prospect Theory Empirical Evidence Finance The Equity Premium Puzzle (Benartzi and Thaler 1995) Stocks' returns are more volatile than bonds' returns The average return to stocks is 8% higher than the average return to bonds this would imply an unrealistically high degree of risk aversion, i.e.
Recommended publications
  • Behavioral Economics Comes of Age
    Behavioral Economics Comes of Age Wolfgang Pesendorfer† Princeton University May 2006 † I am grateful to Markus Brunnermeier, Drew Fudenberg, Faruk Gul and Wei Xiong for helpful comments. 1. Introduction The publication of “Advances in Behavioral Economics” is a testament to the success of behavioral economics. The book contains important second-generation contributions to behavioral economics that build on the seminal work by Kahnemann, Tversky, Thaler, Strotz and others. Behavioral economics is organized around experimental findings that suggest inade- quacies of standard economic theories. The most celebrated of those are (i) failures of expected utility theory; (ii) the endowment effect; (iii) hyperbolic discounting and (iv) social preferences. Most of the articles collected in Advances deal with one of these four topics. Expected Utility: Expected utility theory assumes the independence axiom. The (stochastic version of the) independence axiom says that the frequency with which a pool of subjects chooses lottery p over q doesnotchangewhenbothlotteriesaremixedwithsome common lottery r. Experiments by Allais, Kahnemann and Tversky and others demon- strate systematic failures of the independence axiom. Chapter 4 in the book discusses this experimental evidence and the theories that address it. Kahnemann and Tversky (1979) develop prospect theory to address the failures of expected utility theory. They argue that when analyzing choice under uncertainty it is not enough to know the lotteries an agent is choosing over. Rather, we must know more about thesubject’ssituationatthetimehemakeshischoice.Prospecttheorydistinguishes between gains and losses from a situation-specific reference point. The agent evaluates gains and losses differently and exhibits first-order risk aversion locally around the reference point. The Endowment Effect: In standard consumer theory, demand is a function of wealth and prices but does not depend on the composition of the endowment.
    [Show full text]
  • How Prospect Theory Can Improve Legal Counseling
    University of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review Volume 24 Issue 1 The Ben J. Altheimer Symposium: The Article 4 Impact of Science on Legal Decisions 2001 How Prospect Theory Can Improve Legal Counseling John M.A. DiPippa University of Arkansas at Little Rock William H. Bowen School of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/lawreview Part of the Law and Society Commons, Legal History Commons, and the Legal Profession Commons Recommended Citation John M.A. DiPippa, How Prospect Theory Can Improve Legal Counseling, 24 U. ARK. LITTLE ROCK L. REV. 81 (2001). Available at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/lawreview/vol24/iss1/4 This Essay is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review by an authorized editor of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HOW PROSPECT THEORY CAN IMPROVE LEGAL COUNSELING John MA. DiPippa" I. INTRODUCTION Rational choice is the law's predominate model.' The law believes that (1) clients are rational, and (2) they will act rationally by choosing the path that leads to maximum utility, and (3) lawyers act profession- ally when they base their professional behavior on these assumptions. Clients need the information that will allow them (or their lawyer) to calculate the costs and benefits of each decision. In essence, law transplants the assumptions of classical economics into the realm of lawyer-client decision making.' Recent research casts doubt on the rational choice model of decision making.
    [Show full text]
  • Bounded Rationality Till Grüne-Yanoff* Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm, Sweden
    Philosophy Compass 2/3 (2007): 534–563, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2007.00074.x Bounded Rationality Till Grüne-Yanoff* Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm, Sweden Abstract The notion of bounded rationality has recently gained considerable popularity in the behavioural and social sciences. This article surveys the different usages of the term, in particular the way ‘anomalous’ behavioural phenomena are elicited, how these phenomena are incorporated in model building, and what sort of new theories of behaviour have been developed to account for bounded rationality in choice and in deliberation. It also discusses the normative relevance of bounded rationality, in particular as a justifier of non-standard reasoning and deliberation heuristics. For each of these usages, the overview discusses the central methodological problems. Introduction The behavioural sciences, in particular economics, have for a long time relied on principles of rationality to model human behaviour. Rationality, however, is traditionally construed as a normative concept: it recommends certain actions, or even decrees how one ought to act. It may therefore not surprise that these principles of rationality are not universally obeyed in everyday choices. Observing such rationality-violating choices, increasing numbers of behavioural scientists have concluded that their models and theories stand to gain from tinkering with the underlying rationality principles themselves. This line of research is today commonly known under the name ‘bounded rationality’. In all likelihood, the term ‘bounded rationality’ first appeared in print in Models of Man (Simon 198). It had various terminological precursors, notably Edgeworth’s ‘limited intelligence’ (467) and ‘limited rationality’ (Almond; Simon, ‘Behavioral Model of Rational Choice’).1 Conceptually, Simon (‘Bounded Rationality in Social Science’) even traces the idea of bounded rationality back to Adam Smith.
    [Show full text]
  • Direct Tests of Cumulative Prospect Theory⇤
    Direct Tests of Cumulative Prospect Theory⇤ B. Douglas Bernheim † Charles Sprenger‡ Stanford University and NBER UC San Diego First Draft: December 1, 2014 This Version: November 8, 2016 Abstract Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT), the leading behavioral account of decision making under uncertainty, assumes that the probability weight applied to a given outcome depends on its ranking. This assumption is needed to avoid the violations of dominance implied by Prospect Theory (PT). We devise a simple test involving three-outcome lotteries, based on the implication that compensating adjustments to the payo↵s in two states should depend on their rankings compared with payo↵s in a third state. In an experiment, we are unable to find any support for the assumption of rank dependence. We separately elicit probability weighting functions for the same subjects through conventional techniques involving binary lotteries. These functions imply that changes in payo↵rank should change the compensating adjustments in our three-outcome lotteries by 20-40%, yet we can rule out any change larger than 7% at standard confidence levels. Additional tests nevertheless indicate that the dominance patterns predicted by PT do not arise. We reconcile these findings by positing a form of complexity aversion that generalizes the well-known certainty e↵ect. JEL classification: D81, D90 Keywords:ProspectTheory,CumulativeProspectTheory,RankDependence,CertaintyEquiv- alents. ⇤We are grateful to Ted O’Donoghue, Colin Camerer, Nick Barberis, Kota Saito, and seminar participants at Cornell, Caltech, and Gary’s Conference (UC Santa Barbara) for helpful and thoughtful discussions. Fulya Ersoy, Vincent Leah-Martin, Seung-Keun Martinez, and Alex Kellogg all provided valuable research assistance.
    [Show full text]
  • Behavioral Economics in Context Applications for Development, Inequality & Discrimination, Finance, and Environment
    Behavioral Economics In Context Applications for Development, Inequality & Discrimination, Finance, and Environment By Anastasia C. Wilson An ECI Teaching Module on Social and Environmental Issues in Economics Global Development Policy Center Boston University 53 Bay State Road Boston, MA 02155 bu.edu/gdp Economics in Context Initiative, Global Development Policy Center, Boston University, 2020. Permission is hereby granted for instructors to copy this module for instructional purposes. Suggested citation: Wilson, Anastasia C. (2020) “Behavioral Economics In Context: Applications for Development, Inequality & Discrimination, Finance, and Environment.” An ECI Teaching Module on Social and Economic Issues, Economics in Context Initiative, Global Development Policy Center, Boston University, 2020. Students may also download the module directly from: http://www.bu.edu/eci/education-materials/teaching-modules/ Comments and feedback from course use are welcomed: Economics in Context Initiative Global Development Policy Center Boston University 53 Bay State Road Boston, MA 02215 http://www.bu.edu/eci/ Email: [email protected] NOTE – terms denoted in bold face are defined in the KEY TERMS AND CONCEPTS section at the end of the module. BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS IN CONTEXT TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................................ 4 1.1 The History and Development of Behavioral Economics .......................................................... 5 1.2 Behavioral Economics Toolkit:
    [Show full text]
  • Applications of Prospect Theory to Political Science
    JACK S. LEVY APPLICATIONS OF PROSPECT THEORY TO POLITICAL SCIENCE ABSTRACT. Prospect theory is an alternative theory of choice under conditions of risk, and deviates from expected utility theory by positing that people evaluate choices with respect to gains and losses from a reference point. They tend to overweight losses with respect to comparable gains and engage in risk-averse behavior with respect to gains and risk-acceptant behavior with respect to losses. They also respond to probabilities in a non- linear manner. I begin with an overview of prospect theory and some of the evidence upon which it is based, and then consider some of the implications of the theory for American politics, international relations, and the law. I end with a brief discussion of some of the conceptual and methodological problems confronting the application of prospect theory to the study of politics. Rational choice theories based on expected-utility models of decision- making have come to play an increasingly important role in political science over the last two decades, to the point that the debate between rational choice theorists and their critics now constitutes one of the central themes in the theoretical literature on American, comparative, and interna- tional politics. While cultural and constructivist critics of rational choice question its choice-theoretic foundations, behavioral decision theorists ac- cept those basic foundations but question whether expected utility provides an adequate descriptive theory of how people actually make choices under conditions of risk and uncertainty. Although the debate among contending theories of risky choice has yet to be resolved by social psychologists and experimental economists (Bat- talio et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Overcoming the Loss Aversion Obstacle in Negotiation
    \\jciprod01\productn\H\HNR\25-2\HNR202.txt unknown Seq: 1 30-SEP-20 12:42 Overcoming the Loss Aversion Obstacle in Negotiation Yair Livneh* The cognitive bias of loss aversion—the phenomenon that losses loom larger than gains—poses an obstacle in negotiation. Each party’s own concessions loom larger than those of the other party, which makes it difficult to reach an agreement by trading conces- sions. This Article suggests ways to overcome this obstacle. Two types of solutions are presented: substantive solutions, which fo- cus on features in an agreement that may counter loss aversion; and tactical solutions, which focus on presentation strategies to counter loss aversion. This Article also considers whether several well-known but undertheorized negotiation practices owe their effectiveness to their capacity to counter loss aversion bias. CONTENTS I. The Loss Aversion Cognitive Bias .................... 188 R A. The Status Quo Bias, Endowment Effect, and Offer-Asking Gap ................................. 189 R B. Loss Aversion in the Legal Field .................. 190 R II. The Loss Aversion Obstacle in Negotiation ........... 191 R III. Overcoming the Loss Aversion Obstacle .............. 192 R A. Substantive Aspects: Designing an Offer in Light of Loss Aversion ............................ 192 R 1. Making Effective Concessions: Decreasing an Adversary’s Losses Adds More Value than Increasing Their Gains .................. 193 R * Yair Livneh is an Israeli lawyer, veteran of the Israeli tech industry, former commercial litigator, corporate in-house lawyer, and a seasoned negotiator. Yair earned his LL.B. from Tel Aviv University (1995) and his LL.M. from the Hebrew University in Jerusalem (2003), clerked in the chamber of the honorable Justice E.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Stock of the Neuroscientific Approach on Decision Making
    Chapter 22 The Brain is not “as-if” — Taking Stock of the Neuroscientific Approach on Decision Making Kirsten G. Volz and Gerd Gigerenzer Additional information is available at the end of the chapter http://dx.doi.org/10.5772/31393 1. Introduction How do we make decisions? This question has long engaged researchers from various disciplines, including philosophy, psychology, economics, and cognitive neuroscience. Recently, a new discipline – neuroeconomics – emerged, devoted to addressing exactly this question by means of interdisciplinary endeavors. Broadly stated, neuroeconomics sets out “to promote interdisciplinary collaborations on the topics lying at the intersection of the brain and decision sciences in the hope of advancing both theory and research in decision making” (Society for Neuroeconomics, www.neuroeconomics.org), so that it can be used “for discrim‐ inating among standard economic models” (Maskin, 2008, p. 1788) and thus inform economic theory. Neuroeconomics evolved as a field in the late 1990s, an offspring of behavioral economics and cognitive neuroscience. Behavioral economics is itself a relatively new field, just two decades old, and is commonly traced back to Herbert Simon’s concept of bounded rationality (Simon, 1989). All three fields share the same goal of making theories of decision making more realistic by using insights from psychology or cognitive neuroscience. But what may be unrealistic about classical theories of decision making? It appears that there is little evidence that humans make decisions by calculating the expected utility (EU) or any of its variants outside the world of choices between gambles, if at all (e.g., Kahneman & Tversky, 2000; Lopes, 1981; Rubinstein, 1988; Russo & Dosher, 1983).
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Prospect Theory
    An Introduction to Prospect Theory Author(s): Jack S. Levy Source: Political Psychology, Vol. 13, No. 2, Special Issue: Prospect Theory and Political Psychology, (Jun., 1992), pp. 171-186 Published by: International Society of Political Psychology Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3791677 Accessed: 05/06/2008 13:52 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ispp. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Political Psychology, Vol. 13, No. 2, 1992 An Introductionto Prospect Theory Jack S. Levy' Prospect theory has emerged as a leading alternative to expected utility as a theory of decision under risk and has very recently begun to attract attention in the literatureon internationalrelations.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Biases in Risk Management
    Scholars' Mine Masters Theses Student Theses and Dissertations Fall 2007 Cognitive biases in risk management William Thomas Siefert Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsmine.mst.edu/masters_theses Part of the Systems Engineering Commons Department: Recommended Citation Siefert, William Thomas, "Cognitive biases in risk management" (2007). Masters Theses. 4590. https://scholarsmine.mst.edu/masters_theses/4590 This thesis is brought to you by Scholars' Mine, a service of the Missouri S&T Library and Learning Resources. This work is protected by U. S. Copyright Law. Unauthorized use including reproduction for redistribution requires the permission of the copyright holder. For more information, please contact [email protected]. i COGNITIVE BIASES IN RISK MANAGEMENT by WILLIAM THOMAS SIEFERT A THESIS Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the UNIVERSITY OF MISSOURI-ROLLA In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree MASTER OF SCIENCE IN SYSTEMS ENGINEERING 2007 Approved by ___________________ __________________ Cihan H. Dagli, Advisor Ann Miller ___________________ Eric D. Smith ii © 2007 WILLIAM THOMAS SIEFERT All Rights Reserved iii ABSTRACT The purpose of this thesis is to explore the relationship of risk management/mitigation and the people who practice the discipline. Much has been written concerning risk and the analytical ways that it can be measured. The need for accurate and timely risk mitigation has accelerated with the pace of new and replacement programs. A part of the process that needs to be updated is that risk needs to be seen as systems attribute, much the same as cost, schedule and technical compliance. It is absolutely necessary that today’s Systems Engineers develop and follow a Risk Management and Mitigation Plan in the early phases of the project.
    [Show full text]
  • Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain
    NEUROECONOMICS Decision Making and the Brain SECOND EDITION Edited by PAUL W. G LIMCHER New York University, New York, NY, USA ERNST FEHR University of Zurich, Switzerland AMSTERDAM • BOSTON • HEIDELBERG • LONDON NEW YORK • OXFORD • PARIS • SAN DIEGO SAN FRANCISCO • SINGAPORE • SYDNEY • TOKYO Academic Press is an imprint of Elsevier Academic Press is an imprint of Elsevier 32 Jamestown Road, London NW1 7BY, UK 225 Wyman Street, Waltham, MA 02451, USA 525 B Street, Suite 1800, San Diego, CA 92101-4495, USA Copyright r 2014, 2008 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior written permission of the publisher. Permissions may be sought directly from Elsevier’s Science & Technology Rights Department in Oxford, UK: phone (144) (0) 1865 843830; fax (1 44) (0) 1865 853333; email: permissions@elsevier. com. Alternatively, visit the Science and Technology Books website at www.elsevierdirect.com/ rights for further information. Notice No responsibility is assumed by the publisher for any injury and/or damage to persons or property as a matter of products liability, negligence or otherwise, or from any use or operation of any methods, products, instructions or ideas contained in the material herein. Because of rapid advances in the medical sciences, in particular, independent verification of diagnoses and drug dosages should be made. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication
    [Show full text]
  • Prospect Theory Or Skill Signaling?
    Prospect Theory or Skill Signaling? Rick Harbaugh June 2020 Abstract Formalizing early social psychology models, we show that a rational desire to avoid looking unskilled generates prospect theory’sanomalies of loss aversion, probability weighting, and framing. Loss aversion arises because losing any gamble, even a friendly bet with little or no money at stake, reflects poorly on the decision maker’sskill. Probability weighting emerges because winning a gamble with a low probability of success is a strong signal of skill, while losing a gamble with a high probability of success is a strong signal of incompetence. Framing can affect behavior by selecting among multiple equilibria. D81; D82; C92; G11 Kelley School of Business, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN (email: [email protected]). I thank David Bell, Roland Benabou, Tom Borcherding, Vince Crawford, Nandini Gupta, Bill Harbaugh, Wayne Harbaugh, Ron Harstad, Tatiana Kornienko, Ricky Lam, Marilyn Pease, Lan Zhang, and seminar participants at the Claremont Colleges, DePaul University, Emory University, IUPUI, Princeton University, UNC/Duke, the Behavioral Research Council, the Econometric Society Winter Meetings, the Stony Brook Game Theory Conference, the Midwest Theory Meetings, and the Berlin Status and Social Image Workshop. Most risky decisions involve both skill and chance, so success brings not just material gain but an enhanced reputation for skill, while failure is doubly unfortunate. Completing a diffi cult project wins the confidence of friends and colleagues, while an embarrassing failure leaves one looking like a foolish loser. As shown in the classic psychology theories of self-esteem (James, 1890), achievement motivation (Atkinson, 1957), and self-handicapping (Jones and Berglas, 1978), people choose among risky alternatives not just for the immediate monetary payoffs, but also to avoid appearing unskilled.
    [Show full text]