Preface Part I Intuitions 1 Ethical Intuitionism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Preface Part I Intuitions 1 Ethical Intuitionism Notes Preface 1. For example, the special issue of Philosophical Explorations that is devoted to the discussion of the meaning of neurological findings for moral philoso- phy is set up within the dichotomy ‘sentimentalism’ versus ‘rationalism’ (cf. Gerrans and Kennett 2006). Part I Intuitions 1. This they have in common with the earlier sentimentalists such as Hutcheson and Price. W.D. Hudson includes them in his definition of intuitionism: ‘Ethical intuitionism is here taken to be the view that nor- mal human beings have an immediate awareness of moral values,’ Hudson (1967, 1). I do not include the sentimentalists in my account since they do not fit into the core theory; that is, they are generally not taken to be nonreductive moral realists but subjectivists instead (with the exception of Shaftesbury, cf. Gill 2006). 2. There may be philosophers who are not characterized as intuitionists but who still fulfill the criteria. Strictly speaking, they could then be called intuitionists as well. The idea that intuitionism is more widely accepted than only by textbook-intuitionists is something Reid would be eager to acknowledge. He emphasizes throughout his work that he is saying nothing controversial but is defending a theory that is supposed to capture com- monsense and that has been defended by many philosophers, in particular Aristotle. 1 Ethical intuitionism 1. David Brink (1989, 102) and Michael Huemer (2005) have a similar char- acterization of intuitionism. Brink refers mainly to the same authors as I do. 2. Whether this is a correct interpretation is a matter of debate among Hume scholars, but I will adopt this interpretation since this is how Hume is com- monly understood in the recent meta-ethical literature. 3. In Chapter 2, I will discuss the different importance intuitionists assign to these propositions. 4. Cf. also Broadie (1998). For a criticism of Reid’s view on this point, see Chapter 5. 5. At least as they present themselves in recent analytical metaethics, such as Korsgaard and Rawls. 183 184 Notes 6. I will mainly use the contemporary terminology of ‘basic belief’, but when I quote Reid the reader should realize that this is what he means by ‘first principle’; that is, for Reid a particular observation can also function as a ‘first principle’, namely, as a foundation for other beliefs. 7. Sidgwick takes these principles to be moral axioms. 8. This example can be found in different versions in the literature, for exam- ple, in AP 232, McNaughton (1988), and Little (1995). 9. In the case of animals, Reid calls this opinion and reserves the term judg- mentt for rational beings only. 10. It may not be a coincidence that in that quote Reid takes the Golden Rule as an example, as this can be seen as more or less (extensionally) equivalent to the categorical imperative. 11. An example of an externalist who does speak in terms of justification is Alvin Goldman: ‘I do not even assume that when a belief is justified there is something “possessed” by the believer which can be called a “jus- tification.” I do assume that a justified belief gets its status of being justi- fied from some processes or properties that make it justified’ (Goldman 1992, 106). 12. This still allows for the possibility that theorems that we can intuit can also be verified, that is, in the case of improperly basic beliefs. But in the end such a verification will rely on basic beliefs concerning axioms (cf. the point about overdetermination before). 13. Moore says something similar, cf. PE 145. 14. In the case of moral beliefs this last criterion might invite more disagree- ment than consensus. I will discuss this point further in Chapter 3. 15. I will discuss this notion in Chapter 2. 16. However, recently, for example, Cuneo (2007) and Shafer-Landau (2003) have defended moral realism in book-length studies. 17. Cf. Sayre-McCord (1988b), especially the diagram on p. 15. I will argue fur- ther on in this section why I believe that an antirealist version of cognitiv- ism is problematic. 18. There has been a huge debate about whether Moore’s open question argu- ment indeed proves what it is supposed to, or whether it proves too much, for example, that water and H2O cannot be the same since we can always ask whether this is really true. I will not go into this debate here; instead, I try to capture the spirit of the open-question argument, which is that moral properties cannot be reduced to nonmoral properties as morality is an irre- ducible domain of reality (cf. Huemer 2005, 94, 95). 19. Dancy argues that ‘resultance’ and supervenience are strictly speaking not the same. Supervenience is more suited for a generalist account, whereas resultance is more suited for a particularist account. Cf. for example Dancy (1993) 73–8. I will come back to the issue of generalism and particularism in Chapter 4. 20. However, compare with what I said before and what I will say in Chapter 2, when I discuss that both Ross and Reid believe that we have to believe that what we do is right. But this does not mean that our beliefs can change the facts; it just means that we have to act from a good motive and with the right intentions. Notes 185 21. In his discussion of different ways to understand naturalist epistemology Jaegwon Kim defends that Moore is a (nonreductive) ethical naturalist, cf. Kim (1993, 233, 234). See also Kim’s quote of Moore on p. 233. 22. According to Reid, this same figurative way of assigning properties to objects that actually are properties of the mind of the object’s creator occurs with regards to works of art, science, and God’s creation and so on, cf. IP 773–5. 23. However, elsewhere Reid distinguishes between the inherent value of an action in abstraction of the intentions of an agent and the value of an action given the agent’s intentions (APP 394, 395; cf. my Chapter 2). 2 Different forms of intuitionism 1. By active principles of man, Reid means instincts, desires, and rationality; cf. Essay III of the AP. 2. Rawls (1971, 45) claims that his attempt to provide for a serial ordering of moral principles is a novelty, but Reid already did so 200 years before Rawls, and Sidgwick can be understood to attempt something similar, as will become clear below. 3. Cf. AP 431: ‘The simple rule, of not doing to his neighbour what he [a man] would think wrong to be done to himself, would lead him to the knowledge of every branch of justice.’ 4. Sidgwick calls these ‘Principles’ with a capital P, while principles with a small p refer to principles in the sense of ‘first principles’. 5. Hedonism here means the prevention of pain and the maximization of happiness. 6. Actually, Sidgwick claims that universal hedonism and egoistic hedon- ism are equally self-evident but lead to contrary results; this is what he calls the ‘paradox of practical reason’, an issue I will not discuss any further. 7. Concer ning the end of happiness understood in an egoistic way, Sidgwick believes that the most reliable method is ‘empirical hedonism’. 8. J.B. Schneewind (1977, 291) emphasizes that Sidgwick reformulates these axioms several times throughout ME; these are the shortest versions, but probably not the most complete. 9. Cf. the discussion of nonreductionism in Chapter 1. 10. Hence Rawls misrepresents Sidgwick completely when he says that ‘[c]lassical utilitarianism tries, of course, to avoid the appeal to intuition altogether’ (Rawls 1971, 40, 41), where he refers to Sidgwick explicitly. This might be due to Rawls’s own disputable definition of intuition as particular basic moral belief, but this is a definition which is (at least con- cerning the intuitionists) historically incorrect and causes a misrepresen- tation of the intuitionists’ views. I will come back to this at the end of this chapter. 11. The theory of the ‘organic whole’ can in Moore’s words be summarized as this: ‘The value of a whole must not be assumed to be the same as the sum of the values of its parts’ (PE 28). 186 Notes 12. Prima facie is meant as ‘as far as it goes’. I will explain this idea in more detail in Section 3. 13. This is a different formulation of the principle of justice than the one I quoted in Section 2. Note that the other formulation is in positive terms, but still Sidgwick would find that principle insufficient. 14. Note that in contemporary literature the notion ‘pro tanto reason’ (meaning ‘as far as it goes’, see Dancy 1993, 180) is sometimes used instead of prima facie duty, to avoid the misleading expression ‘prima facie’, which might sug- gest that it is immediately obvious what our duty is; indeed Ross was not happy with that expression (RG 20). 15. In this context, Ross only refers to Kant, but I think his point is valid against all kinds of monist theories, cf. McNaughton (1988) 198. Cf. also De Haan (2000), who argues that monist theories cannot acknowledge the possibility of moral dilemmas; according to him a Rossian-style pluralist intuitionism can give the most plausible account of what a moral dilemma is and why we experience it as such. 16. I try to avoid the term deontologyy, as it might be understood as referring to unconditional duties (as Sidgwick presents it). As I will argue in this section, Reid and Ross are well aware of the importance of considering consequences of actions, but not in the sense of maximizing outcomes.
Recommended publications
  • Ethical Intuitionism: a Structural Critique
    J Value Inquiry (2016) 50:631–647 DOI 10.1007/s10790-016-9547-8 Ethical Intuitionism: A Structural Critique Danny Frederick1 Published online: 8 February 2016 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 1 Introduction Recent years have seen attempts by many philosophers to rehabilitate, with some modifications, a traditional doctrine of ethical intuitionism (henceforward ‘‘intu- itionism’’). Contemporary intuitionists claim that moral knowledge consists of those propositions that are known by intellectual reflection (intuition), by moral observation or by moral emotion, or which are capable of being cogently inferred from propositions which are items of moral knowledge. Some intuitionists, such as Michael Huemer, admit only intuition (of particular or of general propositions) as a non-inferential source of moral knowledge; but others, such as Robert Audi, allow also moral observation and moral emotion. I offer a critique of contemporary intuitionist theories that depends upon their common structure: analysis of the abstract features of the approach show it to be an inadequate account of moral knowledge. I use Huemer and Audi as representative intuitionists. The differences between their views, and between their views and those of other intuitionists, are incidental at the level of generality of my argument. In section 2, I outline the contemporary intuitionist approach to moral knowledge. In sections 3, 4 and 5, I show that the problem of inter-cultural conflict undermines the claims that moral intuition, moral observation and moral emotion, respectively, are sources of non-inferential moral knowledge. I also explain the inadequacy of the intuitionist attempt to solve the problem by invoking bias or intellectual or moral failings.
    [Show full text]
  • Kantian Intuitionism
    An Intuitionist Response to Moral Scepticism A critique of Mackie's scepticism, and an alternative proposal combining Ross's intuitionism with a Kantian epistemology by Simon John Duffy PhD The University of Edinburgh 2001 PhD Thesis: An Intuitionist Response to Moral Scepticism - Page 1 CONTENTS ABSTRACT .................................................................................................................................................................... 4 DECLARATION .................................................................................................................................................................... 5 INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................................................................................... 6 1 .................................................................................................................................................................... OUR BELIEFS ABOUT MORALITY .................................................................................................................................................................... 11 1.1 WHAT DO WE OWE COMMON-SENSE? .11 1.2 OUR EVERYDAY CONCEPTION OF ETHICS .17 1.3 THE CENTRALITY OF DUTY .24 1.4 THE IMPLICATIONS OF DUTY .32 2 .................................................................................................................................................................... THE SCEPTICAL ATTACK ...................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • ¼ PHILOSOPHY of RELIGION.Pdf
    ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION other books in the same series A Concise Encyclopedia of Judaism, Dan Cohn-Serbok, ISBN 1–85168–176–0 A Concise Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Klaus K. Klostermaier, ISBN 1–85168–175–2 A Concise Encyclopedia of Christianity, Geoffrey Parrinder, ISBN 1–85168–174–4 A Concise Encyclopedia of Buddhism, John Powers, ISBN 1–85168–233–3 A Concise Encyclopedia of the Baha´’ı´ Faith, Peter Smith, ISBN 1–85168–184–1 A Concise Encyclopedia of Islam, Gordon D. Newby, ISBN 1–85168–295–3 related titles published by oneworld Ethics in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–247–3 The Fifth Dimension, John Hick, ISBN 1–85168–191–4 Global Philosophy of Religion: A Short Introduction, Joseph Runzo, ISBN 1–85168–235–X God: A Guide for the Perplexed, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–284–8 God, Faith and the New Millennium, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–155–8 Love, Sex and Gender in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–223–6 The Meaning of Life in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–200–7 The Phenomenon of Religion, Moojan Momen, ISBN 1–85168–161–2 ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION ANTHONY C. THISELTON A CONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Oneworld Publications (Sales and Editorial) 185 Banbury Road Oxford OX2 7AR England www.oneworld-publications.com # Anthony C. Thiselton 2002 All rights reserved. Copyright under Berne Convention A CIP record for this title is available from the British Library ISBN 1–85168–301–1 Cover design by Design Deluxe Typeset by LaserScript, Mitcham, UK Printed and bound in the United Kingdom by Bell & Bain Ltd, Glasgow NL08 Contents Preface and acknowledgements vi A Concise Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Religion 1 Chronology 329 Index of names 337 Preface and acknowledgements Aims, scope and target readership he following selection of subject entries has been shaped in the light of Tmany years of feedback from my own students.
    [Show full text]
  • A Further Reinterpretation of the Moral Philosophy of John Stuart Mill
    A FURTHER REINTERPRETATION OF THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF JOHN STUART MILL. by Derek Jo Banks M.A.9 University of Glasgow, 1970 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Philosophy 0 DEREK JOHN BANKS 1972 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY January 1972 Name : Derek J. Banks !iiitlc of '.thesis : li ir'urther deinterpretation of the Floral I'hilosophy of John ,Stuart Mill Examining Cornrni-ttee : Chairman: Kay Jennings """ Lionel Kenner Senior Supervisor P "-" Donald G. Brown Lxt ernal Axaminer &of essor of 'hilosophy University of British Columbia I ABSTRACT Those of Mill's critics who focus their attention on Utilitarianism assume that Mill must have held that certain ethical sentences, including one expressing the principle of utility, are properly describable as true. In this thesis I set out to demonstrate the spuriousness of this assumption. I begin by showing that in several important works - works which he thought much more highly of than he did Utilitarianism - Mill denied that the truth (or falsity) of any ethical sentences can ever be established. Next I produce evidence that his reason for this denial lies in his commitment to the view that ethical sentences are really disguised imperative sentences, and hence have no truth-value. Pinally, it is argued that there is nothing in Utilitarianism that is inconsistent with the meta-ethical position which we have found him to adopt in his other works related to ethics. In a short coneluding chapter I devote as much space as I deem permissible in a thesis of this type to show that reinterpretation of Mill's ethical theory on an imperative model renders it more plausible than it is generally taken to be, since all theories which allow truth-values to ethical sentences are open to knock-down objections.
    [Show full text]
  • A Perceptual Theory of Hope
    AN OPEN ACCESS Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY A Perceptual Theory of Hope MICHAEL MILONA Auburn University KATIE STOCKDALE1 Sam Houston State University This paper addresses the question of what the attitude of hope consists in. We ar- gue that shortcomings in recent theories of hope have methodological roots in that they proceed with little regard for the rich body of literature on the emotions. Taking insights from work in the philosophy of emotions, we argue that hope involves a kind of normative perception. We then develop a strategy for determining the con- tent of this perception, arguing that hope is a perception of practical reasons. Our proposal stands in contrast with familiar views on which hope is fundamentally about the good. We conclude by considering the increasingly popular idea that some hopes are non- intentional and thus, by implication, non- perceptual. We reply by arguing that our perceptual theory plausibly generalizes to these instances of hope. Keywords: hope, perception, emotion, moral psychology 1. Introduction The view that hope involves a desire for p and a belief that p’s obtaining is pos- sible but not certain has become known as the standard or orthodox account of hope (Martin 2014; Meirav 2009). Some philosophers think that the standard view is sufficient to capture some of our trivial hopes, like the hope that the sun will come out soon (Calhoun in press; Pettit 2004). There is widespread consen- sus in the literature, however, that the standard account cannot make sense of our most significant hopes, like the hope to be cured of cancer or the hope that a wrongdoer be brought to justice.
    [Show full text]
  • From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)
    From:214 L—rsmkv!rs—ks—syxsMichael Huemer,sm! Ethical Intuitionism (2005) finds Sally funny, but later decides he was mistaken about her funniness when the audience merely groans.) It seems, then, that humor subjectivism is far more defensible than moral subjectivism. One further point. Many examples of 'obviously subjective' properties may have evaluative components, and this will stymie any attempt to give them purely subjectivist analyses. 'If baby-killing i mpressed a lot of people, then baby-killing would be cool' is false because baby-killing is bad, and 'cool' implies 'good' (whatever else it implies). Similarly, in some cases, a person may argue that something is 'not funny' on moral grounds—for instance, that it is inappropriate to laugh at a thing because doing so would offend others or express a bad attitude. Perhaps 'funny' implies 'not bad to laugh at'. 'Sexy' may similarly imply 'not bad (or abnormal) to feel sexual attraction towards'. If this is so, then of course these concepts will resist purely subjectivist treatments, but that would not pose a challenge to the arguments of this book. :08 E}ur{zout gtj kznoiy 8.6.1 The evolutionary objection to realism Sociobiologists (or 'evolutionary psychologists', in the current lingo) have offered explanations for moral behavior and moral beliefs, in terms of the theory of evolution. Since evolution generally leads us to expect selfishness, the main problem has been taken to be that of explaining why we often help others at some cost to ourselves. Proffered partial explanations include: Kin selection: We help members of our own families, often at great expense to ourselves, because family members share many of the same genes.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberty University School of Divinity a Non
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Liberty University Digital Commons LIBERTY UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF DIVINITY A NON-VOLUNTARIST THEORY: AN ALTERNATE EVANGELICAL APOLOGETIC FOR DEALING WITH THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF LIBERTY UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF DIVINITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY EVAN TAYLOR POSEY LYNCHBURG, VIRGINIA OCTOBER 2016 APPROVAL SHEET A NON-VOLUNTARIST THEORY: AN ALTERNATE EVANGELICAL APOLOGETIC FOR DEALING WITH THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA Evan Taylor Posey Read and approved by: Chair Person: Richard A. Holland Reader: Edward N. Martin Reader: Anthony C. Thornhill Date: 10/9/2016 ii To my wife, Leslie-Ann, my children, and my family: There are no words that can adequately express my gratitude for your love, encouragement, and patience. iii CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ............................................................................................................ vi ABSTRACT ................................................................................................................................. viii CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................. 1 Statement of Purpose and Thesis ...................................................................................... 10 Definitions .......................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Humanist Liturgy and Proposals
    84 Toward Thinking Freely: Propositions (More and Less True) Concerning Humanism and Freethought (in no particular order) One believes in existence; Another says, "There is nothing!" Rare is the one who believes in neither. That one is free from confusion. Ashtavakra Gita 18:42 (500 BCE) 85 * * * There are many ponderous tomes concerning Humanism. Some are worth the time. Many are not. In the following pages I intend to be pithy, not ponderous, concerning living a life of humanistic freethought. * * * Keep in mind that there is no single Humanism. There are many human expressions of a life well-lived that can be termed Humanism. Hereafter, when I use the term, I mean a particular type of Humanism from a particular tradition. However, humility teaches of other ways and places of being across borders and boundaries of time, place, and culture. * * * There is no one way to be a Humanist or freethinker. Your viewpoint begins with your standpoint. * * * Some argue that the concept of the human has changed so much in the last century that it’s time to move from “humanism” to “post-humanism” as a way of signaling this turn of thought. I’m good with that. * * * Freethinkers and Humanists usually adopt a naturalistic and materialistic worldview. This worldview implies that there is no difference between body and mind (all thought is embodied thought) and that human beings are each a temporary congeries of matter that has before and will later appear in a different congeries. * * * A naturalistic and materialist viewpoint implies that all matter everywhere is of equal worth and importance, whether that matter appears as a human, a squirrel, a cloud, or 86 a rock.
    [Show full text]
  • An Unconnected Heap of Duties?
    An Unconnected Heap of Duties? Despite its name, the school of ethical intuitionism which flourished between the World Wars, and whose greatest proponents were Prichard and Ross, was not distinguished from its competitors by a distinctive epistemology. The dispute between intuitionism and its main rival, the utilitarian tradition, revolved around the issue of whether there was more than one fundamental moral principle.1 The utilitarian tradition in ethical thought can be represented as holding that there is just one fundamental duty or moral principle: the duty of beneficence. Ethical intuitionism rejected this monism as over- simple, and insisted that there is a number of distinct basic duties or moral principles.2 Both parties to this debate were taken to agree that an ethical theory must be based on intuition, by which was meant no more than that the most basic ethical principles, since they could not be inferred from more basic ones, must be self-evident.3 It has become commonplace to dismiss the deontic pluralism of an ethical intuitionist such as Ross fairly briskly. The two main charges are, first, that it is unsystematic, offering us merely a 'heap of unconnected duties' with no unifying rationale and, second, that it can give nothing in the way of general guidance to the agent who is faced with a conflict of duties, because it refuses to rank duties in order of importance or stringency.4 The intuitionists were, of course, aware of these objections; what I intend to show in this paper is that we can find, in the writings of W.D.
    [Show full text]
  • An Interdisciplinary Analysis of the Use of Ethical Intuition in Legal Compliance Decisionmaking for Business Entities Eric C
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Digital Commons @ UM Law Maryland Law Review Volume 74 | Issue 3 Article 3 An Interdisciplinary Analysis of the Use of Ethical Intuition in Legal Compliance Decisionmaking for Business Entities Eric C. Chaffee Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr Part of the Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, and the Legal Profession Commons Recommended Citation 74 Md. L. Rev. 497 (2015) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Academic Journals at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Maryland Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. AN INTERDISCIPLINARY ANALYSIS OF THE USE OF ETHICAL INTUITION IN LEGAL COMPLIANCE DECISIONMAKING FOR BUSINESS ENTITIES * ERIC C. CHAFFEE I. INTRODUCTION Amanda Appleton is a mid-level associate in the business law department of Boxer & Boxer LLP, a large international law firm. Her practice focuses on advising companies on matters re- lating to the regulation of publicly traded securities. She is well respected at the firm, and her prognosis for making partner is ex- cellent. At 11:30 AM yesterday morning, Paul Pratt, a partner in the business law department, called Appleton with an assignment. Global Giant Corporation is preparing to make various public disclosures by filing a Form 10-K with the Securities and Ex- change Commission (“SEC”). Pratt asked Appleton to research whether some of the proposed disclosures might be considered manipulative or deceptive in violation of various securities laws and regulations.
    [Show full text]
  • Seeing Right from Wrong: a Defense of a Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism
    Syracuse University SURFACE Dissertations - ALL SURFACE July 2016 Seeing Right from Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism Preston John Werner Syracuse University Follow this and additional works at: https://surface.syr.edu/etd Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Werner, Preston John, "Seeing Right from Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism" (2016). Dissertations - ALL. 532. https://surface.syr.edu/etd/532 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the SURFACE at SURFACE. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations - ALL by an authorized administrator of SURFACE. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Preston J. Werner Seeing What’s Right and Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism Dissertation Abstract This dissertation develops and defends A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism, the view that our epistemic access to moral properties is grounded in perceptual experience. It contains two parts. In part I, I present the epistemic access problem for realist moral epistemology and argue against several a priori attempts to resolve it. In part II, I defend A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism and its ability to resolve the epistemic access problem. Part I begins by arguing that evolutionary debunking arguments are best understood as claiming that we lack epistemic access to mind-independent moral facts. The remainder of part I rejects several attempts to respond to this challenge. I first argue that even sophisticated versions of reflective equilibrium, as coherentist theories, fall victim to a “garbage in, garbage out” objection. I conclude that a proper solution to the epistemic access problem must be foundationalist.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Intuitionism
    Ethical intuitionism Previous (Ethical Culture) (/entry/Ethical_Culture) Next (Ethics) (/entry/Ethics) Ethical intuitionism refers to a core of related moral theories, influential in Britain already in the 1700s, but coming to especial prominence in the work of G.E. Moore (/entry/G.E._Moore), H.A. Pritchard and W. D. Ross (/entry/W._D._Ross) in the earlier part of the twentieth century. Somewhat confusingly, however, the label ‘ethical intuitionism’ has had at least two distinct contemporary uses. Firstly, ‘intuitionism’ between the 1860s and 1920s was another name for unranked pluralism (/entry/Pluralism), the doctrine that there is a plurality of moral principles none of which is more basic than any other. In this respect, intuitionism is a normative ethical theory (/entry/Normative_ethics) contrasted with versions of monism (/entry/Monism)—the view that there is only one basic moral principle—such as utilitarianism (/entry/Utilitarianism), and Kantianism (/entry/Kantianism). Intuitionism in this sense is nowadays distinguished as methodological intuitionism. Secondly, and primarily, intuitionism in ethics refers to a cluster of theories Contents about how moral agents come to know which things are good, or which actions are right and wrong. This view may be distinguished as 1 Historical overview 2 Two senses of intuitionism epistemological (/entry/Epistemology) intuitionism, a theory of the way in 3 Varieties of epistemological which ethical propositions come to be grasped or known. The relationship intuitionism between these doctrines is primarily historical: important intuitionist thinkers 4 Arguments for intuitionism such as H.A. Pritchard and W.D. Ross embraced both methodological and 5 Objections to intuitionism epistemological intuitionism.
    [Show full text]