Philosophical Pursuit and Flight: Homer and Thucydides in Plato's

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophical Pursuit and Flight: Homer and Thucydides in Plato's The International Journal The International Journal of the of the Platonic Tradition 8 (2014) 72-91 Platonic Tradition brill.com/jpt Philosophical Pursuit and Flight: Homer and Thucydides in Plato’s Laches1 Steve Maiullo Hope College, Holland, Michigan, USA [email protected] Abstract This paper offers a new reading of Plato’s Laches that examines the dialogue’s philo- sophical approach not only to courage but also to two literary texts that both formed and questioned traditional Athenian views of it: Homer and Thucydides. In the middle of Plato’s Laches, the eponymous character claims that the courageous man “should be willing to stay in formation, to defend himself against the enemy, and to refuse to run away.” Socrates responds by wondering whether a man can be courageous in retreat. He cites Homer’s description of Aeneas’ horses that “know how to pursue and flee quickly this way and that” (191b), a quotation that appears twice in the Iliad: once at 5.222-3 when Aeneas refuses to retreat from the rampaging Diomedes and again at 8.106-8 when Diomedes retreats from Hector, despite their belief that to do so is cowardly. On the surface, it seems that the contexts of the Homeric line do not match Socrates’ argu- ment. This paper will argue that Socrates’ apparent ‘miscue’ is both intentional and pur- poseful because it signals a correspondence between the Homeric scenes and Thucydides’ narrative of the Battle of Mantinea that invites criticism of Homer’s place in the value systems of contemporary Athens. Plato signals a philosophical reading of Homer’s Iliad and of Thucydides’ description of the Battle of Mantinea, through which we are invited to evaluate not only the traditional model of Athenian education, 1 Versions of this paper were read in April 2009 at the Annual Meeting of the Classical Association of the Middle West and South in Minneapolis, MN and in March 2011 at the Annual Meeting of the Classical Association of New England at Mt. Holyoke College. I have profited greatly from the comments, questions, and suggestions of both audiences. I also owe a debt of gratitude to Anna Peterson and Anthony Kaldellis whose insightful criticisms of earlier drafts have clarified my language and argument. © maiullo, ���� | doi ��.����/��������-�������� This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial 3.0. Unported (CC BY-NC 3.0) License, http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/ brill.com/jpt Downloaded from Brill.com10/03/2021 03:00:00AM via free access Philosophical Pursuit and Flight 73 embodied by the former, but also its application in fifth-century Athens, as revealed by the latter. This paper, therefore, demonstrates that the philosophical and literary strate- gies behind Plato’s decision to ‘misuse’ Homer reveal a disjunction between wisdom and manliness in the Athenian cultural tradition that philosophy aims to resolve. Keywords Plato – Homer – Thucydides – Laches – Battle of Mantinea – courage – virtue – misquotation – poetry – history Introduction The last quarter century has witnessed a sea change in Platonic scholarship that has raised the consideration of the literary and rhetorical features of the dialogues—studies of character, setting, and genre, to name a few—to the same level as what used to be regarded the ‘strictly’ philosophical.2 New approaches have advanced our understanding of Plato’s corpus as a whole and his philosophical project in general, as well as of individual dialogues.3 One dialogue that has particularly benefited from new approaches is Plato’s Laches, which was originally viewed as one of the earliest and, in some cases, most awk- ward of Plato’s definition dialogues.4 It was counted among the early dialogues because it shares many elements in common with other so-called early defini- tion dialogues: it is concerned with the virtues—in this case, andreia (‘manly courage’)—and their possible unity; it advances a series of definitions that are tested and ultimately rejected; it ends in aporia; and it lays the groundwork for proper education of the youth, to name a few.5 It was considered clumsy, 2 For a synthesis of how Plato has been read over the last two centuries by philosophers, see A. Bowen (1988) 49-65. Whereas Plato’s readers have attempted to outline what he thought and believed by focusing on arguments, he concludes that readers cannot strip away the dramatic elements of the dialogues because they are crucial to their meaning. 3 For a representative list of these approaches, see C. Griswold (1999) 361 as well as C. Zuckert (2009) 1-47. 4 On the ‘primitive form’ of the dialogue, see W.K.C. Guthrie (1975) 124. 5 The scholarly literature on the Laches has focused primarily on virtue, with particular atten- tion to the unity of the virtues. See H. Bonitz (1871) 413-42; G. Santas (1969); M. O’Brien (1971) 303-25; D. Devereux (1992) 765-769; T. Penner (1992) 1-27; and T. Brickhouse and N. Smith (1997) 317-324. The different definitions of courage in the Laches have also been well studied. The International Journal of the Platonic TraditionDownloaded � ( from�0�� Brill.com10/03/2021) 7�-9� 03:00:00AM via free access 74 Maiullo moreover, because it takes so long for Socrates to enter, for the main problem to be outlined, and for the elenchos to begin.6 As an early and primitive dia- logue, the Laches was believed to express the historical Socrates’ beliefs about virtue.7 But other readers, focusing less on claims about its date of composition, have recognized the Laches as a dialogue of greater depth than previously thought.8 This case has been made largely through historical and literary analysis. Socrates’ main interlocutors in this dialogue were well-known Athenian politicians and generals, Laches and Nicias, and scholars have argued that Socrates interrogates both traditional and radical views about warfare and courage and their application in fifth-century Athens. The ‘histori- cal’ fatal character flaws of both Laches and Nicias—as recorded by the Greek historians themselves—are the very flaws that shape their initial views and then prevent their progress in the philosophical search for courage (on which more later).9 On this reading, in questioning Laches and Nicias, Socrates both questions traditional and sophistic notions of courage respectively and also See S. Umphrey (1976) 14-22 for the view that Laches’ definition is crucial to the Socratic understanding of courage. See C. Emlyn-Jones (1999) 123-138 for the view that the definitions represent a progression from less (those of Laches) to more (those of Nicias) sophisticated definitions of courage. For the relationship between courage and education, with emphasis on self-knowledge, see C. Griswold (1986) 177-93. 6 To put it in perspective, the dialogue begins at 178, Socrates does not enter until 181d, the main question is not formulated until 185a, and the testing of the question does not truly begin until 189e. Compare this with another early definition dialogue, the Euthyphro in which Socrates appears on the first page. For discussion, see C. Emlyn-Jones (1999) 123-30. 7 Because the text has been viewed as early, some historicists suggest that the understanding of virtue found in the Laches can be attributed to the historical Socrates. See, e.g., C. Gould (1987) 265-66 and D. Devereux (1992) 767. Scholars of this school generally follow the work of G. Vlastos (1991) 45-80, who argued that the Socrates of the early dialogues was the historical Socrates. 8 An account of the traditional ordering of the dialogues by stylometric analysis and the diffi- culty of ordering the early dialogues specifically can be found in L. Brandwood (1992) 90-120. The limitations of this kind of organization have been articulated, and scholars instead have offered thematic solutions. See, e.g., C. Kahn (1997) 48-59. An overview of thematic approaches taken to organize Plato’s corpus is given in D. Clay (2000) 283-86 and C. Zuckert (2009) 1-47, esp. 1-7. A full and certainly stimulating treatment of the topic is C. Griswold (1999). In fact, Zuckert’s project to treat the dialogues in order of dramatic date is suggested by Griswold (he call this “fictive chronology”), but this approach too has its own limitations. 9 My focus in this paper is on Laches, since it is in Socrates’ discussion with him that we find the Homeric misquotation, but for a good discussions of Nicias, see W. Schmid (1992) 132-176 and C. Zuckert (2009) 247-57. The International Journal of the PlatonicDownloaded Tradition from Brill.com10/03/2021 � (�0��) 7�-9 03:00:00AM� via free access Philosophical Pursuit and Flight 75 becomes a new paradigm for philosophical andreia himself.10 Plato, therefore, employs this tension between past and present views of courage to comment philosophically on the social, cultural, and political world of fifth-century Athens and to carve out Socrates’ place within it.11 Scholars have shown, more- over, the characters of Laches and Nicias in the dialogue represent parodies of their historical counterparts, particularly when Plato’s portrayal is compared with other sources, such as Thucydides and Aristophanes (and, to a lesser extent, Plutarch).12 Although literary approaches have allowed scholars to look beneath the Laches’ apparently simple exterior, the connections between Homer, Thucydides, and the Laches have not been fully explored or, for that matter, universally accepted.13 This paper seeks to present a new reading that shows how Plato connects Homeric and Thucydidean narratives with the philosophi- cal interactions between Socrates and Laches, the character around whom this tension exists most clearly and for whom the dialogue is titled.14 I will argue that probing Socrates’ (mis)quotations of Homer in the Laches reveals that this dialogue provides a philosophical approach not only to courage and virtue, as has been argued, but also to the literary texts that affirm and question tradi- tional Athenian value systems.
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ostensible Author of Ps.-Aeschines Letter 10 Reconsidered
    Journal of Hellenic Studies 139 (2019) 210–221 doi:10.1017/S0075426919000703 © The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies 2019 THE OSTENSIBLE AUTHOR OF PS.-AESCHINES LETTER 10 RECONSIDERED ZILONG GUO Northeast Normal University* Abstract: This article examines the alleged author, or first-person narrator, of the tenth pseudonymous letter in the Corpus Aeschineum. It argues that the forger, in a short epistolary novel that describes the seduction of a certain Callirhoe in Troy, uses puns (αἰσχύνειν, ἀναισχυντία, etc.) on the name of the fourth-century BC orator Aeschines. It notes that αἰσχρός-words recur in ancient works and, as a rhetorical device, are attested in Demosthenes. The forger’s aims are, first, to serialize the ‘Aeschinean’ letters as a whole by relating them to the same author and, second, to create an ‘aischro- logic’ counterpart of the Callirhoe, which is attributed to Chariton (Χαρίτων/‘The Graceful’). Thus there is less likelihood of suggesting other figures such as the eponymous Aeschines Socraticus. Keywords: pseudonymous letters, authorship, Aeschines, Chariton, pun In the manuscript tradition of Aeschines we find a collection of 12 letters that purport to describe the orator’s exile from Athens after the ‘crown trial’ in 330 BC. These letters are called ‘pseudony- mous’ because of their questionable authenticity: Letters 2, 3, 7, 11 and 12 imitate the letters of Demosthenes and are reminiscent of the historical declamations and progymnasmata familiar from Hellenistic times onward; Letters 1, 5, 6, 8, 9 and 10 reconstruct a fictitious narrative of Aeschines’ exile, and have traditionally been accepted as products of the so-called Second Sophistic.
    [Show full text]
  • Citations in Classics and Ancient History
    Citations in Classics and Ancient History The most common style in use in the field of Classical Studies is the author-date style, also known as Chicago 2, but MLA is also quite common and perfectly acceptable. Quick guides for each of MLA and Chicago 2 are readily available as PDF downloads. The Chicago Manual of Style Online offers a guide on their web-page: http://www.chicagomanualofstyle.org/tools_citationguide.html The Modern Language Association (MLA) does not, but many educational institutions post an MLA guide for free access. While a specific citation style should be followed carefully, none take into account the specific practices of Classical Studies. They are all (Chicago, MLA and others) perfectly suitable for citing most resources, but should not be followed for citing ancient Greek and Latin primary source material, including primary sources in translation. Citing Primary Sources: Every ancient text has its own unique system for locating content by numbers. For example, Homer's Iliad is divided into 24 Books (what we might now call chapters) and the lines of each Book are numbered from line 1. Herodotus' Histories is divided into nine Books and each of these Books is divided into Chapters and each chapter into line numbers. The purpose of such a system is that the Iliad, or any primary source, can be cited in any language and from any publication and always refer to the same passage. That is why we do not cite Herodotus page 66. Page 66 in what publication, in what edition? Very early in your textbook, Apodexis Historia, a passage from Herodotus is reproduced.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Athenian Democracy.Pdf
    Rethinking Athenian Democracy A dissertation presented by Daniela Louise Cammack to The Department of Government in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Political Science Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2013 © 2013 Daniela Cammack All rights reserved. Professor Richard Tuck Daniela Cammack Abstract Conventional accounts of classical Athenian democracy represent the assembly as the primary democratic institution in the Athenian political system. This looks reasonable in the light of modern democracy, which has typically developed through the democratization of legislative assemblies. Yet it conflicts with the evidence at our disposal. Our ancient sources suggest that the most significant and distinctively democratic institution in Athens was the courts, where decisions were made by large panels of randomly selected ordinary citizens with no possibility of appeal. This dissertation reinterprets Athenian democracy as “dikastic democracy” (from the Greek dikastēs, “judge”), defined as a mode of government in which ordinary citizens rule principally through their control of the administration of justice. It begins by casting doubt on two major planks in the modern interpretation of Athenian democracy: first, that it rested on a conception of the “wisdom of the multitude” akin to that advanced by epistemic democrats today, and second that it was “deliberative,” meaning that mass discussion of political matters played a defining role. The first plank rests largely on an argument made by Aristotle in support of mass political participation, which I show has been comprehensively misunderstood. The second rests on the interpretation of the verb “bouleuomai” as indicating speech, but I suggest that it meant internal reflection in both the courts and the assembly.
    [Show full text]
  • Read Ebook {PDF EPUB} Tides of War by Steven Pressfield ISBN 13: 9780553527315
    Read Ebook {PDF EPUB} Tides of War by Steven Pressfield ISBN 13: 9780553527315. Plutarch, Plato, and Thucydides have all immortalized Alcibiades (ca. 450-404 b.c.) as a peerless general and conqueror on sea and land, whom the tides of war and fortune always favored. Raised as a ward of Pericles, he was later a protégé of Socrates, and inevitably compared to the legendary Achilles. The destinies of Alcibiades and Athens were inextricably intertwined; the man and the city-state mirrored each other's boldness, ambition, and the fatal flaws that were their undoing. When allied, Alcibiades and Athens were unbeatable. When divided, he led Sparta and Persia to glory. At the end of his life, in exile from all factions, Alcibiades was shunned by his countrymen in their most desperate hour. Athens would rather fall than be led by its most brilliant leader. Narrated by Alcibiades' trusted bodyguard and hired assassin in a mesmerizing death-row confession, TIDES OF WAR is epic historical fiction at its finest--a full-bodied, flesh-and-blood retelling of one of history's pivotal conflicts. "synopsis" may belong to another edition of this title. After chronicling the Spartan stand at Thermopylae in his audacious Gates of Fire , Steven Pressfield once again proves that it's all Greek to him. In Tides of War , he tells the tale of Athenian soldier extraordinaire Alcibiades. Despite the vaunted claims for Periclean democracy, he is undoubtedly first among equals--a great warrior and an impressive physical specimen to boot: "The beauty of his person easily won over those previously disposed, and disarmed even those who abhorred his character and conduct." He is also a formidable orator, whose stump speeches are paradoxically heightened by what some might consider an impediment: As they were in his previous novel, Pressfield's battle scenes are extraordinarily vivid and visceral.
    [Show full text]
  • The Regime of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317–307
    Th e Regime of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317–307 BCE Mnemosyne Supplements History and Archaeology of Classical Antiquity Edited by Susan E. Alcock, Brown University Th omas Harrison, Liverpool Willem M. Jongman, Groningen H.S. Versnel, Leiden VOLUME 318 Th e Regime of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317–307 BCE A Philosopher in Politics By Lara O’Sullivan LEIDEN • BOSTON 2009 On the cover: Detail of the Parthenon. Photo: Author. Th is book is printed on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data O’Sullivan, Lara. Th e rule of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317-307 B.C. : a philosopher in politics / by Lara O’Sullivan. p. cm. — (Mnemosyne supplements. History and archaeology of classical antiquity, ISSN 0169-8958 ; v. 318) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-90-04-17888-5 (hbk. : alk. paper) 1. Demetrius, of Phaleron, b. ca. 350 B.C. 2. Demetrius, of Phaleron, b. ca. 350 B.C.—Political and social views. 3. Governors—Greece—Athens—Biography. 4. Statesmen—Greece—Athens— Biography. 5. Orators—Greece—Athens—Biography. 6. Philosophers, Ancient— Biography. 7. Athens (Greece)—Politics and government. 8. Philosophy, Ancient. 9. Athens (Greece)—Relations—Macedonia. 10. Macedonia—Relations—Greece— Athens. I. Title. II. Series. DF235.48.D455O87 2009 938’.508092—dc22 [B] 2009033560 ISSN 0169-8958 ISBN 978 90 04 17888 5 Copyright 2009 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, Th e Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Knowledge, Elenchus and Authority in Early Plato
    Phronesis 65 (2020) 247-280 brill.com/phro Self-Knowledge, Elenchus and Authority in Early Plato Fiona Leigh University College, London [email protected] Abstract In some of Plato’s early dialogues we find a concern with correctly ascertaining the contents of a particular kind of one’s own psychological states, cognitive states. Indeed, one of the achievements of the elenctic method is to facilitate cognitive self- knowledge. In the Alcibiades, moreover, Plato interprets the Delphic injunction, ‘know yourself’, as crucially requiring cognitive self-knowledge, and ending in knowing one- self as subject to particular epistemic norms. Epistemic authority for self-knowledge is, for Plato, conferred on the basis of correct application of norms to cognitive self- ascriptions, and not confined to the first-personal perspective. This implies first- personal plural epistemic authority for self-knowledge. Keywords self-knowledge – elenchus – epistemic authority – dialogue – Alcibiades – Apology – Laches – Gorgias 1 Introduction In contemporary discussions of the topic that has become known as ‘self- knowledge’, philosophers not infrequently ask whether knowing the contents of one’s own thought is like perception or something more distinctive and spe- cial, or worry about privileged access to one’s own states.1 By contrast, scholarly 1 See for example, Ryle 1949, ch. 6, Evans 1982, Boghossian 1989, Shoemaker 1994, Cassam 1994, O’Brien 2007, Gertler 2015. © Fiona Leigh, 2020 | doi:10.1163/15685284-bja10020 This is an open access article distributed
    [Show full text]
  • Athenian Homicide Rhetoric in Context
    ATHENIAN HOMICIDE RHETORIC IN CONTEXT BY CHRISTINE C. PLASTOW Thesis submitted to University College London for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy DEPARTMENT OF GREEK AND LATIN UNIVERSITY COLLEGE LONDON 1 DECLARATION I, Christine C. Plastow, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. Signed: --------------------------------------------------------------------------- 2 ABSTRACT Homicide is a potent crime in any society, and classical Athens was no exception. The Athenians implemented legal methods for dealing with homicide that were set apart from the rest of their legal system, including separate courts, long-established laws, and rigorous procedures. We have, however, limited extant sources on these issues, including only five speeches from trials for homicide. This has fomented debate regarding aspects of law and procedure, and rhetoric as it relates specifically to homicide has not been examined in detail. Here, I intend to examine how the nature of homicide and its prosecution at Athens may have affected rhetoric when discussing homicide in forensic oratory. First, I will establish what I will call the ideology of homicide at Athens: the set of beliefs and perceptions that are most commonly attached to homicide and its prosecution. Then, I will examine homicide rhetoric from three angles: religious pollution, which was believed to adhere to those who committed homicide; relevance, as speakers in the homicide courts were subject to particular restrictions in this regard; and motive and intent, related issues that appear frequently in rhetoric and, in some cases, define the nature of a homicide charge.
    [Show full text]
  • The Arousal of Emotion in Plato's Dialogues Author(S): David L. Blank Source: the Classical Quarterly, New Series, Vol
    The Arousal of Emotion in Plato's Dialogues Author(s): David L. Blank Source: The Classical Quarterly, New Series, Vol. 43, No. 2, (1993), pp. 428-439 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/639181 Accessed: 10/08/2008 13:36 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Classical Quarterly 43 (ii) 428-439 (1993) Printed in Great Britain 428 THE AROUSAL OF EMOTION IN PLATO'S DIALOGUES In Aeschines' dialogue Alcibiades, Socrates sees his brilliant young partner's haughty attitude towards the great Themistocles.
    [Show full text]
  • Illinoisclassica131988univ Bw 2.Pdf
    CI Otyi^^c^ ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XIIL2 FALL/1988 Miroslav Marcovich, Editor ISSN 0363-1923 2 ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XIII. Fall 1988 Miroslav Marcovich, Editor SCHOLARS PRESS ISSN 0363-1923 2 ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XIII. Plutarch The Board of Trustees University of Illinois Copies of the journal may be ordered from: Scholars Press Customer Services P. O. Box 6525 Ithaca, New York 14851 Printed in the U.S.A. 2 EDITOR Miroslav Marcovich CO-EDITORS OF ICS XIII. Frederick E. Brenk, S.J. (Rome) Jackson P. Hershbell (Minneapolis) Philip A. Stadter (Chapel Hill) ADVISORY EDITORIAL COMMITTEE John J. Bateman Howard Jacobson David F. Bright J. K. Newman Gerald M. Browne David Sansone CAMERA-READY COPY PRODUCED BY Mary Ellen Fryer Illinois Classical Studies is published semi-annually by Scholars Press. Camera-ready copy is edited and produced in the Department of the Classics, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Each contributor receives twenty-five offprints. Contributions should be addressed to: The Editor Illinois Classical Studies Department of the Classics 4072 Foreign Languages Building 707 South Mathews Avenue Urbana, Illinois 61801 PLUTARCH ROBERT FLACELERE (1904-1982) INMEMORIAM Preface The present issue oi ICS comprises the papers presented at the Conference of the International Plutarch Society held in the summer of 1987 at Athens. I have included the contributions by the scholars unable to attend the Athens Conference. In preparing the typescripts for publication I have been assisted by such renowned Plutarchean scholars as Fr. E. Brenk, S.J. (Rome), J. P. Hershbell (Minneapolis), and Ph. A. Stadter (Chapel Hill).
    [Show full text]
  • Tides of War Download Free
    TIDES OF WAR Author: Steven Pressfield Number of Pages: 608 pages Published Date: 05 Mar 2001 Publisher: Transworld Publishers Ltd Publication Country: London, United Kingdom Language: English ISBN: 9780553813326 DOWNLOAD: TIDES OF WAR Tides of War PDF Book Thanks for telling us about the problem. Attempting to out-maneuver Ferdinand, the French were unable to trap him but did capture the vital supply depot at Minden. In many ways this tragic story is one of great insight regarding the role heroes of the day play in our lives. No one knew someone that served in that war. I rated this as average based on the excellent historical background and insight it provides. Also, the book is way too long. A surgeon started the surgeries to help shrapnel victims with extreme facial injuries. Straight to your inbox. While George Bernard Shaw's masterpiece was, for him and me, Back to Methuselah , Pygmalion will always be the popular standout. Mar 22, Briana Patterson added it Shelves: abandoned-with-boredom-or-disgust. No trivia or quizzes yet. He is such a dynamic character that it is difficult to believe in the veracity of his existence and I am amazed that he is not a more notorious historical figure. How is it different from treason? In the Battle of Carillon , the British suffered over 1, casualties while French losses were fewer than There's a crisis for writers these days. Abigail Johnson, CEO of Fidelity Investments, on managing disruption through innovation, what's next for the financial services giant, and why Bitcoin matters and why it doesn't.
    [Show full text]
  • Women and Property in Ancient Athens: a Discussion of the Private Orations and Menander Cheryl Cox University of Memphis
    Women and Property in Ancient Athens: A Discussion of the Private Orations and Menander Cheryl Cox University of Memphis There has been a great deal of discussion in the past two decades or so among social historians and anthropologists of the proposition that women in European societies, both in the past and in the present, have informal power at the private level of the household. Women’s interests were reflected and expressed in succession practices and in the management of the household economy. Central to the status of women was the dowry because of its place in the conjugal household and the negotiations over its use and transmission. A large dowry ensured the woman’s important role in the decisions of the marital household and thus helped to stabilize the marriage. Because the dowry, as the property of the woman’s natal kin, would ideally be transmitted to the man’s children, the man could become involved in the property interests of his wife’s family of origin.1 In a material sense, in classical Athens the wife’s dowry allowed for the cohesion of two households (oikoi): the oikos of her marriage and that of her natal family. The dowry in legal terms belonged to the woman’s natal family, as it had to be returned to her family of origin either on divorce or on the death of her husband and her remarriage. Much of the information we have for dowries pertains to elite families. Because the woman’s dowry could be inherited by the children, it was worth fighting for, especially if she had not received her full share (Dem.
    [Show full text]