<<

On the Evolutionary Origin of Preferences

Rose McDermott University of , Santa Barbara James H. Fowler University of California, San Diego Oleg Smirnov State University of New York at Stony Brook

Prospect theory scholars have identified important human decision-making biases, but they have been conspicuously silent on the question of the origin of these biases. Here we create a model that shows preferences consistent with prospect theory may have an origin in evolutionary . Specifically, we derive a model from -sensitive optimal foraging theory to generate an explanation for the origin and function of context-dependent and risk-seeking behavior. Although this model suggests that human cognitive architecture evolved to solve particular adaptive problems related to finding sufficient food resources to survive, we argue that this same architecture persists and is utilized in other survival-related decisions that are critical to understanding political outcomes. In particular, we identify important departures from standard results when we incorporate prospect theory into theories of spatial voting and legislator behavior, international bargaining and conflict, and economic development and reform.

rospect theory has become one of the most figures such as B.F. Skinner (1952) who wholly influential behavioral theories of choice in the disregarded the importance of cognitive processing P wider social sciences, particularly in psychol- in human action. As such, prospect theory can be ogy and (Kahneman, Slovic, and Tversky understood as representing the apex of the cognitive 1982; Kahneman and Tversky 1979). It has also been revolution in psychology and social sciences in general applied to issues in political science (Druckman 2001; (Simon 1985). This historical development of prospect Lau and Redlawsk 2001; McDermott 2004; Mercer, theory as a significant departure from behavioral into 2005; Quattrone and Tversky 1988); in particular, in cognitive explanations for decision making is interest- the areas of international relations (Berejikian 1997, ing because, as Mercer notes; ‘‘The dominant explan- 2002; Faber 1990; Jervis 1994, 2004; Levy 1994, 1997; ation for political scientists’ tepid response focuses on McDermott 1998), international political the theoretical problems with extending a theory (Elms 2004), comparative politics (Weyland 1996, devised in the lab to explain political decisions in 1998), American politics (Patty 2006), and public the field ....It suggests that prospect theory’s failure policy (McDaniel and Sistrunk 1991). As a model to ignite the imagination of more political scientists explaining decision making under conditions of risk, probably results from their aversion to behavioral prospect theory provides an elegant description of the assumptions and not from problems unique to pros- relationship between environmental contingency in pect theory’’ (2005, 1). And, indeed, more recent work the form of gains and losses and individual risk in decision making within has propensity. In short, those faced with gains tend to be also begun to incorporate and risk averse, while those confronting losses become much into cognitively oriented theories of choice. Similar more risk seeking. Prospect theory developed in explicit research trends can be observed in economics as well opposition to more normative models of rational (Andreoni 1990; Bolton and Ockenfels 2000; Dawes choice, such as subjective expected theory. et al. 2007; Fehr and Schmidt 1999; Rabin 1993, 2002). Historically, prospect theory also evolved in reac- Models derived from risk-sensitive optimal for- tion to earlier behavioral models exemplified by aging theory offer an opportunity to generate an

The Journal of Politics, Vol. 70, No. 2, April 2008, Pp. 335–350 doi:10.1017/S0022381608080341 Ó 2008 Southern Political Science Association ISSN 0022-3816 335 336 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov explanation for the origin of the risk propensities ations, and choices than being poor, black, and described by prospect theory. Certainly, female. Behavior results from the person acting such as Gigerenzer (1996) and Cosmides and Tooby within the context of a situation; both disposition (1996), among others, endorse an evolutionarily in- and situation determine , and neither should formed alternative perspective on the origin and be left out of the equation in service of parsimony or function of human decision-making biases. Our par- simplicity. ticular evolutionary model provides a parsimonious explanation for why individuals may possess hard- wired tendencies to make choices consistent with the Prospect Theory predictions of prospect theory. Although this model suggests that human cognitive architecture evolved to won the in Economics solve particular adaptive problems related to finding in 2002 for his work with on prospect sufficient food resources to survive, we argue that this theory. This model proved widely influential because same architecture persists and is utilized in other it provided comprehensive empirical demonstrations survival-related decisions. of actual human decision-making behavior in risky An evolutionary model for the origin of prospect domains. This theory contradicted many of the theory preferences holds significant implications assumptions and implications of standard economic for understanding the nature and function of human theory, thereby spawning a great deal of research in decision-making processes. This matters because in- designed to examine ‘‘anoma- tervention is less likely to be successful in changing lies’’ in choice. these risk predilections. For example, cognitive biases, Briefly, prospect theory comprises two phases, and other lapses from rationality, can be at least the editing phase, which constitutes framing effects, partially remedied with sufficient learning, awareness, and the evaluation phase. Framing effects demon- and education. This can take place through experience, strate, for example, that people make substantively Bayesian updating, or other processes. While such different choices when confronting alternate outcome biases may always have the characteristic quality of framings (Tversky and Kahneman 1981). Most fa- visual illusions in that people can ‘‘feel’’ the pull of mously, people make different choices about medical framing effects even when they are made transparent, treatment when options are phrased in terms of individuals can adopt strategies to overcome their ‘‘survival’’ or ‘‘mortality,’’ even when the objective more negative tendencies. However, if prospect theo- outcome probabilities remain identical. Specifically, retic tendencies concerning risk propensity lie more people are much more risk averse in the ‘‘gain frame’’ deeply rooted in human , the when outcomes are expressed in terms of the prob- implications for decision making and potential reme- ability of living (survival), than in the ‘‘loss frame’’ diation shift. First, such biases may not be so easily when outcomes are expressed in terms of the prob- overcome, particularly with individuals who live close ability of dying (mortality) (McNeil, Sox, and Tversky to the margin of survival. Second, people may prove 1982). less likely to be able to learn over time or through The evaluation phase incorporates a value func- experience to compensate for these tendencies. And tion and a weighting function. The value function finally, politicians and others may be able to manipulate predicts risk aversion in the domain of gains and risk humans for their own means by invoking such modules, taking in losses. Importantly, gains and losses are for example by emphasizing emotional threats to evaluated relative to a reference point, often assumed survival to order to increase support for risky policies. to be equivalent to the status quo, but which in reality We argue for a greater sensitivity to ecological can deviate from this point in response to such factors rationality in models of politics. How a person thinks, as social comparison, current need state, future expect- and what constitutes rational behavior, depends on ations, or past history. The weighting function estab- the situational and environmental context in which lishes a nonlinear decision weight independent of that individual operates. An ecologically valid model normative probability. This function demonstrates of political behavior, or any other behavior, involves that individuals tend to overweight small probability an interaction between both individual characteristics events while underweighting medium and high prob- and specific situational aspects of the environment. ability events. Interestingly, people overweight cer- Being hungry provokes different thoughts, feelings, tainty, such that they tend to treat highly probable and behaviors than being full, just as being wealthy, events as certain and highly improbable events as if white, and male produces different options, expect- they are impossible. on the evolutionary origin of prospect theory preferences 337

Several findings prove quite robust experimen- smart makes women patient and men take more ’’ tally, including framing effects, shifts in risk propen- (2005, 38). sity based on domain, and , Sex differences in this area can be explained by that losses hurt more than equal gains please. Tversky different evolutionary motives and pressures as well; argued that this model was intuitively supported by women are more likely to pass on their genes if they the of ; it is easy to make provide nurturance and protection for their children, someone miserable for a long time, but quite hard while men often have to fight challengers for access to make anyone happy for even a brief period. The to reproductive rights from the outset. Individuals ‘‘Hedonic Treadmill’’ (Brickman and Campbell 1971) would thus be expected to vary predictably in their is a perfect example of this phenomenon; people have individual risk curves if their current state, starvation to work harder and harder just to maintain the same or satiation, determines whether the survival of their level of happiness. Because human evolved genes is at stake. In other words, individuals in to focus on change as opposed to stasis, individuals different hedonic states, happy or sad, hungry or full, remain most sensitive to change that threatens to may demonstrate the same prospect theory shaped make things worse. curve, albeit with different reference points based on In fact, asymmetry in the hedonic experience of a transient current state (Aktipis and Kurzban 2004). gains and losses can be understood intuitively from From an evolutionary perspective, we would ex- this evolutionary perspective as well. Outside the pect decisions over life and death matters to demon- realms of reproduction and eating, few positive ex- strate greater consistency with prospect oriented periences offer fitness advantage. After all, in the end, preferences than choices involving money. If such risk there are natural limits on reproduction and raising propensities evolved in the context of choices that offspring, which are higher for women than men, affect survival, the cues which trigger them would since the length of pregnancy places limits on the most likely be elicited in similar contexts. Further, we number of children a woman can bear. But surviving might expect systematic sex differences in basic risk or avoiding even a single negative experience result- propensity, reflected by different average reference ing from encounters with predators or poisoned food points experienced by men and women; women, may prove essential for survival and fitness. In other requiring greater protection during pregnancy and words, when survival is uncertain, marginal losses later for protecting vulnerable offspring, would likely prove more critical for reproductive success than mar- have lower starting reference points than men, on ginal gains. As Aktipis and Kurzban (2004) note, a average, leading to greater caution in survival-related hungry animal should be more motivated, and thus circumstances. Again, circumstances dictate the con- risk taking, to find food, than a full one. That is why, text of individual choice and structure the cues which as they argue, the first doughnut always tastes better trigger either risk-seeking or risk-averse behavior; than the fifth, a phenomenon akin to those experi- the genetic costs for women abandoning offspring enced by coffee and tobacco addicts. are simply much higher than they are for men, Indeed, some have questioned whether individ- inducing greater caution in environments of uncer- uals display such strong framing effects with regard tainty, whereas men may benefit reproductively by to money as they do in the arena of human lives, taking chances to find and win mates. assuming that most people value the latter more than the former. In one study (Fagley and Miller 1997), subjects made riskier choices in the domain of human life than in the financial realm, regardless of whether that choice was in gains or losses. However, a Risk-Sensitive Optimal Foraging notable sex difference appeared in this study, indicat- Theory ing that women’s choices were affected by frame, while men’s choices were not. The authors provide Employing a theoretical evolutionary perspective no explanation for their findings, but this sex differ- helps provide a consistent explanation for human ence may simply reflect the location of the salient decision making which, while often appearing con- reference point across genders. For example, Shane sistent with some elements of standard economic Frederick argued that smarter people appeared to be theory, deviates systematically and predictably within more risk acceptant in general, while men prove risky contexts in the ways expected by prospect theory. more risk acceptant than women, even controlling Importantly, an evolutionary perspective posits that for . He writes, ‘‘(e)xpressed loosely, being humans evolved specific cognitive mechanisms that 338 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov were selected over time to respond to the adaptive approval; once the Food and Drug Administration challenges repeatedly faced by our hunter-gatherer approves the use of a particular drug, doctors often ancestors (Barkow, Cosmides, and Tooby 1992). prescribe it ‘‘off-label’’ for uses far removed from Specifically, humans evolved a variety of innate their original purpose, to good or bad effect. programs designed to solve particular problems, such Around the time that Tversky and Kahneman as language acquisition. These programs are domain were developing prospect theory, behavioral ecolo- specific and content laden. The skills and strategies gists, ethnologists, and evolutionary biologists began humans use differ by task: acquiring language re- questioning established views of animal behavior as quires different skills and abilities than learning math; well. In particular, Caraco (1980) and Stephens linguists like Chomsky (1956) and Fitch, Hansen, and (1981) began challenging existing foraging models Chomsky (2005) have shown that mathematical laws as deficient, once environmental realities, such as applied to language acquisition fail to account for the variation in food availability over different terrains, speed, accuracy, and universal fluency achieved by all were taken into account. Caraco employed an ex- normal young children. Similarly, particular domains pected utility model to demonstrate that animals can contain very specific content. For example, vision has often benefit from a risk-taking in their very specific content which allow us to maintain color feeding preferences if these environmental variations constancy over the course of changing sunlight across prove critical to survival. Stephens (1981; Stephens the day. The information our eyes process is not at all and Krebs 1986) extended and formalized this notion what we experience ourselves as ‘‘seeing’’ and yet our to explain such risk sensitivity in optimal foraging, brains ‘‘see’’ the same thing (say ‘‘green grass’’) over arguing that animals evolved to take advantage of the course of the day although the light spectrum variations in the probability of payoffs across various changes reliably as the earth rotates on its axis. contexts. Often we remain unaware of our evolved pro- Why was this realization important? Prior models grams because they operate so flawlessly, automati- assumed that animals would simply forage for food cally, and without effort, like vision. Yet, over time, where the mean expected payoff was highest, inde- these programs can be adapted for other uses, just as pendent of variance. This strategy can work effec- reading and writing developed as by-products of our tively when food is abundant, but can risk starvation innate ability to acquire spoken language. Similarly, when the environment changes or remains uncertain the cognitive hardwiring that evolved to handle risk because of seasonal weather variations. The evolu- likely evolved to solve important repeated problems tionary argument offers the important insight that which systematically affected reproductive fitness. animals will become most accepting of risk when These challenges most likely related to survival tasks, their chance for starvation runs highest. Alternate such as acquiring food and avoiding predators. Thus, feeding grounds with higher variance may present a in searching for a domain area in which to examine higher risk, but they may also offer the possibility of a the evolutionary development of innate human risk- higher reward and provide a chance to stave off taking strategies, problems related to foraging for starvation. In terms of risk taking, optimal foraging food present a promising arena. Over long periods of models suggest that sensitivity to variance in outcome evolutionary time, successful strategies become uni- can be rational under conditions where survival is versal as random genetic mutations which offer threatened. Later models sought to incorporate var- reproductive advantage become universal. Particular ious trade-off calculations, as when finding more or content laden programs are then cued by the triggers better quality food also poses a greater risk of that signaled significant risk in the past. These predators (Houston, McNamara, and Hutchinson programs, in turn, entrain specific repertoires of 1993). Note the difference between this foraging thoughts, feelings, and responses which conveyed strategy and that predicted by standard economic reproductive success to our ancestors, but which theory, which assumes that an individual should may or may not serve us well in the current environ- always seek out the highest expected value payoff. ment, which is quite different than the one in which In many circumstances, such as when resources are humans originally evolved. Such programs also then abundant, it makes sense to maximize expected value become available for cooptation and adaptation in and minimize risk because this strategy maximizes other situations and contexts that cue risk, no matter the probability of survival. When survival is virtually how divorced those environments may be from the assured, standard economic theory offers good pre- original one in which they evolved. A modern dictions for human behavior. However, the literature example of this phenomenon can be found in drug on prospect theory shows that when confronting loss on the evolutionary origin of prospect theory preferences 339 and death in particular, standard economic theory These authors were able to reverse the ambiguity fails in predictable ways. In these circumstances, effect when the subjects’ need remained greater than people do behave in ways consistent with a model the expected mean outcome. When subjects were based on environmental contingency, however. satisfied with their position, they remained risk averse Clear evidence exists that animals can demon- and avoided the unknown probability, but when strate sophisticated strategies concerning risk (with- they were not satisfied, they developed a risk-seeking out being taught economic theory!). For example, for the ambiguous option, for example. As Chen, Lakshminarayanan, and Santos conducted an these authors conclude, ‘‘(o)ne should not expect the experimental demonstration of trading behavior in cognitive architectures of evolved organisms to be capuchin monkeys. Seeking to illustrate the innate ‘‘rational’’ when rationality is defined as adherence to nature of decision-making biases in behavior, they a normative theory drawn from or logic. showed that monkeys often appear to demonstrate One should expect their cognitive architectures to be clear preferences, and respond rationally to price and ecologically rational: well designed for solving adapted wealth changes, as a standard might suggest problems their ancestors faced during their evolu- humans do. However, once risky choices are imposed tionary history’’ (Cosmides and Tooby 1994, 329; on the capuchins, ‘‘they display several hallmark [Tooby and Cosmides 1999]). biases when faced with gambles, including reference dependence and loss-aversion’’ (2006, 517). The au- thors conclude that such demonstrations indicate the innate basis of these biases, suggesting that some The Model evolved part of capuchin instinct is sensitive to risk and becomes increasingly risk seeking in the face of In this section, we present a model designed to loss. Evidence from these primates suggests a com- demonstrate how differences in risk propensity con- mon evolutionary basis for such risk propensities sistent with prospect theory predictions can offer in humans. survival advantages, thus offering a theoretical evolu- In recent work designed to explain the existence tionary basis for the origin of prospect-oriented of individual personality in animals, Wolf et al. preferences. Specifically, we show how factors beyond (2007) examines the trade-off between early and late the control of the individual, such as environmental reproductive strategies and risk-taking behavior. contingencies, can influence independent decisions Empirically, research has demonstrated that animal over risk. These contingencies, in turn, can serve as personality is both heritable (van Oers et al. 2005) environmental cues for particular patterns of risk pro- and linked to reproductive fitness (Dingemanse and pensity in related but independent contexts, although Reale, 2005), and yet remains obviously variable. perhaps not as often or as strongly. Seeking to account for this conundrum, Wolf et al. Imagine a world in which one must acquire argue that, ‘‘individuals with high future expectations resources in order to survive and reproduce. The (who have much to lose) should be more risk-averse easiest resource to consider is food. Suppose that in than individuals with low expectations. This applies some period an individual must acquire a minimum to all kinds of risk situations, so individuals should threshold t of food in order to live to the next period. consistently differ in their behaviour’’ (2007, 581). In Survival is a dichotomous variable—you are either the words of a Nature writer characterizing this work, dead or alive, you either reproduce or you do not. ‘‘the optimal animal should be bold only when it But resources are continuous and subject to numer- makes sense to be bold, and adjust its behaviour ous random fluctuations. For example, variation in when the situation changes’’ (Bell 2007, 539). seasonal rainfall can dramatically affect the produc- Optimal foraging models also prove relevant tion of fruit and nuts sought by hunter-gatherers and for understanding the origins of other interesting harvests of other foods in primitive agricultural ‘‘anomalies’’ in preferences that are consistent with societies. There may also be tremendous variation prospect theory. For example, , in the day-to-day availability of small and large game. whereby people prefer options with stated probabil- Suppose further that such an individual con- ities to those without them—even when both options fronts a choice between a low mean, low variance hold the same expected value—can be explained from source of food, and a high mean, high variance this perspective. Rode et al. (1999) suggest that alternative source. If the person is at risk of starva- people avoid unknown probabilities because they tion, he or she is likely to choose the high mean, high tend to co-occur with high variance in outcome. variance source precisely because it maximizes the 340 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov probability of finding enough food to survive. The FIGURE 1 Effect of Risky and Safe Choices on the low mean, low variance option may guarantee a high Probability of Survival in Various probability of a positive payoff, but if the expected Environments value is low enough, the person will not survive. Thus, the person will likely take a greater risk to seek 1.0 π food at the high mean, high variance site because it safe offers the possibility of survival, however remote, that πrisky the low mean source does not. However, if the person 0.8 has already acquired sufficient resources from other activities, he or she may choose the low mean, low Domain of Gains variance site to guarantee a surplus of food above the 0.6 minimum threshold. This scenario demonstrates two important factors: (1) risk propensity will depend on Domain of Losses the current state of the decision maker, his individual 0.4 reference point; (2) a switching strategy between sites Probability of Survival can maximize survival prospects over either constant πrisky risk averse or risk seeking strategies. 0.2 We can abstract from these daily struggles with a πsafe

simple assumption: the amount of food an individual 0.0 acquires from the environment e is a simple draw from μ < τ μ = τ μ > τ a probability distribution. The likelihood that an Total Payoff individual acquires enough resources to survive is thus simply Pr (e . t). Suppose this is a stable probability decreasing in the size of the loss: losing the third meal distribution (the Normal, Cauchy, and Levy are probably hurts much less than losing the second or versions of this type of probability) with mean m first meal. At absolute starvation levels we might even 2 and variance s . Under these conditions, the proba- be willing to risk the first meal in order to obtain bility that an individual survives is a simple standard enough meals to survive. cumulative distribution of the stable density (F): Thus, the need to attain a fixed payoff threshold m t to survive has consequences for choices made under F : ð1Þ s risk. Suppose an individual in an environment with expected payoff m receives both a payoff from the Figure 1 plots the probability of survival as a environment and a payoff from a decision over two function of the expected payoff m. Notice that the alternatives. These two alternatives have the same relationship is not linear. When resources are very expected value, but one is ‘‘safe’’ and the other is scarce (m t) survival is unlikely and when they ‘‘risky’’—the safe choice yields a payoff of p with areveryabundant(m t), survival is virtually probability 1. The risky choice yields a payoff of 1 assured. Between these extremes is an s-shaped with probability p and 0 otherwise. Since the expected transition in which the probability bends upward as value of each choice is the same, standard economic it becomes increasingly responsive to gains and then theory has nothing to say about it without adding an flattens out and bends downward as it approaches extra ad hoc assumption about risk. However, under unity. If the payoff distribution is normal, then this the assumption that survival depends on achieving a curve follows a familiar probit form, but any stable minimum payoff, we can see how selection might probability will generate an s-shaped cumulative favor certain types of individuals. distribution. Intuitively, the figure shows that devia- Suppose there are two types of individuals, the bold tions from the point where the expected payoff equals and the meek. Bold individuals always take the risky the survival threshold (m 5 t) have similar effects but choice which nets them a probability of survival of in opposite directions. Suppose that under these conditions the environment generates three meals m t þ 1 m t p 5 pF þ ðÞ1 p F : ð2Þ in a given period. The marginal benefit of gains is risky s s decreasing in the size of the gain: we may not enjoy the fourth and fifth meal in a given period as much as In other words, the probability of survival is a weighted the third meal because it has less impact on our average of the high-gain payoff (1) and the low-gain survival. However, the marginal cost of losses is also payoff (0). As p increases from 0 to 1, the expected on the evolutionary origin of prospect theory preferences 341 survival rate increases linearly from FðÞðÞm t =s species will not be able to adapt optimal behavior to FðÞðÞm t þ 1 =s . In contrast, meek individuals al- each new environment. Thus, there may be a selective ways choose the safe option which nets them a sure- advantage to choice behavior that explicitly takes thing increase in their payoff. This translates into a account of the environment when making choices. survival probability We call individuals who exhibit this kind of behavior prospectors. These individuals will take risks when m t þ p psafe 5F : ð3Þ their survival is threatened and play it safe otherwise. s The more their choices conform to optimal strategies Here, p appears inside the probability of survival term for maximizing survival, the more likely the mecha- because it is a certain payoff. The meek survival rate nisms that evolved to generate these choices will be also increases from FðÞðÞm t =s to FððÞm t þ 1 = passed on to future generations. sÞ as p goes from 0 to 1. However, it does so This begs the question regarding what strategy is nonlinearly, traveling along the contour of the optimal. How much risk is too much? To analyze the s-shaped cumulative distribution function.1 As Figure 1 question, suppose that an individual must acquire a shows, this means that the best-surviving strategy payoff t in order to survive in an environment that changes depending on the environment. In abundant generates a payoff e of stable random distribution 2 environments (m . t) the safe choice yields a prob- with mean m, variance s , and cumulative distribu- ability of survival that is higher than the risky choice tion F. This payoff reflects the fact that there are for any given p. This is because the probability of many factors beyond the individual’s control that survival is already high—success in the risky option affect his or her survival. But there are also some does not add much to this probability, but failure factors over which an individual has control. Suppose substantially increases the risk of falling below the the individual additionally faces a choice Q between a threshold. Symmetrically, when resources are scarce low-risk outcome usafe and a high-risk outcome urisky. (m . t) the risky choice improves the probability of Given a choice between two certain outcomes, the survival. When individuals have nothing to lose, individual that chooses the one with higher payoff it makes sense for them to engage in risky behavior will always be more likely to survive. However, when with the hope that it will keep them alive through the outcomes are uncertain, the best choice is less straight- next period. forward. Individuals must take into account the ex- Students of prospect theory will immediately pected payoff, expected variance, and risk of each recognize in Figure 1 the pattern of choices that have choice and also the expected payoff resulting from been observed in countless tests of Kahneman and environmental factors over which they have no control. Tversky’s conjectures. In the ‘‘domain of gains,’’ To see why, suppose the payoffs from each choice people typically trade reward for risk and accept the (usafe; urisky) are drawn from the same stable distri- lower payoffs of the safe option. In contrast, in the bution as e but with different means (mrisky; msafe) and variances (s2 . s2 ). The optimal prospector ‘‘domain of losses’’ they are more likely to choose risky safe gambles, even when they generate expected payoffs will take the risky choice only when it generates a that are lower than the safe option. higher probability of survival: Pr e þ urisky . t . Pr e þ usafe . t . This occurs when2 0 1 0 1 The Evolution of Prospect Bm þ m tC Bm þ m tC Preferences F@ qffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffirisky A .F@ qffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffisafe A: ð4Þ s2 þ s2 s2 þ s2 risky safe We can imagine long-term changes in the abundance of resources having a profound effect on the selection of risky behavior. When times are tough, bold types will do better and when times are good the meek will fare better. If the typical variation in resources 2Consider the probability of survival with the risky choice on the happens much faster than the pace of evolution, then left-hand side. Since both random variables are drawn from stable probabilities, they can be expressed as a single random variable with the same distribution, mean m þ mrisky, and 1 2 2 Since stable probability densities are unimodal (Yamazato 1978), variance s þ srisky. Similarly, the random variables on the right 00 F is positive before the mode, indicating it is concave up, and combine to form a single random variable with mean m þ msafe, 2 2 negative after the mode, indicating it is concave down. and variance s þ ssafe. 342 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov

Solving for m produces an optimal rule for when to mistakes because it is difficult to determine whether switch from the safe to the risky choice. The risky one is in the domain of gains or losses, then a non- choice is favored when: contingent rule like the one used by meek may be superior. By symmetry, when m is always low, bold m m rriskyffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffiffi safe types may do better than prospectors. Thus, we expect m , t msafe þ ð5Þ s2 þ s2 risky the greatest evolutionary pressure for the develop- s2 þ s2 1 safe ment of prospector preferences to occur where envi- ronments and choices keep individuals living close to Intuitively, the rule specifies conditions under the threshold of survival, or specifically where the which an individual makes a decision in the domain average payoff from the environment m is equal to the of losses as opposed to the domain of gains. The rule right-hand side in the rule above. Although such an shows that there always exists a set of conditions environment may not exist in advanced industrial- under which the probability of survival is improved 3 ized countries, it seems likely to have existed in by the risky choice. It is especially important to prehistoric hunter-gatherer societies and may even realize that this is even true when the risky choice characterize modern-day societies where survival is yields an expected payoff that is lower than the safe difficult. choice. Individuals in scarce environments benefit Finally, it is important to remember that we are from risk because it is the only way to make it above assuming here that payoffs have an effect on the the survival threshold, and they are even willing to probability of survival. Note here that in evolutionary trade off some expected value to acquire this risk. In theory survival relates not to that of the individual, economics, this kind of choice is said to have option but to the survival of offspring; in other words, value. reproduction is critical. Individuals who find enough Suppose that the higher risk choice also yields the food will survive, but they may not reproduce. higher reward (mrisky . msafe). First, notice that the Extremely thin women, for example, have a hard right-hand side increases as the mean payoff from 2 time conceiving. If selection favors mechanisms that the safe outcome msafe decreases and its variance ssafe help us behave like prospectors, then we expect these increases. As the value of the safe option declines and mechanisms to have a greater effect on choices that becomes more uncertain, survival may be best are fitness relevant, that is, related to the survival of achieved by switching to the risky option. In contrast, offspring. Specifically, choices about life and death, the right-hand side increases as the mean payoff from reproduction, and the survival of related individuals the risky outcome mrisky increases and its variance 2 are all more likely to be governed by prospect srisky decreases. Safer and more rewarding risky preferences than other choices that have little bearing choices will be more likely to entice prospectors to on our survival or the transmission of our genes. take a chance. Although these conditions may be rare, they certainly Second, the mean and variance of payoffs that are exist in conditions of combat, famine, or other natural independent of the choice also affect the decision. disasters affected by political contexts. Increasing the average expected payoff in the envi- ronment (m) decreases the set of conditions that would cause a prospector to switch to the risky choice. Political Implications In other words, as resources become more abundant, we expect individuals to become generally more risk Aktipis and Kurzban (2004) have called attention to averse. In contrast, increasing the variance of the 2 the importance of foraging theory for economic environment s increases the value of the right-hand models of choice and decision making and here we side, which makes it more likely we will observe do the same for models of politics. If human individuals making risky choices. Uncertain environ- cognitive architecture evolved to respond differen- ments select for individuals who choose the high-risk, tially to risk in the face of scarcity and abundance high-reward option. based on environmental contingencies, then those Third, notice that the fitness advantage of pros- cues will serve to trigger specific risk-taking behaviors pectors depends on environmental change. If m is in other arenas, including political contexts. This will always high, then the meek will do nearly as well as be especially likely if the survival of early humans prospectors. In fact, if prospectors sometimes make depended on political decisions about cooperation 3This is true as long as the means are finite, the variances are and resource distribution among group members 2 2 positive and finite, and srisky 6¼ ssafe (Boehm 1999). on the evolutionary origin of prospect theory preferences 343

For example, political leaders who make deci- voters and leaders face coalitional choices in sions with regard to international challenges may most political decisions. accept greater costs to regain the previous reference Allocating time and energy to such decision point in the face of losses—having living soldiers die making constitutes an important adaptive task, which to justify past losses provides only the most salient requires a great deal of as well. example of this type of strategy. We often see leaders Delegating particular communal concerns to estab- taking much greater risks in the area of war, involving lished representatives can provide an important life and death, than we do in international economic mechanism for confronting risk within the context relations, which largely involve money, trade, and of a particular preestablished coalition, such as a wealth (Fagley and Miller, 1997; Kuhberger, Schulte- political party, ethnic group, or religion. The problem Mecklenbeck, and Perner 1999; McDermott 1998). of course is that such behavior evolved in the context Indeed, we would expect such differences in risk of much smaller groups than modern political or- propensity based on our model. Leaders who espouse ganizations, and these strategies may no longer be a constant risk strategy may do well in certain adaptive within our much larger current social and environments, as our earlier bold and meek individ- political environment. But the tendency to expect uals succeed in scarce and abundant environments, cooperation and service from leaders remains. Just as respectively. But leaders who demonstrate flexibility tribal societies value cooperation and egalitarianism, and the ability to switch strategies based on particular and punish aggression and self-aggrandizement in environmental contingencies may do best of all, leaders (Boehm 1999), modern societies seek to punish especially in environments where threats to survival ethical violations on the part of our leaders through change over time. sanctions including job loss, jail, and in certain so- The behavior of ordinary citizens is also likely to cieties, death. Similarly, triggers and adaptive pro- be influenced by prospect theory preferences. Just as a grams evolved for one context become entrained to willingness to take risk varies with the current respond to established cues embedded within entirely hedonic state of the individual in our model, the cur- different substantive areas in predictable ways. For rent state of an individual may influence their per- example, voters might worry that a politician who spective on a wide variety of political issues, from cheats on his wife may similarly cheat on his coa- immigration to war. The reference point of given lition, acting as a free rider, or taking undue rewards, individuals may differ based on their level of wealth, while others may feel the need to support one’s own for example, but the basic risk propensity of prefer- national alliance and coalition under conditions of ring caution in good times, and risk in bad, is likely conflict, in fear of being overwhelmed by the enemy. to remain robust in general if it is underscored by the evolutionary processes we suggest. Risk acceptance Revisiting Extant Political Models proclivities in the domain of losses may explain, for example, why voters appear particularly willing to If existing theoretical and empirical models and our take large risks and chances when things are going alternative prospector model generate the same re- badly (Weyland 1996). sults, then our theory would not be of much Prospect theory also has implications for coali- importance. However, we note that most models of tional behavior. The size and strength of alliances politics typically have not assumed prospector pref- may prove central in individuals’ assessments of the erences, and this has caused them to generate challenges they confront, and their ability to respond important results that cause scholars to make incor- successfully to them. Just as animals face a trade off rect inferences in at least some cases. It is not true in deciding whether to forage for food alone or that extant models are always wrong, but rather that in groups (Houston, McNamara, and Hutchinson they are reliably right under certain conditions, and 1993), leaders, members of Congress, and individual that they are predictably, systematically incorrect re- voters face a similar calculus in decisions about who garding other conditions, specifically those involving to support politically and how much to sacrifice on risk or threat to survival. It may be that standard behalf of their communal concerns. In the animal models work well when environmental conditions are world, foraging with others increases the likelihood of characterized by abundance. However, when the finding food and also reduces the risk of predation. external situation changes and individuals or groups But such a strategy also potentially reduces the begin to face real or perceived threats to survival, amount of food an individual can eat if he must preferences will change in the predictable way that we share with his foraging partners. Similarly, individual have demonstrated, and this will have an effect on 344 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov inferences drawn from important models in each models, the weighting function represents this dy- major subfield of political science. Certainly alter- namic well; the end-points (outcomes judged to be native explanations exist for all these models, but we either certain or impossible) are not well behaved present some illustrations of how an evolutionary precisely because psychological assessment remains lens can shift our understanding. indifferent between such choices.4 This reasoning suggests that the utility of a policy will be s-shaped— American Spatial Voting Models concave near the ideal point and convex at the ex- tremes, flattening out as the distance tends to infinity. Black (1958) and Downs (1957) conceptualized a The largest differences in utility will occur between broad set of political decisions as being spatial in equally spaced alternatives that are only moderately nature. Policies are located in an ideological space, distant from the preferred alternative. and each individual has a certain ideal policy in mind Psychological evidence suggests that human de- when they compare alternatives. The utility of a given cisions do conform to an s-shaped spatial utility alternative is inversely related to the Euclidean dis- function. For example, Shepard (1962) shows that tance between it and the individual’s ideal policy. people are better able to discriminate hues close to Later scholars developed the spatial theory (e.g., their favorite hue. A wide variety of other discrim- Davis, Hinich, and Ordeshook 1970) and used it to ination tasks suggest that a basic property of human generate sophisticated models of party competition is the ability to scrutinize differences in (e.g., Roemer 2001; Wittman 1977) and the legislative preferred objects and the inability to detect similarly process (e.g., Baron and Ferejohn 1989). These sized differences in less-preferred objects (Shepard models have greatly improved our understanding of 1987). This is similar to findings in psychology con- politics, but the vast majority of them have made cerning ingroup effects, whereby people see more strong assumptions about risk in order to achieve variation within members of their social ingroup than tractability. For example, the canonical risk assump- among outgroup members, who are perceived as tion in this literature is quadratic utility—alternatives largely homogenous (Ostrom and Sedikides, 1992). become worse with the square of the distance from Moreover, psychologists like Nosofsky (1986) have one’s ideal point (Austen-Smith and Banks 1988; explicitly linked discrimination ability to the framing Baron 1994; Martin 2001). Quadratic utility func- effects observed by Tversky (1977)—they argue that tions are mathematically convenient for finding equi- the frame serves to focus attention on similar out- libria since they differentiate to linear functions, comes, which makes it harder to determine differ- making optimization easy. A related but more general ences in less similar outcomes. For these reasons, Poole risk assumption is that the utility function is concave (2005) argues that spatial utility functions should be in the distance from the ideal point (Banks and Gaussian instead of quadratic because they are more Duggan 2000; Huber and McCarty 2001; Weingast consistent with evidence from the psychological lit- 1989). This form is convenient because the sum of erature on discriminant ability. two concave functions must also be concave, mean- The convexity at the extreme of the spatial utility ing proofs of equilibrium existence can be supported function invalidates the proofs of several important by several theorems related to concavity (like the spatial models, most notably models of party com- single-crossing property). petition (Downs 1957; Roemer 2001; Wittman 1977). However, these gains in tractability come at a In particular, Roemer (2001) compares standard price. Prospect and optimal foraging theories suggest models and notes that the assumption that parties that spatial utility is neither quadratic nor concave. care only about winning office generates an unreal- Individuals concerned with survival are likely to be istic equilibrium—namely, both parties in a two- risk averse when the alternatives are close enough to party system will offer exactly the same policy to the the ideal to guarantee staying alive. However, if the voters. As a consequence, he infers that parties must alternatives are farther away, survival may depend on also care about policy since models that make this accepting a risky alternative. At a certain extreme, assumption are able to generate equilibria in which alternatives may be so distant that none yield a sig- the two parties offer different policies. However, nificant improvement in survival, even if the alter- natives themselves are quite distant from one 4Tversky and Kahneman (1992) developed a version of prospect another. In other words, at a certain point individuals theory, called cumulative prospect theory, that allowed endpoints to converge. This theoretical model does not affect the exper- will be indifferent between a very distant alternative imental findings which demonstrate clear deviation around the and a very, very distant alternative. In prospect theory endpoints. on the evolutionary origin of prospect theory preferences 345 suppose voters have Gaussian instead of quadratic For example, in one well-known article, Fearon utility functions. If so, then some extremists may be considers two nation-states that must decide between alienated and may choose to abstain instead of voting engaging in a costly war and arriving at a negotiated for the closest moderate party—in essence, they stay settlement. He shows that there always exists a home because ‘‘there’s not a dime’s worth of differ- negotiated settlement that both sides will prefer, as ence’’ between the two parties (Adams, Dow, and long as the range of possible settlements is continu- Merrill 2006). Knowing this, the parties have an ous, the two nation-states share a common belief incentive to shift their policies towards their ‘‘base’’— about the probability of who will win the war, and even if they are purely office seeking (Adams and they are both risk averse (or risk neutral). As a result, Merrill 2003). he argues against ‘‘the conventional view that rational In another theory of party competition, Alesina states can and often do face a situation of , and Rosenthal (1995) develop an elaborate ‘‘electoral in which war occurs because no mutually preferable balancing’’ explanation for why the President’s party bargain exists’’ (1995, 409). What Fearon does not tends to lose seats in midterm elections. This explan- consider is the relationship between the territory or ation relies on sophisticated coordination strategies power under dispute and a nation’s or a leader’s among moderate risk-neutral voters who split their survival. When the negotiated settlement puts survival ticket and then switch their vote at the midterm if at risk, a war—even one with a lower expected value their preferred candidate for President loses. In con- than the negotiated settlement—may be preferable. trast, Patty (2006) shows that the simple assumption Fearon explains his choice to assume risk aversion: of prospect theory preferences implies that abstaining ‘‘In effect, the assumption means that leaders do not supporters of the losing party in the Presidential like gambling when the downside risk is losing at war, election will have a greater incentive than those who which seems plausible given the presumption that state won to cover their loss by showing up to vote in the leaders normally wish to retain territory and power. A risk-acceptant leader is analogous to a compulsive midterm election. gambler—willing to accept a sequence of gambles that Thus, prospect theory helps to simplify key has the expected outcome of eliminating the state and problems in American politics by generating results regime. Even if we admitted such a leader as rational, it that are consistent with party behavior (policy di- seems doubtful that many have held such preferences vergence) and voter behavior (abstention due to (Hitler being a possible exception).’’ (388) alienation, voting against the President’s party) that However, prospect theory and the model presented in flow directly from a widely tested and plausible as- this article suggest that we should expect the same sumption about risk. We acknowledge that there are decision makers to be risk averse when survival is many alternative hypotheses that explain alienation, assured and risk acceptant when it is not, helping to divergence, and midterm loss, but if these theories are explain the Hitler exception along with many im- based on quadratic or quasi-concave spatial utility portant others (Stalin, Mao, etc.). Therefore, a proper functions then they, too, are suspect. It may make model of international conflict should be based not sense to assume such preferences when we expect the only on the individual characteristics of the decision issue domain to be narrow around ideal points or maker (s), but also on the context of the conflict. to have little effect on the survival of groups or in- Indeed, one of the insights provided by prospect dividuals, but not for big issue spaces with broad theory highlights the central influence of the situation implications. Thus, models that assume strict risk on the risk propensity of any given leader. The aversion or neutrality may miss out on the oppor- interpretation and perception of that environment tunity to answer questions about the most important may differ across individual leaders (i.e., the point at problems in American Politics. which he understands his survival to be at risk), but the importance of such variables on choice remains critical and constant. Many international conflicts— Conflict Models in International Relations in fact, our most important ones—have threatened survival, placing decisions in the domain of losses Some important models in international relations and giving leaders and peasants alike an incentive to take account of prospect theoretic type preferences gamble to stay alive, remain in power, or to keep (Jervis, 2004). However, in many analytic models of their nations safe (Downs and Rocke 1995; Popkin international security, the nation-states (or their 1979). Under this assumption, Fearon’s model gen- leaders) are assumed to be risk averse or risk neutral, erates a conclusion opposite to the one he drew: some and this assumption drives some important results. conflicts are actually intractable. 346 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov

The positive and normative implications of pros- Many extant theories have difficultly accounting pect theory preferences for international relations are for risky actions such as these on the part of leaders, tremendous. Although scholars like Fearon make much less explaining widespread support for such substantive claims about the assumption of risk action. For example, some rational choice models aversion, one of the main reasons analytic modelers assume widespread risk aversion, suggesting that assume it is for the sake of mathematical convenience. leaders will eschew radical reform because they fear Risk aversion implies concavity in utility functions, such policies will lead to their eminent electoral failure and a number of general results about concavity (Ames, 1987; Geddes, 1995; Remmer, 1991). Similarly, help to ensure the existence of a unique equilibrium. rational choice theorists argue that popular groups or However, this is a costly assumption to make if it leaders will capitulate immediately to the pressures of affects inferences. Prospect theory and optimal forag- popular opposition and stop or refuse reform in order ing theory suggest that we should not treat the conflict to avoid the political costs inevitably associated with between and Palestine as though it were equiv- further economic decline (Alesina and Prelec 1991). alent to the soft lumber dispute between Canada and Such arguments extend beyond the area of neo- the . If parties to the Arab-Israeli conflict liberal economic reform into the realm of explaining see their survival at stake, then a mutually acceptable public support for economic stabilization as well. alternative to war may not exist. Rodrik (1994), for example, argues that voters will Our perspective remains quite consistent, how- eventually prefer the benefits of preventing or ameli- ever, with sophisticated rational choice arguments orating a severe economic crisis over the distribu- comparing regime type and political accountability in tional costs which triggered previous opposition to explaining the survival of political leaders in office structural economic reform. Similarly, Przeworski (Bueno de Mesquita and Siverson, 1995). Bueno de (1991) must implicitly assume risk acceptant policy Mesquita et al. (1999, 2002, 2005) seek to account for makers and publics in his rational choice explanation these observed differences in political survival and for the pace of economic readjustment and stabiliza- war by examining the basis and nature of resource tion. Although the uncertain nature of such reforms allocation. A democratic leader must rely on large suggests that the structure of economic incentives winning coalition to remain in power while an author- drives politicians to enact radical economic reforms itarian leader depends on a much smaller ‘‘selectorate’’ quickly, it still leaves such politicians vulnerable to to retain political viability. Most leaders are reluctant public and electoral protest. Note that the implicit risk to accept a sure loss to their own political power and acceptance in this model diverges from the implicit risk thus are willing to take risky actions such as war to aversion assumed by other rational choice models in avoid such a loss. This view provides an empirical this debate (Geddes 1995). demonstration of the risk-sensitive nature of political More recent arguments focus on switching strat- decision making; when political or physical survival is egies employed by Latin American politicians (Stokes threatened, leaders appear much more likely to engage 2001) which are consistent with the prospecting in risky actions like war. model we present here. In discussing how politicians invoke a switching strategy between efficacy-oriented Models of Economic Development and or welfare oriented policies, Stokes argues that un- Reform in Comparative Politics popular policies are often best for the welfare of constituents, and thus for the long-term political An important topic that has recently captured the interests of their representatives. attention of many scholars in comparative politics is Indeed, such prospect-oriented risk propensities the decision by some leaders to implement radical have been demonstrated among many states and polit- economic reform, particularly in areas struggling ical leaders in Latin American and Eastern Europe with economic development and democratization. (Weyland 1996, 1998). For instance, Weyland (1996) From Latin America to Eastern Europe, leaders like demonstrates how leaders facing economic crisis in Alberto Fujimori in Peru institute bold economic Argentina, Brazil, and Peru enacted bold, risky, and reforms with severe costs for the population and, costly strategies which elicited strong popular support. surprisingly, receive widespread support for such By contrast, leaders in Chile pursued more cautious action. Similarly, leaders such as Boris Yeltsin in policies while facing better economic prospects. In Russia and Vaclav Klaus in the Czech Republic were later work, Weyland (1998) employed prospect theory reelected despite instituting costly economic adjust- to examine the stages of economic reform and ment plans. stabilization in a large number of countries within on the evolutionary origin of prospect theory preferences 347

Latin America, Africa, and Eastern Europe. His argu- In other words, the prospector will make a risky choice ments demonstrate that prospect preferences can only when such an option offers a higher probability explain both why politicians may enact costly reform of survival. As the environment becomes more certain policies and why they receive high levels of popular or more abundant, prospectors become more cautious. support for these strategies when people exist at near- Importantly, the relative survival benefit for prospectors subsistence levels. This model also explains why such depends on environmental uncertainty; further, one policies do not find as much support in relatively more would expect such prospect theory tendencies in risk stable such as Chile. It also provides a propensity to manifest most strongly in the arena of coherent explanation for why leaders and publics may life and death decisions. shift from avoiding the risk of economic stabilization This evolutionary model, while specifically de- policies to accepting this risk. Thus, prospect prefer- signed to provide an explanation for the origins of ences provide a more comprehensive and parsimo- prospect-type preferences, may also possibly serve to nious model than the extant rational choice models to inform the origin of preferences from within more explain this wide variety of approaches to reform normative models such as subjective expected utility across many regions of the world. theory. While most rational choice theorists remain uninterested in explaining the origins of preferences, accepting them as exogenous, evolutionary models Conclusion provide helpful cues for the development of particular tastes. For example, humans evolved to prefer meat Adapting a model from optimal foraging theory, we and high sugar, high-fat tastes because of their caloric have demonstrated how risk seeking in losses and risk value. Individuals who partook of such foods clearly aversion in gains can represent an optimal strategy avoided starvation at a higher rate than those who did for a person evolved to maximize his prospects for not. But such foods were rare in the environment in survival in environments that vary between abun- which humans evolved; meat was scarce and largely dance and scarcity over time. These strategies repre- lean, while most sugar came from fruit and honey and sent an important element of human cognitive most fat derived from nuts. Having such food prefer- hardware for solving adaptive problems related to ences in the current context of fattened beef and risk taking under uncertainty. We suggest this kind of processed sugars and fats often leads to bad health risk propensity operates as an evolutionary module in outcomes. Similarly, political strategies which proved human psychological architecture. Environmental effective in small hunter-gatherer bands may not prove contingencies cue particular responses in automatic as adaptive today within the context of larger social ways; abundance leads to caution, while scarcity groups with more diverse interests and goals. provokes risk. Further evidence in support of this To be clear, we are not arguing only that under- innate bias comes from primates who demonstrate standing the sources of preferences can be interesting similar tendencies in experimental contexts (Chen, in its own right, although we believe that to be the Lakshminarayanan, and Santos 2006; Brosnan et al. case. Rather, we are emphasizing the fact that such an 2007). evolutionary origin for prospect theory type prefer- Our model demonstrates ecological rationality, or ences, particularly contingent on and how prospectors can do better over the long term, thus contingencies surrounding survival, holds significant providing an evolutionary fitness advantage that implications for human decision making and behav- would be passed along to descendants. If bold indi- ior. Prospect theory represents more than a bag of viduals always make the risky choice, they will do cognitive biases without rhyme or reason; in our better in environments of scarcity; if meek individuals view, it represents a comprehensive module of human always take the safe option, they will do better when preference concerning risk. Such a module, with roots times are abundant. If the best survival strategy deep in human evolutionary history, aided chances for changes depending on shifting environmental contin- survival, and would prove highly resistant to change or gencies, then prospectors are most likely to prevail learning through experience or education over time. under conditions of uncertainty, as we see in the It would not be easily corrected by policymakers, classic prospect theory curve. Uncertain environments but, when harnessed properly, could quickly and naturally select for individuals who prefer high-var- efficiently be manipulated by sophisticated leaders iance payoffs, even when such outcomes offer lower to encourage those whose survival felt threatened expected value. Such individuals take risks when their to support risky policies. In this way, we argue that survival is threatened, and otherwise they play it safe. the evolutionary origins of prospect theory preferences 348 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov hold profound implications for decision-making Adams, James, and Samuel Merrill. 2003. ‘‘Voter Turnout and analysis. Candidate Strategies in American Elections.’’ Journal of Politics 65 (1): 161–89. Prospect theory was developed through a series of Aktipis, C.A., and Robert Kurzban. 2004. ‘‘Is elegant empirical demonstrations conducted by Daniel Extinct? Vernon Smith, Daniel Kahneman and the Evolu- Kahneman and Amos Tversky. Prospect theory be- tionary Perspective.’’ In Advances in Austrian Economics, ed. haviors have been typically presented through the R. Koppl. Elsevier: Amsterdam, 135–53. prism of —in fact, equated with Alesina, Alberto, and Drazen Prelec. 1991. ‘‘Why Are Stabiliza- tions Delayed?’’ American Economic Review 81 (5): 1170–88. irrationality (Kahneman and Tversky 1982). Human Alesina, Alberto, and Howard Rosenthal. 1995. Partisan Politics, cognitive modules, however, have been designed not Divided Government, and the Economy. New York: Cambridge for economic rationality in a consumer environment University Press. of abundance, but for ‘‘hot ’’ to respond to Ames,B.1987.Political Survival. Berkeley: University of California ‘‘crucial events related to survival and reproduction’’ Press (Kenrick, Sadalla, and Keefe 1998, 488). In this respect, Andreoni, James. 1990. ‘‘Impure Altruism and Donations to Public Goods; A Theory of Warm Glow Giving’’ Economic psychological biases helping individual survival are Journal 100 (401): 464–77. ‘‘better than rational’’ (Cosmides and Tooby 1994). As Austen-Smith, David, and Jeffrey S. Banks. 1988. ‘‘Elections, evolutionary psychologists further point out: ‘‘If hu- Coalitions, and Legislative Outcomes.’’ American Political mans had evolved in casinos where their winnings Science Review 82 (2): 405–22. translated into reproductive success, selection prob- Banks, Jeffrey S., and John Duggan. 2000. ‘‘A Bargaining Model ably would have eliminated the gambler’s fallacy. But of Collective Choice.’’ American Political Science Review 94 (1): 73–88. in the real world it often pays to behave as if the past Barkow, Jerome, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby. 1992. The and future are not independent’’ (Gaulin and McBur- Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of ney 2001, 175). In the real world it pays to be Culture. New York: Oxford University Press. adaptively rational; and if evolutionary advantage gives Baron, David P. 1994. ‘‘Electoral Competition with Informed and you advice different from the one suggested by logic— Uniformed Voters.’’ American Political Science Review 88 (1): 33–47. then you will be ‘‘worse for the logic’’ (Fox 1992). Baron, David P., and John A. Ferejohn. 1989. ‘‘Bargaining in Human , therefore, enable us ‘‘to make Legislatures.’’ American Political Science Review 83 (4): reasonable decisions and behave adaptively in our 1181–1206. environment—Homo sapiens would be lost without Bell, Alison. 2007. ‘‘Animal Personalities.’’ Nature 447 (31): them’’ (Gigerenzer 1999, 29). 539–40. The authors of prospect theory and most of their Berejikian, Jeffrey D. 1997. ‘‘The Gains Debate: Framing State followers did not need or provide an evolutionary Choice.’’ American Political Science Review 91 (4): 789–805. Berejikian, Jeffrey D. 2002. ‘‘A Cognitive Theory of Deterrence.’’ perspective to explain or justify their findings. How- Journal of Peace Research 39 (2): 165–83. ever, such a link provides a comprehensive and Black, Duncan. 1958. The Theory of Committees and Elections. consistent explanation for the evolution of such Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. risk-taking propensities, pointing to their innate Boehm, Christopher. 1999. Hierarchy in the Forest: The Evolution basis. Optimal foraging theory explains why evolved of Egalitarian Behavior. Cambridge: Press. sensitivity to probability and variance, within the Bolton, Gary, and A. Ockenfels. 2000. ‘‘ERC: A Theory of Equity, context of particular needs and environmental con- Reciprocity, and Competition.’’ American Economic Review 90 (1): 166–93. tingencies, proves a quite ecologically rational strat- Brickman, Philip, and Donald Campbell. 1971. ‘‘Hedonic Rela- egy. If our analysis for the origins of such preferences tivism and Planning the Good Society.’’ In Adaptation Level is correct, eliminating such biases in judgment and Theory: A Symposium, ed. M.H. Apley. New York: Academic decision making will prove even more challenging, Press, 287–302. and unlikely, than previously assumed. Brosnan, Sarah F., Owen D. Jones, Susan P. Lambeth, Mary C. Mareno, Amanda S. Richardson, and Steven J. Schapiro. 2007. ‘‘Endowment Effects in Chimpanzees.’’ Current Biology 17 Manuscript submitted 17 April 2007 (19): 1704–1707. Manuscript accepted for publication 16 July 2007 Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, and Randolph Siverson. 1995. ‘‘War and Survival of Political Leaders: A Comparative Study of Regime Types and Political Accountability.’’ American Polit- References ical Science Review 89 (4): 841–55. Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James Morrow, Randolph Siverson, and Alastair Smith. 1999. ‘‘Policy Failure and Political Adams, James, James Dow, and Samuel Merrill. 2006. ‘‘The Survival.’’ Journal of Conflict Resolution 43 (2): 147–61. Political Consequences of Alienation-Based and Indifference- Based Voter Abstention: Applications to Presidential Elec- Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James Morrow, Randolph Siverson, tions.’’ Political Behavior 28 (1): 65–86. and Alastair Smith. 2002. ‘‘Political Institutions, Policy on the evolutionary origin of prospect theory preferences 349

Choices and the Survival of Leaders.’’ British Journal of Gigerenzer, Gerd. 1996. ‘‘On Narrow Norms and Vague Heu- Political Science 32 (4): 559–90. ristics: A Reply to Kahneman and Tversky.’’ Psychological Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce, James Morrow, Randolph Siverson, Review 103 (3): 592–96. and Alastair Smith. 2005. The Logic of Political Survival. Houston, Alasdair, John McNamara, and John Hutchinson. 1993. Cambridge: MIT Press. ‘‘General Results Concerning Trade-off between Gaining Caraco, Thomas. 1980. ‘‘On Foraging Time Allocation in a Energy and Avoiding Predation.’’ Philosophical Transactions of Stochastic Environment.’’ Ecology 61 (1): 199–28. the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 341 (1298): 375–97. Chen, Keith, Venkat Lakshminarayanan, and Laurie Santos. 2006. ‘‘How Basic Are Behavioral Differences? Evidence from Huber, John D., and Nolan McCarty. 2001. ‘‘Cabinet Decision Capuchin Monkey Trading Behavior.’’ Journal of Political Rules and Political Uncertainty in Parliamentary Bargaining.’’ Economy 114 (3): 517–37. American Political Science Review 95 (2): 345–60. Chomsky, Noam. 1956. ‘‘Three Models for the Description of Jervis, Robert. 1994. ‘‘Political Implications of Loss Aversion.’’ In Language.’’ IRE Transactions on Information Theory IT 2 (3): Avoiding Losses/Taking Risks: Prospect Theory in International 13–54. Politics, ed. Barbara Farnham. Ann Arbor: Press, 23–40. Cosmides, Leda, and John Tooby. 1994. ‘‘Better than Rational: Evolutionary Psychology and the Invisible Hand.’’ American Jervis, Robert. 2004. ‘‘The Implications of Prospect Theory for Hu- Economic Review 84 (2): 327–32. man Nature and Values.’’ 25 (2): 163–76. Cosmides, Leda, and John Tooby. 1996. ‘‘Are Humans Good Kahneman, Daniel, , and Amos Tversky (Eds.). 1982. Intuitive Statisticians After All? Rethinking Some Conclusions Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. New York: from the Literature on Judgment under Uncertainty.’’ Cogni- Cambridge University Press. tion 58 (1): 1–73. Kahneman, Daniel, and Amos Tversky. 1979. ‘‘Prospect Theory: Davis, Otto, M.J. Hinich, and P.C. Ordeshook, 1970. ‘‘An An Analysis of Decision Making Under Risk.’’ Expository Development of a Mathematical Model of the 47 (2): 263–91. Electoral Process.’’ American Political Science Review 64 (2): Kenrick, D., E. Sadalla, and R. Keefe. 1998. ‘‘Evolutionary 426–48. : The Missing Heart of Modern Cognitive Dawes, Christopher T., James H. Fowler, Tim Johnson, Richard Science.’’ In Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology,ed.C. McElreath, and Oleg Smirnov. 2007. ‘‘Egalitarian Motives in Crawford and D. Krebs. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum, 485–514. Humans.’’ Nature 446 (7137): 794–96. Kuhberger, Anton, Michael Schulte-Mecklenbeck, and Josef Dingemanse, Niels, and Denis Reale. 2005. ‘‘Natural Selection Perner. 1999. ‘‘The Effects of Framing, Reflection, Probability, and Animal Personality.’’ Behavior 142 (9-10): 1159–1184. and Payoff on Risk Preferences in Choice Tasks.’’ Organiza- tional Behavior and Human Decision Making Processes 78 (3): Downs, Anthony. 1957. An Economic Theory of Democracy. New 204–31. York: Harper Collins. Lau, Richard R., and David P. Redlawsk. 2001. ‘‘Advantages and Downs, George, and David Rocke. 1995. Optimal Imperfection. Disadvantages of Cognitive Heuristics in Political Decision Princeton: Press. Making.’’ American Journal of Political Science 45 (4): 951–71. Druckman, James N. 2001. ‘‘The Implications of Framing Effects Levy, Jack. 1994. ‘‘Prospect Theory and International Relations: for Citizen Competence.’’ Political Behavior 23 (3): 225–56. Theoretical Applications and Analytical Problems.’’ In Avoid- Elms, Deborah. 2004. ‘‘Large Costs, Small Benefits: Explaining ing Losses/Taking Risks: Prospect Theory in International Politics, Trade Dispute Outcomes.’’ Political Psychology 25 (2): 241–70. ed. Barbara Farnham. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, Faber, Jan. 1990. ‘‘On Bounded Rationality and the Framing of 119–46. Decision in International Relations: Towards a Dynamic Levy, Jack. 1997. ‘‘Prospect Theory, Rational Choice, and Network Model of World Politics.’’ Journal of Peace Research International Relations.’’ International Studies Quarterly 27 (3): 307–19. 41 (1): 87–112. Fagley, N.S., and Paul Miller. 1997. ‘‘Framing Effects and Arenas of Martin, Andrew D. 2001. ‘‘Congressional Decision Making and Choice: Your Money or Your Life?’’ Organizational Behavior the Separation of Powers.’’ American Political Science Review and Human Decision Making Processes 71 (3): 355–73. 95 (2): 361–78. Fearon, James. 1995. ‘‘Rationalist Explanations for War.’’ Inter- McDaniel, William C., and Francis Sistrunk. 1991. ‘‘Management national Organization 49 (3): 379–414. Dilemmas and Decisions: Impact of Framing and Anticipated Fehr, E., and K.M. Schmidt. 1999. ‘‘A Theory of Fairness, Responses.’’ Journal of Conflict Resolution 35 (1): 21–42. Competition, and Cooperation.’’ Quarterly Journal of Economics McDermott, Rose. 1998. Risk Taking in International Politics: 114 (3): 817–68. Prospect Theory in American Foreign Policy. Ann Arbor: Fitch, Tecumsuh, Marc Hansen, and . 2005. University of Michigan Press. ‘‘Evolution and the Language Facility: Clarifications and McDermott, Rose. 2004. "Prospect Theory in Political Science: Implications.’’ Cognition 97 (2): 179–210. Gains and Losses from the First Decade.’’ Political Psychology Fox, Robin. 1992. ‘‘Prejudice and the Unfinished Mind: A New 25 (2): 289–312. Look at an Old Failing.’’ Psychological Inquiry 3 (2): 137–52. McNeil, B., S. Pauker, H. Sox, and Amos Tversky. 1982. ‘‘On the Frederick, Shane. 2005. ‘‘Cognitive Reflection and Decision Elicitation of Preferences for Alternative Therapies.’’ New Making.’’ Journal of Economic Perspectives 19 (4): 24–42. England Journal of Medicine 306 (21): 1259–62. Gaulin, Steven J.C., and Donald H. McBurney. 2001. Psychology: Mercer, Jonathan. 2005. ‘‘Prospect Theory and Political Science.’’ An Evolutionary Approach. Prentice-Hall. Annual Review of Political Science 8 : 1–25. Geddes, Barbara. 1995. ‘‘Uses and Limitations of Rational Nosofsky, R.M. 1986. ‘‘Attention, Similarity, and the Identifica- Choice.’’ In Latin American Comparative Perspectives, ed. tion-Categorization Relationship.’’ Journal of Experimental P. Smith. Boulder: Westview Press, 81–108. Psychology-General 115 (1): 39–57. 350 rose mcdermott, james fowler, and oleg smirnov

Ostrom, T.M., and C. Sedikides. 1992. ‘‘Out-group Homogeneity Stokes, Susan. 2001. Mandates and Democracy. Cambridge: Effects in Natural and Minimal Groups.’’ Psychological Bulletin Cambridge University Press. 112 (3): 536–52. Tooby, John, and Leda Cosmides. 1999. ‘‘Ecological Rationality Patty, John. 2006. ‘‘Loss Aversion, Presidential Responsibility and in a Modular Mind: Grounding Normative Theories in Midterm Congressional Elections.’’ Electoral Studies 25 (2): Adaptive Problems.’’ In Evolutionary Psychology: Foundational 227–47. Papers, ed. John Tooby and Leda Cosmides. Cambridge: MIT Popkin, Samuel. 1979. The Rational Peasant. Berkeley: University Press, 1–32. of California Press. Tversky, Amos. 1977. ‘‘Features of Similarity.’’ Psychological Przeworski, Adam. 1991. Democracy and the Market. Cambridge: Review 84 (4): 327–52. Cambridge University Press. Tversky, Amos, and Daniel Kahneman. 1981. ‘‘The Framing of Quattrone, George A., and Amos Tversky. 1988. ‘‘Contrasting Decisions and the Psychology of Choice.’’ Science 211 (4481): Rational and Psychological Analyses of Political Choice.’’ 453–58. American Political Science Review 82 (3): 719–36. VanOers, Kees, Gerdren Jong, Arie van Noordwijk, B. Kempenaers Rabin, Matthew. 1993. ‘‘Incorporating Fairness into Game and Pieter Drent. 2005. ‘‘Contributions of Genetics to the Study Theory and Economics.’’ American Economic Review 83 (5): of Animal Personalities: A Review of the Case Studies.’’ 1281–1302. Behavior 142 (9–10): 1185–1206. Rabin, Matthew. 2002. ‘‘A Perspective on Psychology and Vogt, Paul. 2005. ‘‘Language Acquisition and Evolution.’’ Adap- Economics.’’ European Economic Review 46 (4-5): 657–85. tive Behavior 13 (4): 265–68. Remmer, Karen. 1991. ‘‘Political Impact of Economic Crisis in Weingast, Barry R. 1989. ‘‘Floor Behavior in the U.S. Congress: Latin America in the 1980s.’’ American Political Science Review Committee Power under the Open Rule.’’ American Political 85 (3): 777–800. Science Review 83 (3): 795–815. Rode, Catrin, Leda Cosmides, Wolfgang Hell, and John Tooby. Weyland, Kurt. 1996. ‘‘Risk Taking in Latin American Economic 1999. ‘‘When and Why Do People Avoid Unknown Proba- Restructuring: Lessons From Prospect Theory.’’ International bilities Under Uncertainty? Testing Some Predictions from Studies Quarterly 40 (2): 185–207. Optimal Foraging Theory.’’ Cognition 72 (3): 269–304. Weyland, Kurt. 1998. ‘‘The Political Fate of Market Reform in Rodrik, Dani. 1994. ‘‘The Rush to Free Trade in the Developing Latin America, Africa, and Eastern Europe.’’ International World.’’ In Voting for Reform, ed. Stephen Haggard and Studies Quarterly 42 (4): 645–73. S. Webb. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 61–88. Wittman, Donald. 1977. ‘‘Platforms with Policy Preferences: A Roemer, John E. 2001. Political Competition: Theory and Appli- Dynamic Model.’’ Journal of Economic Theory 14 (1): 180–89. cations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Wolf, Max, G. Sander van Doorn, Olof Leimar, and Franz Shepard, Roger N. 1962. ‘‘The Analysis of Proximities—Multi- Weissing. 2007. ‘‘Life-History Trade-offs Favour the Evolu- dimensional-Scaling with an Unknown Distance Function.’’ tion of Animal Personalities.’’ Nature 447 (31): 581–85. Psychometrica 27 (2): 125–40. Yamazato, M. 1978. ‘‘Unimodality of Infinitely Divisible Shepard, Roger N. 1987. ‘‘Toward a Universal Law of General- Distribution Functions of Class-L.’’ Annals of Probability ization for Psychological Science.’’ Science 237 (4820): 1317–23. 6 (4): 523–31. Simon, Herbert. 1985. ‘‘Human Nature in Politics: The Dialogue of Psychology with Political Science.’’ American Political Rose McDermott is associate professor of political Science Review 79 (2): 293–304. science, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA Skinner, B.F. 1953. Science and Human Behavior. New York: 92106. James H. Fowler is associate professor of Macmillan. political science, University of California at San Diego, Stephens, D.W. 1981. ‘‘The Logic of Risk-Sensitive Foraging Preferences.’’ Animal Behaviour 29 (2): 628–29. San Diego, CA 92093. Oleg Smirnov is assistant Stephens, D.W., and J.R. Krebs. 1986. Foraging Theory. Princeton: professor of political science, State University of Princeton University Press. New York at Stony Brook, Stony Brook, NY 11794.