The Ostensible Author of Ps.-Aeschines Letter 10 Reconsidered

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Ostensible Author of Ps.-Aeschines Letter 10 Reconsidered Journal of Hellenic Studies 139 (2019) 210–221 doi:10.1017/S0075426919000703 © The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies 2019 THE OSTENSIBLE AUTHOR OF PS.-AESCHINES LETTER 10 RECONSIDERED ZILONG GUO Northeast Normal University* Abstract: This article examines the alleged author, or first-person narrator, of the tenth pseudonymous letter in the Corpus Aeschineum. It argues that the forger, in a short epistolary novel that describes the seduction of a certain Callirhoe in Troy, uses puns (αἰσχύνειν, ἀναισχυντία, etc.) on the name of the fourth-century BC orator Aeschines. It notes that αἰσχρός-words recur in ancient works and, as a rhetorical device, are attested in Demosthenes. The forger’s aims are, first, to serialize the ‘Aeschinean’ letters as a whole by relating them to the same author and, second, to create an ‘aischro- logic’ counterpart of the Callirhoe, which is attributed to Chariton (Χαρίτων/‘The Graceful’). Thus there is less likelihood of suggesting other figures such as the eponymous Aeschines Socraticus. Keywords: pseudonymous letters, authorship, Aeschines, Chariton, pun In the manuscript tradition of Aeschines we find a collection of 12 letters that purport to describe the orator’s exile from Athens after the ‘crown trial’ in 330 BC. These letters are called ‘pseudony- mous’ because of their questionable authenticity: Letters 2, 3, 7, 11 and 12 imitate the letters of Demosthenes and are reminiscent of the historical declamations and progymnasmata familiar from Hellenistic times onward; Letters 1, 5, 6, 8, 9 and 10 reconstruct a fictitious narrative of Aeschines’ exile, and have traditionally been accepted as products of the so-called Second Sophistic. Letter 4 is a prose paraphrase of Pindar’s victory odes.1 Among them, Letter 10 has occasioned extensive scholarly discussions. It is unique in resembling what scholars call Briefromane, or ‘epistolary novels’, in that the actual author mixes the theme of adventure with that of the passion of love in a manner similar to the ‘canonical’ novelists Chariton, Xenophon of Ephesus, Achilles Tatius, Longus and Heliodorus.2 Its centrepiece – the seduction of a certain Callirhoe by one Cimon in the guise of the river god Scamander (λαβέ μου, Σκάμανδρε, τὴν παρθενίαν, §§ 3, 5, 6) – holds a special position in classical literature as an outstanding example of the Milesian Tales alongside such Roman counterparts as the works of Petronius and Apuleius;3 the term has its origin in the now lost collection of erotic (if mostly salacious) stories attributed to Aristides of Miletus (ca. first century BC) and was first applied to the account of Letter 10 by Karl Dilthey.4 * [email protected]. I am grateful to the two 4; Reardon (2008) 9; Tilg (2010) 2. But the scandalous anonymous JHS readers for their excellent suggestions. element is more common in some fragmentary and Thanks are also due to Mirko Canevaro, Sven Günther ‘fringe’ novels: Stephens and Winkler (1995) 4–7. For and Qiang Zhang, as well as the Editor of JHS and my example, ὁ Σκάμανδρος Κίμων (§ 5), associating seduc- colleagues at the Institute for the History of Ancient Civi- tion with the theme of disguise, finds an echo in Iolaos’ lizations at Northeast Normal University for their novel (P.Oxy. 42.3010): Puiggali (1988) 34–35; generous help and advice on this article. Mignogna (1996) 318 n. 11. 1 See Reiske (1771) 650–55; Schäfer (1885–1887) 3 Cf., following the Latin adaptation by Lucius 3.292 n. 2; Blass (1887–1898) 3.2.185–86; Drerup Cornelius Sisenna (ca. 120–167 BC), Ov. Tr. 2.413–14, (1904) 51; Wilamowitz-Moellendorff (1905) 147–49; 443–44; Petron. Sat. 85, 111; Apul. Met. 1.1, 2.21, 4.32. On Schwegler (1913); Martin and de Budé (1927–1928) Sisenna’s work, see Aragosti (2000); on the Milesian Tales 2.121–22; Goldstein (1968) 7, 49 n. 70, 100, 128, 131– and Roman novels, see Lefèvre (1997); Jensson (2004); 32, 265–66, 284–86; Salomone (1985); Holzberg (1994) Harrison (2013) 57–68. Less established is the view that 17–22; Glaser (2009) 63–84. These are the subject of my Letter 10 exerted an influence over Petronius’ Satyricon: commentary on the epistolographic corpus that excludes Abbott (1911) 265–66; Konstan (1994) 122 n. 47. Letter 10: Guo (2018). 4 Dilthey (1863) 102 n. 1; see also Weinreich (1911) 2 Also known as the ‘big five’: Rohde (1960) chapter 37–38; Schwegler (1913) 17–18; Martin and de Budé Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Athens, on 02 Oct 2021 at 02:05:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0075426919000703 THE AUTHOR OF PS.-AESCHINES LETTER 10 RECONSIDERED 211 Such generic taxonomies notwithstanding, Letter 10 presents some thorny problems. The story takes place in Asia Minor, where Aeschines spent his exile according to the biographical tradition, but apart from its presence in the manuscripts there is no explicit sign of Aeschinean (or Ps.- Aeschinean) authorship.5 The author (or, as I shall argue, the forger) eschews any direct mention of Aeschines and all we have is little more than a first-person narrated erotic adventure with one Cimon.6 As a result, the ostensible author and the bewildering relation with the rest of the collection of letters have dominated previous scholarship on the letter. While some scholars connect it to the ‘Aeschinean’ letters, there has long been a tendency among others to treat it as a chance insertion that has nothing to do with the orator. Christoph Stöcker, for example, offers a novel interpretation of how it was misplaced in the process of transmission;7 that is, this letter was included erroneously in the epistolographic corpus, primarily due to a series of coincidences of names.8 He conjectures that the letter was addressed to the ‘Socratic’ Aeschines of Sphettus, supposedly by Stesimbrotus of Thasos in the mid-fifth century BC. The latter figure was an exegete of Homer and so expressed a keen interest in sightseeing around the heroes’ graves in Troy (§ 2).9 Cimon is identified with the distinguished Athenian statesman and general.10 Aeschines of Sphettus is as plausible a recipient here as he is in the ‘Socratic’ letters. He was supposed to know how to enjoy the charm of an erotic story as a result of his spiritual superiority, i.e. σὺ δὲ ἂν ἱκανῶς οἶμαι γελάσειας (‘I guess you would find it worth a laugh’, § 10).11 At the same time, since Callias, Cimon’s brother-in-law, is a recurrent figure in Aeschines of Sphettus’ works, it is plausible to establish a connection between this Aeschines and the Cimonian circle.12 The Melanippides that received the two travellers when they were chased by the Trojans (§ 10) would, then, be a Melian contemporary of Aeschines of Sphettus, i.e. Melanippides the dithyrambic poet.13 (1927–1928) 2.133 n. 1; Cataudella (1957) 107, 147–48; tigation of the manuscript tradition. A very different Rohde (1960) 596 n. 1; Lesky (1966) 608, 763; narrative order is represented by the 14th-century Salomone (1985) 232 n. 4; Puiggali (1988) 29–30; Stire- Harleianus 5610, which preserves only Letters 1, 6, 7 and walt (1993) 25 n. 74; Ferrari and Zanetto (1994) 77; 3, but the editio princeps of 1499 and two relevant manu- Gallé Cejudo (1996) 41, 43–44; Mignogna (1996) 86– scripts, Helmstadiensis 806/Guelferbytanus 902 and 87; Lefèvre (1997) 73–74; Benz (2001) 79–83; de Dios Laurentianus 70, 19, may offer evidence for a single (2002) 621 n. 37; Jensson (2004) 170; Bowie (2008) 21; point of origin of the pseudonymous letters, since the Hodkinson (2013) 323 n. 1; Giaquinta (2014) 9–10, 12– editor-scribes read ὁ δὲ Κίμων for ὁ δὴ Κίμων to mark 13, 25. Other notable Greek exponents are the Lucianic continuation: see Dobree (1831) 346; Drerup (1904) 30. Erotes and (probably) P.Oxy. 40.4762; generally on the 8 But this thesis seems rather farfetched to many Milesian Tales, see, for example, Ferrari and Zanetto scholars: for example Mignogna (1996) 316 n. 3: (1994); Benz (2001); Bowie (2013). ‘l’ipotesi tanto ingegnosa quanto poco convincente’. 5 Cf. Plut. Dem. 24.3; [Plut.] Mor. 840c–e; Philostr. 9 Cf. Stesimbrotus of Thasos BNJ 107 T 3 = Pl. Ion V S 1.481, 509; Phot. Bibl. 61.20a; Vitae Aeschin. 1.4–6, 530c–d. 2.12, 3.3–4 Dilts; P.Oxy. 15.1800. 10 As Stöcker points out, the forger may have based 6 For clarity, ‘first-person narrator’ (Ich-Erzähler) or his tale significantly upon Cimon’s unrestricted sexual simply ‘narrator’ are suitable alternatives to ‘author’ or life at an early age – for instance, the incestuous relation- ‘forger’ here, given that they are compatible in the ship with his sister Elpinice – which was probably known context of literary fabrication: cf. Stöcker (1980); Puig- to Stesimbrotus. Cf. SEG 46.79; Stesimbrotus of Thasos gali (1988) 30, 34; Ferrari and Zanetto (1994) 77; BNJ 107 T1, F4; Plut. Cim. 4.4–10, 15.4; Comp. Cim. Holzberg (1994) 19; Giaquinta (2014) 9 n. 4. Notice too Luc. 1.7; Anth. Pal. 11.224; Nep. 5.1.2. See also Davies, that the (alleged) author presenting himself as narrator of APF 302–03; Blamire (1989) 11, 95, 97, 161; Zaccarini an erotic story is typical of the Milesian Tales; accord- (2017) 35–36. ingly, the third-person narrator in P.Oxy. 40.4762 is 11 Cf. Socr. Epp. 10, 16, 22–23. In Socr. Ep. 23.3, deemed ‘exceptional’: cf. Jensson (2004) 192; May for example, he is said to have urged Plato and Aristippus (2010) 76–77; Bowie (2013) 247 n.
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Citations in Classics and Ancient History
    Citations in Classics and Ancient History The most common style in use in the field of Classical Studies is the author-date style, also known as Chicago 2, but MLA is also quite common and perfectly acceptable. Quick guides for each of MLA and Chicago 2 are readily available as PDF downloads. The Chicago Manual of Style Online offers a guide on their web-page: http://www.chicagomanualofstyle.org/tools_citationguide.html The Modern Language Association (MLA) does not, but many educational institutions post an MLA guide for free access. While a specific citation style should be followed carefully, none take into account the specific practices of Classical Studies. They are all (Chicago, MLA and others) perfectly suitable for citing most resources, but should not be followed for citing ancient Greek and Latin primary source material, including primary sources in translation. Citing Primary Sources: Every ancient text has its own unique system for locating content by numbers. For example, Homer's Iliad is divided into 24 Books (what we might now call chapters) and the lines of each Book are numbered from line 1. Herodotus' Histories is divided into nine Books and each of these Books is divided into Chapters and each chapter into line numbers. The purpose of such a system is that the Iliad, or any primary source, can be cited in any language and from any publication and always refer to the same passage. That is why we do not cite Herodotus page 66. Page 66 in what publication, in what edition? Very early in your textbook, Apodexis Historia, a passage from Herodotus is reproduced.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Athenian Democracy.Pdf
    Rethinking Athenian Democracy A dissertation presented by Daniela Louise Cammack to The Department of Government in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Political Science Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2013 © 2013 Daniela Cammack All rights reserved. Professor Richard Tuck Daniela Cammack Abstract Conventional accounts of classical Athenian democracy represent the assembly as the primary democratic institution in the Athenian political system. This looks reasonable in the light of modern democracy, which has typically developed through the democratization of legislative assemblies. Yet it conflicts with the evidence at our disposal. Our ancient sources suggest that the most significant and distinctively democratic institution in Athens was the courts, where decisions were made by large panels of randomly selected ordinary citizens with no possibility of appeal. This dissertation reinterprets Athenian democracy as “dikastic democracy” (from the Greek dikastēs, “judge”), defined as a mode of government in which ordinary citizens rule principally through their control of the administration of justice. It begins by casting doubt on two major planks in the modern interpretation of Athenian democracy: first, that it rested on a conception of the “wisdom of the multitude” akin to that advanced by epistemic democrats today, and second that it was “deliberative,” meaning that mass discussion of political matters played a defining role. The first plank rests largely on an argument made by Aristotle in support of mass political participation, which I show has been comprehensively misunderstood. The second rests on the interpretation of the verb “bouleuomai” as indicating speech, but I suggest that it meant internal reflection in both the courts and the assembly.
    [Show full text]
  • The Regime of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317–307
    Th e Regime of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317–307 BCE Mnemosyne Supplements History and Archaeology of Classical Antiquity Edited by Susan E. Alcock, Brown University Th omas Harrison, Liverpool Willem M. Jongman, Groningen H.S. Versnel, Leiden VOLUME 318 Th e Regime of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317–307 BCE A Philosopher in Politics By Lara O’Sullivan LEIDEN • BOSTON 2009 On the cover: Detail of the Parthenon. Photo: Author. Th is book is printed on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data O’Sullivan, Lara. Th e rule of Demetrius of Phalerum in Athens, 317-307 B.C. : a philosopher in politics / by Lara O’Sullivan. p. cm. — (Mnemosyne supplements. History and archaeology of classical antiquity, ISSN 0169-8958 ; v. 318) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-90-04-17888-5 (hbk. : alk. paper) 1. Demetrius, of Phaleron, b. ca. 350 B.C. 2. Demetrius, of Phaleron, b. ca. 350 B.C.—Political and social views. 3. Governors—Greece—Athens—Biography. 4. Statesmen—Greece—Athens— Biography. 5. Orators—Greece—Athens—Biography. 6. Philosophers, Ancient— Biography. 7. Athens (Greece)—Politics and government. 8. Philosophy, Ancient. 9. Athens (Greece)—Relations—Macedonia. 10. Macedonia—Relations—Greece— Athens. I. Title. II. Series. DF235.48.D455O87 2009 938’.508092—dc22 [B] 2009033560 ISSN 0169-8958 ISBN 978 90 04 17888 5 Copyright 2009 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, Th e Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Knowledge, Elenchus and Authority in Early Plato
    Phronesis 65 (2020) 247-280 brill.com/phro Self-Knowledge, Elenchus and Authority in Early Plato Fiona Leigh University College, London [email protected] Abstract In some of Plato’s early dialogues we find a concern with correctly ascertaining the contents of a particular kind of one’s own psychological states, cognitive states. Indeed, one of the achievements of the elenctic method is to facilitate cognitive self- knowledge. In the Alcibiades, moreover, Plato interprets the Delphic injunction, ‘know yourself’, as crucially requiring cognitive self-knowledge, and ending in knowing one- self as subject to particular epistemic norms. Epistemic authority for self-knowledge is, for Plato, conferred on the basis of correct application of norms to cognitive self- ascriptions, and not confined to the first-personal perspective. This implies first- personal plural epistemic authority for self-knowledge. Keywords self-knowledge – elenchus – epistemic authority – dialogue – Alcibiades – Apology – Laches – Gorgias 1 Introduction In contemporary discussions of the topic that has become known as ‘self- knowledge’, philosophers not infrequently ask whether knowing the contents of one’s own thought is like perception or something more distinctive and spe- cial, or worry about privileged access to one’s own states.1 By contrast, scholarly 1 See for example, Ryle 1949, ch. 6, Evans 1982, Boghossian 1989, Shoemaker 1994, Cassam 1994, O’Brien 2007, Gertler 2015. © Fiona Leigh, 2020 | doi:10.1163/15685284-bja10020 This is an open access article distributed
    [Show full text]
  • Athenian Homicide Rhetoric in Context
    ATHENIAN HOMICIDE RHETORIC IN CONTEXT BY CHRISTINE C. PLASTOW Thesis submitted to University College London for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy DEPARTMENT OF GREEK AND LATIN UNIVERSITY COLLEGE LONDON 1 DECLARATION I, Christine C. Plastow, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. Signed: --------------------------------------------------------------------------- 2 ABSTRACT Homicide is a potent crime in any society, and classical Athens was no exception. The Athenians implemented legal methods for dealing with homicide that were set apart from the rest of their legal system, including separate courts, long-established laws, and rigorous procedures. We have, however, limited extant sources on these issues, including only five speeches from trials for homicide. This has fomented debate regarding aspects of law and procedure, and rhetoric as it relates specifically to homicide has not been examined in detail. Here, I intend to examine how the nature of homicide and its prosecution at Athens may have affected rhetoric when discussing homicide in forensic oratory. First, I will establish what I will call the ideology of homicide at Athens: the set of beliefs and perceptions that are most commonly attached to homicide and its prosecution. Then, I will examine homicide rhetoric from three angles: religious pollution, which was believed to adhere to those who committed homicide; relevance, as speakers in the homicide courts were subject to particular restrictions in this regard; and motive and intent, related issues that appear frequently in rhetoric and, in some cases, define the nature of a homicide charge.
    [Show full text]
  • The Arousal of Emotion in Plato's Dialogues Author(S): David L. Blank Source: the Classical Quarterly, New Series, Vol
    The Arousal of Emotion in Plato's Dialogues Author(s): David L. Blank Source: The Classical Quarterly, New Series, Vol. 43, No. 2, (1993), pp. 428-439 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/639181 Accessed: 10/08/2008 13:36 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Classical Quarterly 43 (ii) 428-439 (1993) Printed in Great Britain 428 THE AROUSAL OF EMOTION IN PLATO'S DIALOGUES In Aeschines' dialogue Alcibiades, Socrates sees his brilliant young partner's haughty attitude towards the great Themistocles.
    [Show full text]
  • Illinoisclassica131988univ Bw 2.Pdf
    CI Otyi^^c^ ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XIIL2 FALL/1988 Miroslav Marcovich, Editor ISSN 0363-1923 2 ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XIII. Fall 1988 Miroslav Marcovich, Editor SCHOLARS PRESS ISSN 0363-1923 2 ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XIII. Plutarch The Board of Trustees University of Illinois Copies of the journal may be ordered from: Scholars Press Customer Services P. O. Box 6525 Ithaca, New York 14851 Printed in the U.S.A. 2 EDITOR Miroslav Marcovich CO-EDITORS OF ICS XIII. Frederick E. Brenk, S.J. (Rome) Jackson P. Hershbell (Minneapolis) Philip A. Stadter (Chapel Hill) ADVISORY EDITORIAL COMMITTEE John J. Bateman Howard Jacobson David F. Bright J. K. Newman Gerald M. Browne David Sansone CAMERA-READY COPY PRODUCED BY Mary Ellen Fryer Illinois Classical Studies is published semi-annually by Scholars Press. Camera-ready copy is edited and produced in the Department of the Classics, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Each contributor receives twenty-five offprints. Contributions should be addressed to: The Editor Illinois Classical Studies Department of the Classics 4072 Foreign Languages Building 707 South Mathews Avenue Urbana, Illinois 61801 PLUTARCH ROBERT FLACELERE (1904-1982) INMEMORIAM Preface The present issue oi ICS comprises the papers presented at the Conference of the International Plutarch Society held in the summer of 1987 at Athens. I have included the contributions by the scholars unable to attend the Athens Conference. In preparing the typescripts for publication I have been assisted by such renowned Plutarchean scholars as Fr. E. Brenk, S.J. (Rome), J. P. Hershbell (Minneapolis), and Ph. A. Stadter (Chapel Hill).
    [Show full text]
  • Women and Property in Ancient Athens: a Discussion of the Private Orations and Menander Cheryl Cox University of Memphis
    Women and Property in Ancient Athens: A Discussion of the Private Orations and Menander Cheryl Cox University of Memphis There has been a great deal of discussion in the past two decades or so among social historians and anthropologists of the proposition that women in European societies, both in the past and in the present, have informal power at the private level of the household. Women’s interests were reflected and expressed in succession practices and in the management of the household economy. Central to the status of women was the dowry because of its place in the conjugal household and the negotiations over its use and transmission. A large dowry ensured the woman’s important role in the decisions of the marital household and thus helped to stabilize the marriage. Because the dowry, as the property of the woman’s natal kin, would ideally be transmitted to the man’s children, the man could become involved in the property interests of his wife’s family of origin.1 In a material sense, in classical Athens the wife’s dowry allowed for the cohesion of two households (oikoi): the oikos of her marriage and that of her natal family. The dowry in legal terms belonged to the woman’s natal family, as it had to be returned to her family of origin either on divorce or on the death of her husband and her remarriage. Much of the information we have for dowries pertains to elite families. Because the woman’s dowry could be inherited by the children, it was worth fighting for, especially if she had not received her full share (Dem.
    [Show full text]
  • Laches Before Charmides: Fictive Chronology and Platonic Pedagogy Autor(Es): Altman, William H
    Laches before Charmides: fictive chronology and platonic pedagogy Autor(es): Altman, William H. F. Publicado por: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra URL persistente: URI:http://hdl.handle.net/10316.2/42193 DOI: DOI:https://doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_10_1 Accessed : 26-Sep-2021 00:33:39 A navegação consulta e descarregamento dos títulos inseridos nas Bibliotecas Digitais UC Digitalis, UC Pombalina e UC Impactum, pressupõem a aceitação plena e sem reservas dos Termos e Condições de Uso destas Bibliotecas Digitais, disponíveis em https://digitalis.uc.pt/pt-pt/termos. Conforme exposto nos referidos Termos e Condições de Uso, o descarregamento de títulos de acesso restrito requer uma licença válida de autorização devendo o utilizador aceder ao(s) documento(s) a partir de um endereço de IP da instituição detentora da supramencionada licença. Ao utilizador é apenas permitido o descarregamento para uso pessoal, pelo que o emprego do(s) título(s) descarregado(s) para outro fim, designadamente comercial, carece de autorização do respetivo autor ou editor da obra. Na medida em que todas as obras da UC Digitalis se encontram protegidas pelo Código do Direito de Autor e Direitos Conexos e demais legislação aplicável, toda a cópia, parcial ou total, deste documento, nos casos em que é legalmente admitida, deverá conter ou fazer-se acompanhar por este aviso. impactum.uc.pt digitalis.uc.pt JOURNAL DEZ 2010 ISSN 2079-7567 eISSN 2183-4105 PLATO 10 Established 1989 http://platosociety.org/ INTERNATIONAL PLATO SOCIETY PLATO INTERNATIONAL PL ATO Société Platonicienne JOURNALInternationale Associazione Internazionale dei Platonisti Sociedad Internacional de Platonistas Internationale Platon-Gesellschaft ALTMAN, William H.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Daimonion of Socrates
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Heinz-Günther Nesselrath, Reinhard Feldmeier und Rainer Hirsch-Luipold Band XVI Plutarch On the daimonion of Socrates Human liberation, divine guidance and philosophy edited by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath Introduction, Text, Translation and Interpretative Essays by Donald Russell, George Cawkwell, Werner Deuse, John Dillon, Heinz-Günther Nesselrath, Robert Parker, Christopher Pelling, Stephan Schröder Mohr Siebeck e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156444-4 ISBN 978-3-16-150138-8 (cloth) ISBN 987-3-16-150137-1 (paperback) The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio- nal bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data is availableon the Internet at http:// dnb.d-nb.de. © 2010 by Mohr Siebeck Tübingen. This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This applies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and processing in electronic systems. This book was typeset by Christoph Alexander Martsch, Serena Pirrotta and Thorsten Stolper at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen, printed by Gulde- Druck in Tübingen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times. The first four centuries of our era have, however, produced a cornucopia of works in Greek and Latin dealing with questions of philoso- phy, ethics, and religion that continue to be relevant even today.
    [Show full text]
  • Popular Attitudes to Judicial Activity in the Age of Aristophanes
    Popular Attitudes to Judicial Activity in the Age of Aristophanes Angus Julian Dewar Crichton PhD Thesis University College London ProQuest Number: 10017252 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. uest. ProQuest 10017252 Published by ProQuest LLC(2016). Copyright of the Dissertation is held by the Author. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 Abstract The aim of the thesis is to understand popular attitudes in Athens to judicial activity in the late fifth and early fourth centuries, the period in which Aristophanes wrote and performed his plays. Within the Aristophanic world, characters are frequently portrayed as engaging in litigation and jury service. Moreover, this portrayal of judicial activity is decidedly ambivalent, with the comic hero often fleeing from judicial activity into a fantastical paradise within which judicial activity is consciously banished. And yet as the play continues, judicial activity often resurfaces within the fantastical paradise. These on-stage images of judicial activity are compared with portraits which litigants paint of themselves and their opponents in the Attic Orators. Litigants characteristically present themselves as inexperienced and reluctant to engage in judicial activity, while portraying their opponents as experienced to the point of sycophancy.
    [Show full text]