Seeing Right from Wrong: a Defense of a Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Seeing Right from Wrong: a Defense of a Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism Syracuse University SURFACE Dissertations - ALL SURFACE July 2016 Seeing Right from Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism Preston John Werner Syracuse University Follow this and additional works at: https://surface.syr.edu/etd Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Werner, Preston John, "Seeing Right from Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism" (2016). Dissertations - ALL. 532. https://surface.syr.edu/etd/532 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the SURFACE at SURFACE. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations - ALL by an authorized administrator of SURFACE. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Preston J. Werner Seeing What’s Right and Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism Dissertation Abstract This dissertation develops and defends A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism, the view that our epistemic access to moral properties is grounded in perceptual experience. It contains two parts. In part I, I present the epistemic access problem for realist moral epistemology and argue against several a priori attempts to resolve it. In part II, I defend A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism and its ability to resolve the epistemic access problem. Part I begins by arguing that evolutionary debunking arguments are best understood as claiming that we lack epistemic access to mind-independent moral facts. The remainder of part I rejects several attempts to respond to this challenge. I first argue that even sophisticated versions of reflective equilibrium, as coherentist theories, fall victim to a “garbage in, garbage out” objection. I conclude that a proper solution to the epistemic access problem must be foundationalist. I then survey other influential a priori approaches to epistemic access. I conclude that each either fails to ensure epistemic access, or succeeds by providing epistemic access to the wrong properties—viz. not the robustly normative ones. Part II begins with an argument that we can have perceptual experiences of moral properties by making use of a “method of contrast” argument of the sort found in the philosophy of perception literature. Next, I defend the foundationalist credentials of a posteriori ethical intuitionism against the objection that moral experiences are epistemically dependent on (moral) beliefs. I then discuss the role of emotions in generating moral perceptions. If emotions are themselves perceptual, their role in producing moral perceptual experiences is not problematic. Some have argued that emotions cannot be perceptual since we can be morally responsible for having (or failing to have) certain emotional experiences. I argue against this claim, and in favor of a perceptualist conception of emotions. Finally, I return to the issue of epistemic access. I argue that the perceptual view provides an explanation of our epistemic access to the moral properties, and that such a view is compatible with the non-causal nature of those properties. Seeing Right From Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism by Preston John Werner B.A. University of Iowa, 2007 M.A. University of Nebraska, 2012 Dissertation Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy. Syracuse University July 2016 Copyright © Preston John Werner. 2016. Seeing Right from Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism by Preston John Werner is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Acknowledgments: You’ll have to humor me, as this is the first, and may very well be the last, time that I’ll be able to acknowledge how much of me is just an amalgamation of the people I’ve been lucky enough to have been surrounded by the last several years. First, my committee—David Sobel, Hille Paakkunainen, Ben Bradley, Russ Shafer-Landau, and Andre Gallois—have helped me immensely in thinking through these issues, and perhaps most importantly, have encouraged me despite the initial questionable plausibility of the view I defend here. I also think it would be negligent to not also include here Mark van Roojen, who, although is not an official committee member, helped me more than he knows at the initial stages of my project. My thoughts about moral epistemology and much else have been deeply influenced by all six of these people. My dissertation was written in two very geographically distinct places—half at the University of Nebraska and half at Syracuse University. But both places are packed with brilliant and hardworking faculty and graduate students. Interesting and insightful philosophical conversation fills the air like snow on any given Syracuse winter day. I want to thank all of the faculty and graduate students at both of these schools, but especially the following for helping to clear my head on various issues in the dissertation that follows: Patrick Arnold, Aaron Bronfman, Gabe Bruguier, Arturo Castellanos, David Chavez, Çağla Çimendereli, Lorenza D’Angelo, Dante Dauksz, Naomi Dershowitz, Maddie Eller, Aaron Elliott, Luke Elwonger, Kendall Fisher, Allison v Fritz, Carolyn Garland, Shane George, C.J.K. Gibilisco, Reina Hayaki, Landon Hedrick, David Henderson, Ben Henke, Cliff Hill, Isaiah Lin, Scott Looney, Yaojun Lu, Tim Loughrist, Jennifer McKitrick, Joseph Mendola, Justin Moss, Chris Richards, Byron Simmons, Steve Steward, Andrew Spaid, Brian Tackett, Travis Timmerman, Adam Thompson, Kaz Watanabe, Sam Wolf, and Seiichi Yasuda. I want to particularly thank Teresa Bruno and Nicole Dular, my fellow graduate students and advisee siblings. With how much they influenced my thinking, and how much they read of my dissertation, they might as well also be honorary committee members. And finally, my mother and father, Nancy and Bruce, and Ted Towner, roommate, friend, and confidant. This dissertation is for Steve Swartzer and Clare LaFrance, for teaching me how to see, and to Nikki Fortier, Emily Garton, and Mose, for teaching me how to feel. vi TABLE OF CONTENTS PART I 1 CHAPTER 1. HOW TO UNDERSTAND THE EPISTEMIC ACCESS PROBLEM 1 CHAPTER 2. SCANLON’S REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM 31 CHAPTER 3. WHY CONCEPTUAL COMPETENCE WON’T HELP THE NON-NATURALIST 52 PART II 89 CHAPTER 4. MORAL PERCEPTION AND THE CONTENTS OF EXPERIENCE 89 CHAPTER 5. A POSTERIORI ETHICAL INTUITIONISM AND COGNITIVE PENETRATION 118 CHAPTER 6. PERCEPTUALISM ABOUT EMOTIONS AND RATIONAL CRITICIZABILITY 149 CHAPTER 7. TOWARD A PERCEPTUAL SOLUTION TO EPISTEMOLOGICAL OBJECTIONS 170 BIBLIOGRAPHY 203 1 Chapter 1 How to Understand the Epistemic Access Problem for Non-Naturalist Moral Realism Introduction A longstanding objection to non-naturalist moral realism (henceforth “non- naturalism”) is that it is incompatible with any plausible explanation of how we can come to have knowledge of moral truths.1 As most non-naturalists accept, our beliefs about these entities could not be caused by them.2 It is mysterious, the objection goes, how we could have epistemic access to these non-causal entities in order to form justified beliefs about them. I call this kind of epistemological objection the access objection.3 Though the objection is frequently gestured at, it is not often developed in much detail. Nevertheless, it is an objection generally taken seriously (and rightly so). The purpose of this paper is to clarify and develop the various forms of the access objection and propose a unique formulation that I believe is superior to those currently found in the literature. The key in developing a proper understanding of the access objection is to do so in a way that is charitable both to the proponent of the objection as well as the non-naturalist. This means that the objection should neither be 1 Arguably, this objection goes at least back to Mackie (1977), Ch. 1. Harman (1977), Ch.1 presses an arguably similar worry, though it is in terms of explanation rather than causation. Two more recent versions of this objection, which emphasize evolution as particularly damning for non-naturalist epistemology are Joyce (2001) and Street (2006). 2 Huemer (2008), Ch.5, Scanlon (forthcoming), Lectures 1-2, Dworkin (2011), Ch.4, and Ridge (2008), Section 3. 3 As will become clear below, there is no single access objection, but many substantively different ways of pressing a general epistemological concern about our access to objective moral truths. So I mean “access objection” to apply to a range of epistemological objections to non-naturalism. 2 formulated in a way that is clearly misguided, nor in a way that begs the question against the non-naturalist. I develop my formulation of the objection by taking a step back from metaethics to epistemology more generally. I do this in order to motivate a general epistemological principle I call the access requirement, which requires that an adequate epistemology for a given domain explain how our justified beliefs can be in some way responsive to the facts of that domain.4 The access requirement is closely related to the fact that, as Lawrence BonJour says, “one crucial part of the task of an adequate epistemological theory is to show that there is an appropriate connection between its proposed account of epistemic justification and the cognitive goal of truth.”5 If this is right, then a theory of justification for any given domain, ethics included, must meet the access requirement. 1. Benacerraf’s Problem What I am calling the access objection to moral realism can be traced back to Paul Benacerraf’s (1973) “Mathematical Truth”. As its title suggests, Benacerraf was worried about the epistemology of mathematics for a Platonist conception of mathematical objects. David Liggins (2010) helpfully reconstructs Benacerraf’s argument as follows: (B1) If mathematical platonism is true, then we have knowledge of abstract mathematical entities. (B2) If we have knowledge of abstract mathematical entities, then we are causally related to them. (B3) We are not causally related to abstract mathematical entities. 4 For the more precise formulation, see section 5 below.
Recommended publications
  • Ethical Intuitionism: a Structural Critique
    J Value Inquiry (2016) 50:631–647 DOI 10.1007/s10790-016-9547-8 Ethical Intuitionism: A Structural Critique Danny Frederick1 Published online: 8 February 2016 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 1 Introduction Recent years have seen attempts by many philosophers to rehabilitate, with some modifications, a traditional doctrine of ethical intuitionism (henceforward ‘‘intu- itionism’’). Contemporary intuitionists claim that moral knowledge consists of those propositions that are known by intellectual reflection (intuition), by moral observation or by moral emotion, or which are capable of being cogently inferred from propositions which are items of moral knowledge. Some intuitionists, such as Michael Huemer, admit only intuition (of particular or of general propositions) as a non-inferential source of moral knowledge; but others, such as Robert Audi, allow also moral observation and moral emotion. I offer a critique of contemporary intuitionist theories that depends upon their common structure: analysis of the abstract features of the approach show it to be an inadequate account of moral knowledge. I use Huemer and Audi as representative intuitionists. The differences between their views, and between their views and those of other intuitionists, are incidental at the level of generality of my argument. In section 2, I outline the contemporary intuitionist approach to moral knowledge. In sections 3, 4 and 5, I show that the problem of inter-cultural conflict undermines the claims that moral intuition, moral observation and moral emotion, respectively, are sources of non-inferential moral knowledge. I also explain the inadequacy of the intuitionist attempt to solve the problem by invoking bias or intellectual or moral failings.
    [Show full text]
  • Kantian Intuitionism
    An Intuitionist Response to Moral Scepticism A critique of Mackie's scepticism, and an alternative proposal combining Ross's intuitionism with a Kantian epistemology by Simon John Duffy PhD The University of Edinburgh 2001 PhD Thesis: An Intuitionist Response to Moral Scepticism - Page 1 CONTENTS ABSTRACT .................................................................................................................................................................... 4 DECLARATION .................................................................................................................................................................... 5 INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................................................................................... 6 1 .................................................................................................................................................................... OUR BELIEFS ABOUT MORALITY .................................................................................................................................................................... 11 1.1 WHAT DO WE OWE COMMON-SENSE? .11 1.2 OUR EVERYDAY CONCEPTION OF ETHICS .17 1.3 THE CENTRALITY OF DUTY .24 1.4 THE IMPLICATIONS OF DUTY .32 2 .................................................................................................................................................................... THE SCEPTICAL ATTACK ...................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • ¼ PHILOSOPHY of RELIGION.Pdf
    ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION other books in the same series A Concise Encyclopedia of Judaism, Dan Cohn-Serbok, ISBN 1–85168–176–0 A Concise Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Klaus K. Klostermaier, ISBN 1–85168–175–2 A Concise Encyclopedia of Christianity, Geoffrey Parrinder, ISBN 1–85168–174–4 A Concise Encyclopedia of Buddhism, John Powers, ISBN 1–85168–233–3 A Concise Encyclopedia of the Baha´’ı´ Faith, Peter Smith, ISBN 1–85168–184–1 A Concise Encyclopedia of Islam, Gordon D. Newby, ISBN 1–85168–295–3 related titles published by oneworld Ethics in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–247–3 The Fifth Dimension, John Hick, ISBN 1–85168–191–4 Global Philosophy of Religion: A Short Introduction, Joseph Runzo, ISBN 1–85168–235–X God: A Guide for the Perplexed, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–284–8 God, Faith and the New Millennium, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–155–8 Love, Sex and Gender in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–223–6 The Meaning of Life in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–200–7 The Phenomenon of Religion, Moojan Momen, ISBN 1–85168–161–2 ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION ANTHONY C. THISELTON A CONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Oneworld Publications (Sales and Editorial) 185 Banbury Road Oxford OX2 7AR England www.oneworld-publications.com # Anthony C. Thiselton 2002 All rights reserved. Copyright under Berne Convention A CIP record for this title is available from the British Library ISBN 1–85168–301–1 Cover design by Design Deluxe Typeset by LaserScript, Mitcham, UK Printed and bound in the United Kingdom by Bell & Bain Ltd, Glasgow NL08 Contents Preface and acknowledgements vi A Concise Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Religion 1 Chronology 329 Index of names 337 Preface and acknowledgements Aims, scope and target readership he following selection of subject entries has been shaped in the light of Tmany years of feedback from my own students.
    [Show full text]
  • A Further Reinterpretation of the Moral Philosophy of John Stuart Mill
    A FURTHER REINTERPRETATION OF THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF JOHN STUART MILL. by Derek Jo Banks M.A.9 University of Glasgow, 1970 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Philosophy 0 DEREK JOHN BANKS 1972 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY January 1972 Name : Derek J. Banks !iiitlc of '.thesis : li ir'urther deinterpretation of the Floral I'hilosophy of John ,Stuart Mill Examining Cornrni-ttee : Chairman: Kay Jennings """ Lionel Kenner Senior Supervisor P "-" Donald G. Brown Lxt ernal Axaminer &of essor of 'hilosophy University of British Columbia I ABSTRACT Those of Mill's critics who focus their attention on Utilitarianism assume that Mill must have held that certain ethical sentences, including one expressing the principle of utility, are properly describable as true. In this thesis I set out to demonstrate the spuriousness of this assumption. I begin by showing that in several important works - works which he thought much more highly of than he did Utilitarianism - Mill denied that the truth (or falsity) of any ethical sentences can ever be established. Next I produce evidence that his reason for this denial lies in his commitment to the view that ethical sentences are really disguised imperative sentences, and hence have no truth-value. Pinally, it is argued that there is nothing in Utilitarianism that is inconsistent with the meta-ethical position which we have found him to adopt in his other works related to ethics. In a short coneluding chapter I devote as much space as I deem permissible in a thesis of this type to show that reinterpretation of Mill's ethical theory on an imperative model renders it more plausible than it is generally taken to be, since all theories which allow truth-values to ethical sentences are open to knock-down objections.
    [Show full text]
  • A Perceptual Theory of Hope
    AN OPEN ACCESS Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY A Perceptual Theory of Hope MICHAEL MILONA Auburn University KATIE STOCKDALE1 Sam Houston State University This paper addresses the question of what the attitude of hope consists in. We ar- gue that shortcomings in recent theories of hope have methodological roots in that they proceed with little regard for the rich body of literature on the emotions. Taking insights from work in the philosophy of emotions, we argue that hope involves a kind of normative perception. We then develop a strategy for determining the con- tent of this perception, arguing that hope is a perception of practical reasons. Our proposal stands in contrast with familiar views on which hope is fundamentally about the good. We conclude by considering the increasingly popular idea that some hopes are non- intentional and thus, by implication, non- perceptual. We reply by arguing that our perceptual theory plausibly generalizes to these instances of hope. Keywords: hope, perception, emotion, moral psychology 1. Introduction The view that hope involves a desire for p and a belief that p’s obtaining is pos- sible but not certain has become known as the standard or orthodox account of hope (Martin 2014; Meirav 2009). Some philosophers think that the standard view is sufficient to capture some of our trivial hopes, like the hope that the sun will come out soon (Calhoun in press; Pettit 2004). There is widespread consen- sus in the literature, however, that the standard account cannot make sense of our most significant hopes, like the hope to be cured of cancer or the hope that a wrongdoer be brought to justice.
    [Show full text]
  • From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)
    From:214 L—rsmkv!rs—ks—syxsMichael Huemer,sm! Ethical Intuitionism (2005) finds Sally funny, but later decides he was mistaken about her funniness when the audience merely groans.) It seems, then, that humor subjectivism is far more defensible than moral subjectivism. One further point. Many examples of 'obviously subjective' properties may have evaluative components, and this will stymie any attempt to give them purely subjectivist analyses. 'If baby-killing i mpressed a lot of people, then baby-killing would be cool' is false because baby-killing is bad, and 'cool' implies 'good' (whatever else it implies). Similarly, in some cases, a person may argue that something is 'not funny' on moral grounds—for instance, that it is inappropriate to laugh at a thing because doing so would offend others or express a bad attitude. Perhaps 'funny' implies 'not bad to laugh at'. 'Sexy' may similarly imply 'not bad (or abnormal) to feel sexual attraction towards'. If this is so, then of course these concepts will resist purely subjectivist treatments, but that would not pose a challenge to the arguments of this book. :08 E}ur{zout gtj kznoiy 8.6.1 The evolutionary objection to realism Sociobiologists (or 'evolutionary psychologists', in the current lingo) have offered explanations for moral behavior and moral beliefs, in terms of the theory of evolution. Since evolution generally leads us to expect selfishness, the main problem has been taken to be that of explaining why we often help others at some cost to ourselves. Proffered partial explanations include: Kin selection: We help members of our own families, often at great expense to ourselves, because family members share many of the same genes.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberty University School of Divinity a Non
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Liberty University Digital Commons LIBERTY UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF DIVINITY A NON-VOLUNTARIST THEORY: AN ALTERNATE EVANGELICAL APOLOGETIC FOR DEALING WITH THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF LIBERTY UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF DIVINITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY EVAN TAYLOR POSEY LYNCHBURG, VIRGINIA OCTOBER 2016 APPROVAL SHEET A NON-VOLUNTARIST THEORY: AN ALTERNATE EVANGELICAL APOLOGETIC FOR DEALING WITH THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA Evan Taylor Posey Read and approved by: Chair Person: Richard A. Holland Reader: Edward N. Martin Reader: Anthony C. Thornhill Date: 10/9/2016 ii To my wife, Leslie-Ann, my children, and my family: There are no words that can adequately express my gratitude for your love, encouragement, and patience. iii CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ............................................................................................................ vi ABSTRACT ................................................................................................................................. viii CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................. 1 Statement of Purpose and Thesis ...................................................................................... 10 Definitions .......................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Humanist Liturgy and Proposals
    84 Toward Thinking Freely: Propositions (More and Less True) Concerning Humanism and Freethought (in no particular order) One believes in existence; Another says, "There is nothing!" Rare is the one who believes in neither. That one is free from confusion. Ashtavakra Gita 18:42 (500 BCE) 85 * * * There are many ponderous tomes concerning Humanism. Some are worth the time. Many are not. In the following pages I intend to be pithy, not ponderous, concerning living a life of humanistic freethought. * * * Keep in mind that there is no single Humanism. There are many human expressions of a life well-lived that can be termed Humanism. Hereafter, when I use the term, I mean a particular type of Humanism from a particular tradition. However, humility teaches of other ways and places of being across borders and boundaries of time, place, and culture. * * * There is no one way to be a Humanist or freethinker. Your viewpoint begins with your standpoint. * * * Some argue that the concept of the human has changed so much in the last century that it’s time to move from “humanism” to “post-humanism” as a way of signaling this turn of thought. I’m good with that. * * * Freethinkers and Humanists usually adopt a naturalistic and materialistic worldview. This worldview implies that there is no difference between body and mind (all thought is embodied thought) and that human beings are each a temporary congeries of matter that has before and will later appear in a different congeries. * * * A naturalistic and materialist viewpoint implies that all matter everywhere is of equal worth and importance, whether that matter appears as a human, a squirrel, a cloud, or 86 a rock.
    [Show full text]
  • An Unconnected Heap of Duties?
    An Unconnected Heap of Duties? Despite its name, the school of ethical intuitionism which flourished between the World Wars, and whose greatest proponents were Prichard and Ross, was not distinguished from its competitors by a distinctive epistemology. The dispute between intuitionism and its main rival, the utilitarian tradition, revolved around the issue of whether there was more than one fundamental moral principle.1 The utilitarian tradition in ethical thought can be represented as holding that there is just one fundamental duty or moral principle: the duty of beneficence. Ethical intuitionism rejected this monism as over- simple, and insisted that there is a number of distinct basic duties or moral principles.2 Both parties to this debate were taken to agree that an ethical theory must be based on intuition, by which was meant no more than that the most basic ethical principles, since they could not be inferred from more basic ones, must be self-evident.3 It has become commonplace to dismiss the deontic pluralism of an ethical intuitionist such as Ross fairly briskly. The two main charges are, first, that it is unsystematic, offering us merely a 'heap of unconnected duties' with no unifying rationale and, second, that it can give nothing in the way of general guidance to the agent who is faced with a conflict of duties, because it refuses to rank duties in order of importance or stringency.4 The intuitionists were, of course, aware of these objections; what I intend to show in this paper is that we can find, in the writings of W.D.
    [Show full text]
  • An Interdisciplinary Analysis of the Use of Ethical Intuition in Legal Compliance Decisionmaking for Business Entities Eric C
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Digital Commons @ UM Law Maryland Law Review Volume 74 | Issue 3 Article 3 An Interdisciplinary Analysis of the Use of Ethical Intuition in Legal Compliance Decisionmaking for Business Entities Eric C. Chaffee Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr Part of the Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, and the Legal Profession Commons Recommended Citation 74 Md. L. Rev. 497 (2015) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Academic Journals at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Maryland Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. AN INTERDISCIPLINARY ANALYSIS OF THE USE OF ETHICAL INTUITION IN LEGAL COMPLIANCE DECISIONMAKING FOR BUSINESS ENTITIES * ERIC C. CHAFFEE I. INTRODUCTION Amanda Appleton is a mid-level associate in the business law department of Boxer & Boxer LLP, a large international law firm. Her practice focuses on advising companies on matters re- lating to the regulation of publicly traded securities. She is well respected at the firm, and her prognosis for making partner is ex- cellent. At 11:30 AM yesterday morning, Paul Pratt, a partner in the business law department, called Appleton with an assignment. Global Giant Corporation is preparing to make various public disclosures by filing a Form 10-K with the Securities and Ex- change Commission (“SEC”). Pratt asked Appleton to research whether some of the proposed disclosures might be considered manipulative or deceptive in violation of various securities laws and regulations.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Intuitionism
    Ethical intuitionism Previous (Ethical Culture) (/entry/Ethical_Culture) Next (Ethics) (/entry/Ethics) Ethical intuitionism refers to a core of related moral theories, influential in Britain already in the 1700s, but coming to especial prominence in the work of G.E. Moore (/entry/G.E._Moore), H.A. Pritchard and W. D. Ross (/entry/W._D._Ross) in the earlier part of the twentieth century. Somewhat confusingly, however, the label ‘ethical intuitionism’ has had at least two distinct contemporary uses. Firstly, ‘intuitionism’ between the 1860s and 1920s was another name for unranked pluralism (/entry/Pluralism), the doctrine that there is a plurality of moral principles none of which is more basic than any other. In this respect, intuitionism is a normative ethical theory (/entry/Normative_ethics) contrasted with versions of monism (/entry/Monism)—the view that there is only one basic moral principle—such as utilitarianism (/entry/Utilitarianism), and Kantianism (/entry/Kantianism). Intuitionism in this sense is nowadays distinguished as methodological intuitionism. Secondly, and primarily, intuitionism in ethics refers to a cluster of theories Contents about how moral agents come to know which things are good, or which actions are right and wrong. This view may be distinguished as 1 Historical overview 2 Two senses of intuitionism epistemological (/entry/Epistemology) intuitionism, a theory of the way in 3 Varieties of epistemological which ethical propositions come to be grasped or known. The relationship intuitionism between these doctrines is primarily historical: important intuitionist thinkers 4 Arguments for intuitionism such as H.A. Pritchard and W.D. Ross embraced both methodological and 5 Objections to intuitionism epistemological intuitionism.
    [Show full text]
  • UTILITARIAN ETHICS New Studies in Ethics Edited by W
    NEW STUDIES IN ETHICS UTILITARIAN ETHICS New Studies in Ethics Edited by W. D. Hudson What is involved in judging_ a person to be moral or immoral, or in calling an action right or wrong? What makes a man good or an action our duty? Such questions as these, which concern the nature and content of morality, have been discussed by philoso­ phers from earliest times and are still live issues today. Many different types of ethical theory have emerged. New Studies in Ethics meets the need for an up-to-date examination of the main types. This series of monographs covers the whole range of ethical theory from Greek philosophers to the latest develop­ ments in contemporary moral philosophy. Each study is complete in itself and the whole series provides a unique treatment of the main philosophical problems in ethics. A distinguished team of philosophers, drawn from universities in Great Britain, the U.S.A. and Australia, was invited to prepare these studies. They have provided a series of monographs which will prove indispensable to university students of Moral Philo­ sophy, and will interest any intelligent reader. The Series H. B. Acton Kant's Moral Philosophy J. N. Findlay Axiological Ethics Antony Flew Evolutionary Ethics PamelaHuby Greek Ethics W.D.Hudson Ethical Intuitionism Eugene Kamenka Marxism and Ethics J. kemp Ethical Naturalism D. J. O'Connor Aquinas and Natural Law Anthony Quinton Utilitarian Ethics W. H. Walsh Hegelian Ethics, G. J. Warnock Existentialist Ethics Mary Warnock Contemporary Moral Philosophy Utilitarian Ethics ANTHONY QUINTON Fellow of New College, Oxford Palgrave Macmillan © Anthony Quinton 1973 All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]