Ethical Intuitionism: a Structural Critique

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ethical Intuitionism: a Structural Critique J Value Inquiry (2016) 50:631–647 DOI 10.1007/s10790-016-9547-8 Ethical Intuitionism: A Structural Critique Danny Frederick1 Published online: 8 February 2016 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 1 Introduction Recent years have seen attempts by many philosophers to rehabilitate, with some modifications, a traditional doctrine of ethical intuitionism (henceforward ‘‘intu- itionism’’). Contemporary intuitionists claim that moral knowledge consists of those propositions that are known by intellectual reflection (intuition), by moral observation or by moral emotion, or which are capable of being cogently inferred from propositions which are items of moral knowledge. Some intuitionists, such as Michael Huemer, admit only intuition (of particular or of general propositions) as a non-inferential source of moral knowledge; but others, such as Robert Audi, allow also moral observation and moral emotion. I offer a critique of contemporary intuitionist theories that depends upon their common structure: analysis of the abstract features of the approach show it to be an inadequate account of moral knowledge. I use Huemer and Audi as representative intuitionists. The differences between their views, and between their views and those of other intuitionists, are incidental at the level of generality of my argument. In section 2, I outline the contemporary intuitionist approach to moral knowledge. In sections 3, 4 and 5, I show that the problem of inter-cultural conflict undermines the claims that moral intuition, moral observation and moral emotion, respectively, are sources of non-inferential moral knowledge. I also explain the inadequacy of the intuitionist attempt to solve the problem by invoking bias or intellectual or moral failings. In section 6, I argue that the intuitionist attempt to solve the problem of conflict by attenuating the content of intuitive knowledge does not succeed. It also generates the further problem of explaining how insubstantial & Danny Frederick [email protected]; https://independent.academia.edu/DannyFrederick 1 Slate House, Hunstan Lane, Old Leake, Boston PE22 9RG, UK 123 632 D. Frederick moral premises can yield substantial moral knowledge. In section 7, I show that intuitionist appeals to analogies with mathematics and with empirical science are unsuccessful in solving that further problem. In section 8, I explain why Huemer’s defence of intuitionism by appeal to the principle of phenomenal conservatism fails. In section 9, I conclude. 2 Intuitionism The general account of moral knowledge offered by intuitionists is along the following lines (the deviations of some intuitionists from this general scheme are immaterial here). Let ‘‘p’’ stand for the expression of an evaluative proposition. If a person, A, knows that p, then, either the proposition represented by ‘‘p’’ can be inferred, cogently, from other knowledge of A,orA has intuitive knowledge that p. Intuitive knowledge is not dependent on inference from other beliefs: it is what seems true to a person independently of arguments for or against it. The sources of intuitive moral knowledge are intellectual reflection (intuition), or moral emotion, or observation of the moral properties of actions or of people. Intuitive moral knowledge is only prima facie justified: it may be overturned by conflicting moral knowledge which has stronger prima facie justification. Such conflicting moral knowledge is either intuitive or it is inferred, ultimately, from intuitive knowledge. The strength of prima facie justification depends upon how clearly the proposition seems true and how well it coheres with other intuitively known propositions, where a collection of propositions is more coherent the more it is systematic and unified and the greater the degree to which some propositions in the collection can explain others. Normally, an intuitive belief with which only a few people agree has weaker prima facie justification than a conflicting intuitive belief which nearly everyone shares. Moral intuitions, emotions or observations should be discounted if they are tainted by bias or by intellectual failings, such as confusion, inattention, distraction or cognitive impairment, or by moral failings, such as amorality or moral insensitivity. There are serious flaws in this account of moral knowledge. Only those which are most relevant here are explained in what follows. 3 Intuition An intuition is a state in which it seems that p, independently of inference, which results from reflection on, or an adequate understanding of, the proposition that p, and which, according to intuitionists, grounds intuitive knowledge that p (Huemer 2005, pp. 99–102, 124–25; Audi 2004, 45–54; 2013, pp. 83–100). It is sometimes objected that intuitions reflect prior beliefs, but according to Huemer: the view that intuitions are or are caused by beliefs fails to explain the origin of our moral beliefs. Undoubtedly some moral beliefs are accounted for by inference from other moral beliefs. But since no moral belief can be derived from wholly non-moral premises, we must start with some moral beliefs that 123 Ethical Intuitionism: A Structural Critique 633 are not inferred from any other beliefs. Where do these starting moral beliefs come from? Do we just adopt them entirely arbitrarily? No; this is not the phenomenology of moral belief. We adopt fundamental moral beliefs because they seem right to us; we don’t select them randomly (2005, p. 103). However, it seems that ‘‘this is not the phenomenology of moral belief’’ either. We do not adopt our starting moral beliefs because they seem right to us; we do not adopt them consciously at all. By the time a person is able to do anything so sophisticated as to consider whether to adopt a moral belief, she has spent years being inducted into a culture in which she has been trained to behave in ways that her immediate community deems acceptable, and to see things largely as her immediate community sees them, and she has been taught, in part by explicit instruction, an elaborate set of evaluative propositions. She has a panoply of moral beliefs that seem obvious to her, independently of any arguments, simply because they have been long induced in her via the varied processes of cultural transmission, often since before she can remember. She has not inferred those beliefs and she has not adopted them because they seem right. She finds that she simply has them. It is those beliefs that generate her initial intuitions, which are therefore cultural or sub-cultural artefacts. Her elders similarly inherited their starting moral views from their elders, though each generation makes modifications to the inherited fabric, which brings about cultural evolution. One might ask: how did our remote ancestors ever arrive at any moral views, if they could not have inferred them from their non-moral views? The answer seems to be that we evolved biologically as creatures with an inborn disposition to develop and use moral concepts (Pinker 2002, pp. 53, 168–69, 242–44), so we interpret the world in evaluative terms. Humans are creatures who expect the world to contain moral rules and who search for them, often mistaking evolved local regularities of behaviour for objective moral rules (Piaget 1929, chapter 7). Huemer objects (2005, pp. 103–104) that our intuitive judgements about real or imagined cases may run counter to previously held moral beliefs, such as act- utilitarianism. He concludes that our intuitions do not simply conform to our moral beliefs and that this gives intuition a role in adjudicating between rival moral theories. However, that reply is vitiated by a failure to distinguish two kinds of moral views. First, there are culturally inherited moral views, which generate our ethical intuitions, which are only in part articulated propositions, being in large part ways of seeing things that people learn from observing and imitating the behaviour of others, and which do not form an integrated system even within the same culture, but contain various internal conflicts (Hayek 1960, pp. 56–65). Second, there are articulated and systematic theories, such as act-utilitarianism, which are typically propounded by reformers who want to replace our culturally inherited views with something they take to be better. It is no surprise that our culturally inherited moral views generate intuitions at variance with the theories of reformers; and it would be pointless or invidious to test such theories against our intuitions. Many of our moral intuitions conflict with those of people from other cultures or sub-cultures, and these conflicting moral views are not always traceable to differences over factual matters (Doris and Stich 2005, pp. 129–37). For example, social-psychological research (Nisbett and Cohen 1996) has revealed that America’s 123 634 D. Frederick South differs from its North in having a strong honour culture which gives rise to people from the South having different moral intuitions to those of people from the North concerning whether violence is appropriate in some types of given (factually identical) situations. Such conflicting intuitions may seem to be equally clear to the people who hold them, though there does not appear to be any objective way of measuring that as yet; and they may also cohere equally well with the other propositions accepted by the respective people. The intuitions may also be widely shared within their respective cultural groups. Such conflicting intuitions appear to have equal strength of ‘‘prima facie justification’’ for their respective adherents, which undermines the intuitionist claim that intuitions ground moral knowledge. It is worth noticing that it is not the fact that moral intuitions are cultural artefacts that undermines their epistemic status. Scientific knowledge is a cultural artefact. Further, it is not the case that conflict between the intuitions of people from different cultures is sufficient to discredit the epistemic status of all the conflicting intuitions. What the conflict between the moral intuitions of people from different cultures does undermine is the claim that moral intuitions are sources of non-inferential moral knowledge.
Recommended publications
  • Kantian Intuitionism
    An Intuitionist Response to Moral Scepticism A critique of Mackie's scepticism, and an alternative proposal combining Ross's intuitionism with a Kantian epistemology by Simon John Duffy PhD The University of Edinburgh 2001 PhD Thesis: An Intuitionist Response to Moral Scepticism - Page 1 CONTENTS ABSTRACT .................................................................................................................................................................... 4 DECLARATION .................................................................................................................................................................... 5 INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................................................................................... 6 1 .................................................................................................................................................................... OUR BELIEFS ABOUT MORALITY .................................................................................................................................................................... 11 1.1 WHAT DO WE OWE COMMON-SENSE? .11 1.2 OUR EVERYDAY CONCEPTION OF ETHICS .17 1.3 THE CENTRALITY OF DUTY .24 1.4 THE IMPLICATIONS OF DUTY .32 2 .................................................................................................................................................................... THE SCEPTICAL ATTACK ...................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • ¼ PHILOSOPHY of RELIGION.Pdf
    ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION other books in the same series A Concise Encyclopedia of Judaism, Dan Cohn-Serbok, ISBN 1–85168–176–0 A Concise Encyclopedia of Hinduism, Klaus K. Klostermaier, ISBN 1–85168–175–2 A Concise Encyclopedia of Christianity, Geoffrey Parrinder, ISBN 1–85168–174–4 A Concise Encyclopedia of Buddhism, John Powers, ISBN 1–85168–233–3 A Concise Encyclopedia of the Baha´’ı´ Faith, Peter Smith, ISBN 1–85168–184–1 A Concise Encyclopedia of Islam, Gordon D. Newby, ISBN 1–85168–295–3 related titles published by oneworld Ethics in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–247–3 The Fifth Dimension, John Hick, ISBN 1–85168–191–4 Global Philosophy of Religion: A Short Introduction, Joseph Runzo, ISBN 1–85168–235–X God: A Guide for the Perplexed, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–284–8 God, Faith and the New Millennium, Keith Ward, ISBN 1–85168–155–8 Love, Sex and Gender in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–223–6 The Meaning of Life in the World Religions, Edited by Joseph Runzo and Nancy M. Martin, ISBN 1–85168–200–7 The Phenomenon of Religion, Moojan Momen, ISBN 1–85168–161–2 ACONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA of the PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION ANTHONY C. THISELTON A CONCISE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Oneworld Publications (Sales and Editorial) 185 Banbury Road Oxford OX2 7AR England www.oneworld-publications.com # Anthony C. Thiselton 2002 All rights reserved. Copyright under Berne Convention A CIP record for this title is available from the British Library ISBN 1–85168–301–1 Cover design by Design Deluxe Typeset by LaserScript, Mitcham, UK Printed and bound in the United Kingdom by Bell & Bain Ltd, Glasgow NL08 Contents Preface and acknowledgements vi A Concise Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Religion 1 Chronology 329 Index of names 337 Preface and acknowledgements Aims, scope and target readership he following selection of subject entries has been shaped in the light of Tmany years of feedback from my own students.
    [Show full text]
  • A Further Reinterpretation of the Moral Philosophy of John Stuart Mill
    A FURTHER REINTERPRETATION OF THE MORAL PHILOSOPHY OF JOHN STUART MILL. by Derek Jo Banks M.A.9 University of Glasgow, 1970 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Philosophy 0 DEREK JOHN BANKS 1972 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY January 1972 Name : Derek J. Banks !iiitlc of '.thesis : li ir'urther deinterpretation of the Floral I'hilosophy of John ,Stuart Mill Examining Cornrni-ttee : Chairman: Kay Jennings """ Lionel Kenner Senior Supervisor P "-" Donald G. Brown Lxt ernal Axaminer &of essor of 'hilosophy University of British Columbia I ABSTRACT Those of Mill's critics who focus their attention on Utilitarianism assume that Mill must have held that certain ethical sentences, including one expressing the principle of utility, are properly describable as true. In this thesis I set out to demonstrate the spuriousness of this assumption. I begin by showing that in several important works - works which he thought much more highly of than he did Utilitarianism - Mill denied that the truth (or falsity) of any ethical sentences can ever be established. Next I produce evidence that his reason for this denial lies in his commitment to the view that ethical sentences are really disguised imperative sentences, and hence have no truth-value. Pinally, it is argued that there is nothing in Utilitarianism that is inconsistent with the meta-ethical position which we have found him to adopt in his other works related to ethics. In a short coneluding chapter I devote as much space as I deem permissible in a thesis of this type to show that reinterpretation of Mill's ethical theory on an imperative model renders it more plausible than it is generally taken to be, since all theories which allow truth-values to ethical sentences are open to knock-down objections.
    [Show full text]
  • A Perceptual Theory of Hope
    AN OPEN ACCESS Ergo JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY A Perceptual Theory of Hope MICHAEL MILONA Auburn University KATIE STOCKDALE1 Sam Houston State University This paper addresses the question of what the attitude of hope consists in. We ar- gue that shortcomings in recent theories of hope have methodological roots in that they proceed with little regard for the rich body of literature on the emotions. Taking insights from work in the philosophy of emotions, we argue that hope involves a kind of normative perception. We then develop a strategy for determining the con- tent of this perception, arguing that hope is a perception of practical reasons. Our proposal stands in contrast with familiar views on which hope is fundamentally about the good. We conclude by considering the increasingly popular idea that some hopes are non- intentional and thus, by implication, non- perceptual. We reply by arguing that our perceptual theory plausibly generalizes to these instances of hope. Keywords: hope, perception, emotion, moral psychology 1. Introduction The view that hope involves a desire for p and a belief that p’s obtaining is pos- sible but not certain has become known as the standard or orthodox account of hope (Martin 2014; Meirav 2009). Some philosophers think that the standard view is sufficient to capture some of our trivial hopes, like the hope that the sun will come out soon (Calhoun in press; Pettit 2004). There is widespread consen- sus in the literature, however, that the standard account cannot make sense of our most significant hopes, like the hope to be cured of cancer or the hope that a wrongdoer be brought to justice.
    [Show full text]
  • From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)
    From:214 L—rsmkv!rs—ks—syxsMichael Huemer,sm! Ethical Intuitionism (2005) finds Sally funny, but later decides he was mistaken about her funniness when the audience merely groans.) It seems, then, that humor subjectivism is far more defensible than moral subjectivism. One further point. Many examples of 'obviously subjective' properties may have evaluative components, and this will stymie any attempt to give them purely subjectivist analyses. 'If baby-killing i mpressed a lot of people, then baby-killing would be cool' is false because baby-killing is bad, and 'cool' implies 'good' (whatever else it implies). Similarly, in some cases, a person may argue that something is 'not funny' on moral grounds—for instance, that it is inappropriate to laugh at a thing because doing so would offend others or express a bad attitude. Perhaps 'funny' implies 'not bad to laugh at'. 'Sexy' may similarly imply 'not bad (or abnormal) to feel sexual attraction towards'. If this is so, then of course these concepts will resist purely subjectivist treatments, but that would not pose a challenge to the arguments of this book. :08 E}ur{zout gtj kznoiy 8.6.1 The evolutionary objection to realism Sociobiologists (or 'evolutionary psychologists', in the current lingo) have offered explanations for moral behavior and moral beliefs, in terms of the theory of evolution. Since evolution generally leads us to expect selfishness, the main problem has been taken to be that of explaining why we often help others at some cost to ourselves. Proffered partial explanations include: Kin selection: We help members of our own families, often at great expense to ourselves, because family members share many of the same genes.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberty University School of Divinity a Non
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Liberty University Digital Commons LIBERTY UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF DIVINITY A NON-VOLUNTARIST THEORY: AN ALTERNATE EVANGELICAL APOLOGETIC FOR DEALING WITH THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF LIBERTY UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF DIVINITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY EVAN TAYLOR POSEY LYNCHBURG, VIRGINIA OCTOBER 2016 APPROVAL SHEET A NON-VOLUNTARIST THEORY: AN ALTERNATE EVANGELICAL APOLOGETIC FOR DEALING WITH THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA Evan Taylor Posey Read and approved by: Chair Person: Richard A. Holland Reader: Edward N. Martin Reader: Anthony C. Thornhill Date: 10/9/2016 ii To my wife, Leslie-Ann, my children, and my family: There are no words that can adequately express my gratitude for your love, encouragement, and patience. iii CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ............................................................................................................ vi ABSTRACT ................................................................................................................................. viii CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................. 1 Statement of Purpose and Thesis ...................................................................................... 10 Definitions .......................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Humanist Liturgy and Proposals
    84 Toward Thinking Freely: Propositions (More and Less True) Concerning Humanism and Freethought (in no particular order) One believes in existence; Another says, "There is nothing!" Rare is the one who believes in neither. That one is free from confusion. Ashtavakra Gita 18:42 (500 BCE) 85 * * * There are many ponderous tomes concerning Humanism. Some are worth the time. Many are not. In the following pages I intend to be pithy, not ponderous, concerning living a life of humanistic freethought. * * * Keep in mind that there is no single Humanism. There are many human expressions of a life well-lived that can be termed Humanism. Hereafter, when I use the term, I mean a particular type of Humanism from a particular tradition. However, humility teaches of other ways and places of being across borders and boundaries of time, place, and culture. * * * There is no one way to be a Humanist or freethinker. Your viewpoint begins with your standpoint. * * * Some argue that the concept of the human has changed so much in the last century that it’s time to move from “humanism” to “post-humanism” as a way of signaling this turn of thought. I’m good with that. * * * Freethinkers and Humanists usually adopt a naturalistic and materialistic worldview. This worldview implies that there is no difference between body and mind (all thought is embodied thought) and that human beings are each a temporary congeries of matter that has before and will later appear in a different congeries. * * * A naturalistic and materialist viewpoint implies that all matter everywhere is of equal worth and importance, whether that matter appears as a human, a squirrel, a cloud, or 86 a rock.
    [Show full text]
  • An Unconnected Heap of Duties?
    An Unconnected Heap of Duties? Despite its name, the school of ethical intuitionism which flourished between the World Wars, and whose greatest proponents were Prichard and Ross, was not distinguished from its competitors by a distinctive epistemology. The dispute between intuitionism and its main rival, the utilitarian tradition, revolved around the issue of whether there was more than one fundamental moral principle.1 The utilitarian tradition in ethical thought can be represented as holding that there is just one fundamental duty or moral principle: the duty of beneficence. Ethical intuitionism rejected this monism as over- simple, and insisted that there is a number of distinct basic duties or moral principles.2 Both parties to this debate were taken to agree that an ethical theory must be based on intuition, by which was meant no more than that the most basic ethical principles, since they could not be inferred from more basic ones, must be self-evident.3 It has become commonplace to dismiss the deontic pluralism of an ethical intuitionist such as Ross fairly briskly. The two main charges are, first, that it is unsystematic, offering us merely a 'heap of unconnected duties' with no unifying rationale and, second, that it can give nothing in the way of general guidance to the agent who is faced with a conflict of duties, because it refuses to rank duties in order of importance or stringency.4 The intuitionists were, of course, aware of these objections; what I intend to show in this paper is that we can find, in the writings of W.D.
    [Show full text]
  • An Interdisciplinary Analysis of the Use of Ethical Intuition in Legal Compliance Decisionmaking for Business Entities Eric C
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Digital Commons @ UM Law Maryland Law Review Volume 74 | Issue 3 Article 3 An Interdisciplinary Analysis of the Use of Ethical Intuition in Legal Compliance Decisionmaking for Business Entities Eric C. Chaffee Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr Part of the Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, and the Legal Profession Commons Recommended Citation 74 Md. L. Rev. 497 (2015) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Academic Journals at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Maryland Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. AN INTERDISCIPLINARY ANALYSIS OF THE USE OF ETHICAL INTUITION IN LEGAL COMPLIANCE DECISIONMAKING FOR BUSINESS ENTITIES * ERIC C. CHAFFEE I. INTRODUCTION Amanda Appleton is a mid-level associate in the business law department of Boxer & Boxer LLP, a large international law firm. Her practice focuses on advising companies on matters re- lating to the regulation of publicly traded securities. She is well respected at the firm, and her prognosis for making partner is ex- cellent. At 11:30 AM yesterday morning, Paul Pratt, a partner in the business law department, called Appleton with an assignment. Global Giant Corporation is preparing to make various public disclosures by filing a Form 10-K with the Securities and Ex- change Commission (“SEC”). Pratt asked Appleton to research whether some of the proposed disclosures might be considered manipulative or deceptive in violation of various securities laws and regulations.
    [Show full text]
  • Seeing Right from Wrong: a Defense of a Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism
    Syracuse University SURFACE Dissertations - ALL SURFACE July 2016 Seeing Right from Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism Preston John Werner Syracuse University Follow this and additional works at: https://surface.syr.edu/etd Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Werner, Preston John, "Seeing Right from Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism" (2016). Dissertations - ALL. 532. https://surface.syr.edu/etd/532 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the SURFACE at SURFACE. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations - ALL by an authorized administrator of SURFACE. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Preston J. Werner Seeing What’s Right and Wrong: A Defense of A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism Dissertation Abstract This dissertation develops and defends A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism, the view that our epistemic access to moral properties is grounded in perceptual experience. It contains two parts. In part I, I present the epistemic access problem for realist moral epistemology and argue against several a priori attempts to resolve it. In part II, I defend A Posteriori Ethical Intuitionism and its ability to resolve the epistemic access problem. Part I begins by arguing that evolutionary debunking arguments are best understood as claiming that we lack epistemic access to mind-independent moral facts. The remainder of part I rejects several attempts to respond to this challenge. I first argue that even sophisticated versions of reflective equilibrium, as coherentist theories, fall victim to a “garbage in, garbage out” objection. I conclude that a proper solution to the epistemic access problem must be foundationalist.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Intuitionism
    Ethical intuitionism Previous (Ethical Culture) (/entry/Ethical_Culture) Next (Ethics) (/entry/Ethics) Ethical intuitionism refers to a core of related moral theories, influential in Britain already in the 1700s, but coming to especial prominence in the work of G.E. Moore (/entry/G.E._Moore), H.A. Pritchard and W. D. Ross (/entry/W._D._Ross) in the earlier part of the twentieth century. Somewhat confusingly, however, the label ‘ethical intuitionism’ has had at least two distinct contemporary uses. Firstly, ‘intuitionism’ between the 1860s and 1920s was another name for unranked pluralism (/entry/Pluralism), the doctrine that there is a plurality of moral principles none of which is more basic than any other. In this respect, intuitionism is a normative ethical theory (/entry/Normative_ethics) contrasted with versions of monism (/entry/Monism)—the view that there is only one basic moral principle—such as utilitarianism (/entry/Utilitarianism), and Kantianism (/entry/Kantianism). Intuitionism in this sense is nowadays distinguished as methodological intuitionism. Secondly, and primarily, intuitionism in ethics refers to a cluster of theories Contents about how moral agents come to know which things are good, or which actions are right and wrong. This view may be distinguished as 1 Historical overview 2 Two senses of intuitionism epistemological (/entry/Epistemology) intuitionism, a theory of the way in 3 Varieties of epistemological which ethical propositions come to be grasped or known. The relationship intuitionism between these doctrines is primarily historical: important intuitionist thinkers 4 Arguments for intuitionism such as H.A. Pritchard and W.D. Ross embraced both methodological and 5 Objections to intuitionism epistemological intuitionism.
    [Show full text]
  • UTILITARIAN ETHICS New Studies in Ethics Edited by W
    NEW STUDIES IN ETHICS UTILITARIAN ETHICS New Studies in Ethics Edited by W. D. Hudson What is involved in judging_ a person to be moral or immoral, or in calling an action right or wrong? What makes a man good or an action our duty? Such questions as these, which concern the nature and content of morality, have been discussed by philoso­ phers from earliest times and are still live issues today. Many different types of ethical theory have emerged. New Studies in Ethics meets the need for an up-to-date examination of the main types. This series of monographs covers the whole range of ethical theory from Greek philosophers to the latest develop­ ments in contemporary moral philosophy. Each study is complete in itself and the whole series provides a unique treatment of the main philosophical problems in ethics. A distinguished team of philosophers, drawn from universities in Great Britain, the U.S.A. and Australia, was invited to prepare these studies. They have provided a series of monographs which will prove indispensable to university students of Moral Philo­ sophy, and will interest any intelligent reader. The Series H. B. Acton Kant's Moral Philosophy J. N. Findlay Axiological Ethics Antony Flew Evolutionary Ethics PamelaHuby Greek Ethics W.D.Hudson Ethical Intuitionism Eugene Kamenka Marxism and Ethics J. kemp Ethical Naturalism D. J. O'Connor Aquinas and Natural Law Anthony Quinton Utilitarian Ethics W. H. Walsh Hegelian Ethics, G. J. Warnock Existentialist Ethics Mary Warnock Contemporary Moral Philosophy Utilitarian Ethics ANTHONY QUINTON Fellow of New College, Oxford Palgrave Macmillan © Anthony Quinton 1973 All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]