Seeing Fictions in Film: the Epistemology of Movies by Wilson

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Seeing Fictions in Film: the Epistemology of Movies by Wilson Book Reviews Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/4/393/5980300 by guest on 24 September 2021 wilson, george m. Seeing Fictions in Film: The Episte- stantly with the narrational and dramatic devices of mology of Movies. Oxford University Press, 2011, Hollywood melodrama in order to highlight the na- viii + 220 pp., $45.00 cloth. ture of the genre itself. In Chapter 9, Wilson argues that the Coen brothers’ film The Man Who Wasn’t There is no doubt that this is a difficult book. The There (2001) modulates the objectivity of its narra- question is whether Seeing Fictions in Film has to be tion according to the shifts in the protagonist’s rela- so difficult and whether working through its argu- tion to others. Even though these final chapters do ments is worth the reader’s effort. Happily, the an- not explicitly address imagined seeing and the status swer to these questions is a definitive yes. In its com- of narration, they demonstrate that close interpreta- plexity and subtlety, the book reveals just what is at tive work is essential to understanding how movies stake in the recent debate about cinematic narration. tell stories. The reader is informed of all the points of confusion Returning to the book’s central thesis, the Imag- and misdirection in this debate. She is then asked ined Seeing Thesis’s (IST) precise specification is to focus on what is really important and consider crucial in the face of preexisting skepticism about a controversial but richly suggestive view about the the role of imagined seeing in fiction film engage- imaginative grounds and distinctive means of cine- ment. First, Wilson rejects the “face-to-face” version matic narration. Many of the components of this view of IST, the version on which “viewers imagine see- are familiar from Wilson’s earlier work, particularly ing segments of the fictional world from a position from a series of fascinating articles appearing be- face-to-face with the segments in question,” on the tween 1997 and 2007. But the book-length treatment grounds that we are never or rarely meant to imag- serves to reveal the continuity of Wilson’s thinking ine being at a vantage point inside a fiction (p. 78). while providing greater stress, elaboration, context, The question is then whether we can make sense of and new responses to recent objections. imagining seeing from an “unoccupied perspective.” The central thesis of Seeing Fictions in Film can Wilson thinks that we can: on the “mediated version” besummedupasfollows.Infictionfilm,thestan- of IST, we imagine seeing depicted fictional events dard function of the image track is to prescribe what indirectly, through “transparently derived” images, viewers imagine seeing in the fiction. In performing and so without being involved in or even present at this function, the image track constitutes a (fictional) fictional events. Of course, for the mediated version narration of the story, a kind of visual narration dis- of IST to be a version of IST at all requires accep- tinctive to cinema (pp. 9–10). There are, of course, tance of the controversial thesis, famously defended as Wilson regularly acknowledges, a parallel set of by Kendall Walton, that certain kinds of images are claims to be made about the sound track in fiction transparent such that we can see through them. Just films. But his focus is on defending the claim that as controversial is Wilson’s further commitment to “imagined seeing” is the “primitive basis” for cine- the indeterminacy of our means of access to the vi- matic narration. The first seeds of the defense are sual narration: we are not meant to imagine anything planted in the book’s introduction, and, in the next about how we came to be viewing a transparent visual seven chapters, we follow its complicated and fecund record of fictional events. growth. Chapters 8 and 9 are then devoted to film in- Wilson’s appeal to fictional indeterminacy in re- terpretation. In Chapter 8, Wilson considers the last sponse to worries about the absurd implications of three films that Josef von Sternberg made with Mar- imagined seeing is familiar from some of his earlier lene Dietrich. Through close structural and thematic work. As before, in Seeing Fictions in Film the appeal analysis, Wilson demonstrates how the films play con- rests on a comparison between literary and cinematic The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 70:4 Fall 2012 c 2012 The American Society for Aesthetics 394 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism narration: just as it remains fictionally indeterminate of IST. Given his commitment to IST, Wilson’s inter- how we came to be reading Lemuel Gulliver’s travel est in narrators is limited to the question of whether log, so it remains fictionally indeterminate how we the style of narration in particular films engenders came to be seeing Charles Foster Kane alone on something more than a “minimal” narrating agency. his deathbed. Once the general plausibility of nar- Returning to the explanatory power of IST, Wilson rational indeterminacy in fiction film has been estab- argues that the mediated version is positively recom- lished, the book introduces a new analogy. This one is mended over the face-to-face version by its allowing between radio plays and fiction films, and it is used to us to mark the differences in our experience of the support the further claim that, in the case of movies, diegetic and nondiegetic visual qualities of a movie indeterminacy sets in specifically between imagined shot. In addition, two important differences between Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/jaac/article/70/4/393/5980300 by guest on 24 September 2021 seeing and imagining being at a vantage point inside kinds of epistemic access to a movie narrative need the fiction (pp. 82–84). The new argument turns on explaining with IST: the difference between know- the claim that, in response to radio plays, we imagine ing something happens in a movie because we “see” hearing fictional sounds in rough spatial relation to it happen versus knowing something happens in the one another, but without imagining being in the space movie that is not shown, on the basis of reasonable of those sounds. Wilson carefully and colorfully elab- inference; and the difference between knowing that orates this claim to bring out its intuitiveness. Unfor- what we “see” in the movie is really happening in the tunately, however, its implications for the cinematic story world versus only in the mind of a character, as case remain unclear: important differences between a dream or hallucination. movies and radio plays may make an imagined van- These phenomenal and epistemic differences are tage point more likely in the former case than in richly illustrated and carefully specified by Wilson. If the latter. For instance, it is unclear whether Wilson we can make sense of the notion of mediated imag- has the means to explain an important difference in ined seeing, the case for its explanatory power is our movie experience between seeing the contents compelling. But can we make sense of this notion? of a shot with a fixed frame and seeing the contents Leaving aside the question of whether seeing can of a shot with a moving frame. The most straight- ever be mediated, there is still a question of what forward explanation of the experienced difference makes a certain kind of imaginative experience, had would surely appeal to whether we are prescribed to in response to what we see, itself a kind of seeing. imagine seeing from a fixed or from a moving van- Wilson describes the relevant sense of imagined see- tage point. But to explain this difference, it seems ing as an imaginative impression as if one is seeing difficult to avoid appealing to a prescription to imag- what is depicted in a fiction film, a kind of impression ine something about our vantage point. distinct from hallucination, from mistaken visual im- Clearly, more needs to be said about the precise pressions of other kinds, and from inner visualization role of fictional indeterminacy in our imaginative (pp. 72–74). But the distinction between imagined experience of a film’s visual narration. But Wilson seeing and other kinds of nonveridical seeing is not would be the first to admit as much: throughout See- entirely clear. The sense in which we see a werewolf ing Fictions in Film, he makes clear that his aim is to in a movie is easily distinguishable from the sense in show that the right version of IST can stand up against which we deliberately conjure up a werewolf in the the initial charges of absurdity and confusion. Once mind’s eye. But it is not so easily distinguishable from IST has been given a fighting chance, we can con- other forms of passive and unintended visualization, sider its explanatory power. And only then is it even like the kind potentially involved in amodal percep- worth considering the issue that has tended to dom- tion whereby we represent occluded parts of per- inate the current debate, that is, whether narrative ceived objects. Furthermore, there is a question about fiction films have implicit visual narrators. Chapter the precise nature of the relation between veridical 6ofSeeing Fictions in Film takes up this issue, but seeing (our actually seeing a visual representation of not in the usual way. Early on in the chapter, Wilson the werewolf) and imagined seeing. renders trivial the question of the ubiquity of implicit This relation could simply be causal: imagined see- visual narrators in light of a commitment to films hav- ing is prompted by actually seeing a visual represen- ing, as part of their fictions, a visual narration, or a tation.
Recommended publications
  • A ADVENTURE C COMEDY Z CRIME O DOCUMENTARY D DRAMA E
    MOVIES A TO Z MARCH 2021 Ho u The 39 Steps (1935) 3/5 c Blondie of the Follies (1932) 3/2 Czechoslovakia on Parade (1938) 3/27 a ADVENTURE u 6,000 Enemies (1939) 3/5 u Blood Simple (1984) 3/19 z Bonnie and Clyde (1967) 3/30, 3/31 –––––––––––––––––––––– D ––––––––––––––––––––––– –––––––––––––––––––––– ––––––––––––––––––––––– c COMEDY A D Born to Love (1931) 3/16 m Dancing Lady (1933) 3/23 a Adventure (1945) 3/4 D Bottles (1936) 3/13 D Dancing Sweeties (1930) 3/24 z CRIME a The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn (1960) 3/23 P c The Bowery Boys Meet the Monsters (1954) 3/26 m The Daughter of Rosie O’Grady (1950) 3/17 a The Adventures of Robin Hood (1938) 3/9 c Boy Meets Girl (1938) 3/4 w The Dawn Patrol (1938) 3/1 o DOCUMENTARY R The Age of Consent (1932) 3/10 h Brainstorm (1983) 3/30 P D Death’s Fireworks (1935) 3/20 D All Fall Down (1962) 3/30 c Breakfast at Tiffany’s (1961) 3/18 m The Desert Song (1943) 3/3 D DRAMA D Anatomy of a Murder (1959) 3/20 e The Bridge on the River Kwai (1957) 3/27 R Devotion (1946) 3/9 m Anchors Aweigh (1945) 3/9 P R Brief Encounter (1945) 3/25 D Diary of a Country Priest (1951) 3/14 e EPIC D Andy Hardy Comes Home (1958) 3/3 P Hc Bring on the Girls (1937) 3/6 e Doctor Zhivago (1965) 3/18 c Andy Hardy Gets Spring Fever (1939) 3/20 m Broadway to Hollywood (1933) 3/24 D Doom’s Brink (1935) 3/6 HORROR/SCIENCE-FICTION R The Angel Wore Red (1960) 3/21 z Brute Force (1947) 3/5 D Downstairs (1932) 3/6 D Anna Christie (1930) 3/29 z Bugsy Malone (1976) 3/23 P u The Dragon Murder Case (1934) 3/13 m MUSICAL c April In Paris
    [Show full text]
  • Midas' Servant, Ceyx, Morpheus As Ceyx, Orpheus, Apollo, A, Philemon
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2007 Playing the Third Man (Midas' Servant, Ceyx, Morpheus as Ceyx, Orpheus, Apollo, A, Philemon) in Mary Zimmerman's Metamorphoses: a production thesis Ronald Ludlow Reeder Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Theatre and Performance Studies Commons Recommended Citation Reeder, Ronald Ludlow, "Playing the Third Man (Midas' Servant, Ceyx, Morpheus as Ceyx, Orpheus, Apollo, A, Philemon) in Mary Zimmerman's Metamorphoses: a production thesis" (2007). LSU Master's Theses. 3653. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/3653 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PLAYING THE THIRD MAN (MIDAS’ SERVANT, CEYX, MORPHEUS AS CEYX, ORPHEUS, APOLLO, A, PHILEMON) IN MARY ZIMMERMAN’S METAMORPHOSES: A PRODUCTION THESIS A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural And Mechanical College In partial fulfillment of the Requirements for the degree of Master of Fine Arts In The Department of Theatre By Ronald Ludlow Reeder B.F.A., University of Texas at Austin, 1991 B.S., University of Texas at Austin, 1994 May, 2007 TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT……………………………………………………………...………………iii
    [Show full text]
  • The Third Man"
    "THE THIRD MAN" by Graham Greene HIGH ANGLE - FULL SHOT - CITY OF VIENNA The title VIENNA SUPERIMPOSED FADES OUT - commentary commences. COMMENTATOR I never knew the old Vienna before the war, with its - MED. SHOT - STATUE OF A VIOLINIST There is snow on it. COMMENTATOR Strauss music, its glamour and easy charm... MED. SHOT - ROW OF STONE STATUES ornamenting the top of a building. In the b.g. the top of a stone archway. They are snow-sprinkled. COMMENTATOR Constantinople suited... MED. SHOT - SNOW-COVERED STATUE Trees in b.g. COMMENTATOR me better. I really got to know it in the... CLOSE SHOT - TWO MEN talking in the street. COMMENTATOR - classic period of the black... CLOSEUP - SUITCASE opens toward camera, revealing contents consisting of tins of food, shoes, etc. The hands of a man come in from f.g. to take something out. COMMENTATOR - market. We'd run anything... CLOSEUP - HANDS OF TWO PEOPLE standing side by side in the street. The person CL running hands through a pair of silk stockings. COMMENTATOR - if people wanted it enough. CLOSEUP - HANDS OF TWO PEOPLE A woman's hands CL wearing a wedding ring - a man's hands CR holding in RH two small cartons - hands them over to her in exchange for some notes which she hands him. COMMENTATOR - and had the money to pay. CLOSE SHOT - FIVE WRIST WATCHES on a man's wrist from which the coat sleeve is turned back. COMMENTATOR Of course a situation like that - LONG SHOT - CAPSIZED SHIP in shallow water with a drowned body floating on the water CR of it.
    [Show full text]
  • Gender and the Family in Contemporary Chinese-Language Film Remakes
    Gender and the family in contemporary Chinese-language film remakes Sarah Woodland BBusMan., BA (Hons) A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at The University of Queensland in 2016 School of Languages and Cultures 1 Abstract This thesis argues that cinematic remakes in the Chinese cultural context are a far more complex phenomenon than adaptive translation between disparate cultures. While early work conducted on French cinema and recent work on Chinese-language remakes by scholars including Li, Chan and Wang focused primarily on issues of intercultural difference, this thesis looks not only at remaking across cultures, but also at intracultural remakes. In doing so, it moves beyond questions of cultural politics, taking full advantage of the unique opportunity provided by remakes to compare and contrast two versions of the same narrative, and investigates more broadly at the many reasons why changes between a source film and remake might occur. Using gender as a lens through which these changes can be observed, this thesis conducts a comparative analysis of two pairs of intercultural and two pairs of intracultural films, each chapter highlighting a different dimension of remakes, and illustrating how changes in gender representations can be reflective not just of differences in attitudes towards gender across cultures, but also of broader concerns relating to culture, genre, auteurism, politics and temporality. The thesis endeavours to investigate the complexities of remaking processes in a Chinese-language cinematic context, with a view to exploring the ways in which remakes might reflect different perspectives on Chinese society more broadly, through their ability to compel the viewer to reflect not only on the past, by virtue of the relationship with a source text, but also on the present, through the way in which the remake reshapes this text to address its audience.
    [Show full text]
  • Film Film Film Film
    Annette Michelson’s contribution to art and film criticism over the last three decades has been un- paralleled. This volume honors Michelson’s unique C AMERA OBSCURA, CAMERA LUCIDA ALLEN AND TURVEY [EDS.] LUCIDA CAMERA OBSCURA, AMERA legacy with original essays by some of the many film FILM FILM scholars influenced by her work. Some continue her efforts to develop historical and theoretical frame- CULTURE CULTURE works for understanding modernist art, while others IN TRANSITION IN TRANSITION practice her form of interdisciplinary scholarship in relation to avant-garde and modernist film. The intro- duction investigates and evaluates Michelson’s work itself. All in some way pay homage to her extraordi- nary contribution and demonstrate its continued cen- trality to the field of art and film criticism. Richard Allen is Associ- ate Professor of Cinema Studies at New York Uni- versity. Malcolm Turvey teaches Film History at Sarah Lawrence College. They recently collaborated in editing Wittgenstein, Theory and the Arts (Lon- don: Routledge, 2001). CAMERA OBSCURA CAMERA LUCIDA ISBN 90-5356-494-2 Essays in Honor of Annette Michelson EDITED BY RICHARD ALLEN 9 789053 564943 MALCOLM TURVEY Amsterdam University Press Amsterdam University Press WWW.AUP.NL Camera Obscura, Camera Lucida Camera Obscura, Camera Lucida: Essays in Honor of Annette Michelson Edited by Richard Allen and Malcolm Turvey Amsterdam University Press Front cover illustration: 2001: A Space Odyssey. Courtesy of Photofest Cover design: Kok Korpershoek, Amsterdam Lay-out: japes, Amsterdam isbn 90 5356 494 2 (paperback) nur 652 © Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam, 2003 All rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of this book may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, me- chanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise) without the written permis- sion of both the copyright owner and the author of the book.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and Film Philosophy 328 Spring 2013 Instructor
    Philosophy and Film Philosophy 328 Spring 2013 Instructor: Professor Dan Flory Office: 2-106 Wilson Hall Office hours: M, 11 AM-noon, WF, 1-2 PM, and by appointment Office phone: 994-5209 E-mail: [email protected] Course Description This course examines the philosophy of film and film aesthetics. Topics we will investigate include: • how can film function as philosophy? • how do films elicit emotion? • how do we engage with narrative characters in film? • what is genre? How does it affect our understanding of a film? • how do different forms of cinematic narration affect viewer understanding? • how does the concept of ‘race’ have an impact on our perception and understanding of film characters? We will explore these issues primarily through the careful analysis of philosophical texts, supplemented by thoughtful viewings of select films, class discussions, written essays and exams, and lectures. Our overall aim will be to develop a reasoned, considered perspective on film as an art form insofar as it can mimic philosophy, elicit viewer emotions, offer different modes of narration, and convey to us crucial insights regarding fictional characters and other human beings. NOTE: The dozen or so films we will view for this course have been chosen to make you think philosophically about film. This aim will probably require you to view these films in a different way from the manner in which you usually watch films. These works of art should challenge you, so be prepared to analyze them, not simply sit back and regard them merely as entertainment. It would by no means be inappropriate for you to take notes on these films while or immediately after viewing them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Third Man 2004
    Repositorium für die Medienwissenschaft Drew Bassett Rob White: The Third Man 2004 https://doi.org/10.17192/ep2004.2.1856 Veröffentlichungsversion / published version Rezension / review Empfohlene Zitierung / Suggested Citation: Bassett, Drew: Rob White: The Third Man. In: MEDIENwissenschaft: Rezensionen | Reviews, Jg. 21 (2004), Nr. 2, S. 250– 251. DOI: https://doi.org/10.17192/ep2004.2.1856. Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Dieser Text wird unter einer Deposit-Lizenz (Keine This document is made available under a Deposit License (No Weiterverbreitung - keine Bearbeitung) zur Verfügung gestellt. Redistribution - no modifications). We grant a non-exclusive, Gewährt wird ein nicht exklusives, nicht übertragbares, non-transferable, individual, and limited right for using this persönliches und beschränktes Recht auf Nutzung dieses document. This document is solely intended for your personal, Dokuments. Dieses Dokument ist ausschließlich für non-commercial use. All copies of this documents must retain den persönlichen, nicht-kommerziellen Gebrauch bestimmt. all copyright information and other information regarding legal Auf sämtlichen Kopien dieses Dokuments müssen alle protection. You are not allowed to alter this document in any Urheberrechtshinweise und sonstigen Hinweise auf gesetzlichen way, to copy it for public or commercial purposes, to exhibit the Schutz beibehalten werden. Sie dürfen dieses Dokument document in public, to perform, distribute, or otherwise use the nicht in irgendeiner Weise abändern, noch dürfen Sie document in public. dieses Dokument für öffentliche oder kommerzielle Zwecke By using this particular document, you accept the conditions of vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, aufführen, vertreiben oder use stated above. anderweitig nutzen. Mit der Verwendung dieses Dokuments erkennen Sie die Nutzungsbedingungen an. Fotogrqfie 1111d Film Roh White: The Third Man London: BFI Publishing 2003 (BFI Film Classics).
    [Show full text]
  • THE THIRD MAN Involved in an Opium-Smuggling Operation
    CD 7A: “Every Frame Has a Silver Lining” - 10/26/1951 Passing through Iran, Harry becomes THE THIRD MAN involved in an opium-smuggling operation. Lives of Harry Lime CD 7B: “Mexican Hat Trick” - 11/02/1951 Program Guide by Elizabeth McLeod Down on his luck in Mexico, opportunity Orson Welles in The Third Man beckons Harry…thanks to a pickpocket! It’s a hard job being a middle-aged wunderkind, especially in show business -- where you’re only as good as your last big success. And CD 8A: “Art Is Long and Lime Is Fleeting” - 11/09/1951 as Orson Welles moved into his mid-thirties, the triumphs of his youth The painting Harry’s trying to sell isn’t really a Renoir, but does that seemed increasingly remote. The Mercury Theatre was just a memory, really matter? and so was the bold 1930s experimental theatre scene that gave it life. Postwar America, with its increasing restrictions on intellectual freedom CD 8B: “In Pursuit of a Ghost” - 11/16/1951 and its suspicion of anyone who dared to color outside the lines, had Harry is caught up in a rush of events and finds himself in the middle of little use for a superannuated boy wonder…especially one who’d made a banana-republic revolution! a career of antagonizing the Establishment. Orson Welles may have been a genius, but it didn’t take a genius to know that there wasn’t much call anymore for the kind of work that he did so well. He’d burned his Elizabeth McLeod is a journalist, author, and broadcast bridges in Hollywood -- and the radio networks, seeing the approaching historian.
    [Show full text]
  • Paper VII, Philosophy and Film Semester V Aims: 1. to Acquaint
    Paper VII, Philosophy and Film Semester V Aims: 1. To acquaint students with a new intriguing subject in Philosophy, i.e. Philosophy of Film. 2. To acquaint students with Film as an independent art form. 3. To acquaint students that the most powerful mass media of communication i.e. film has its pragmatic aspect and its own axiology. 4. To acquaint students with different aspects of Film philosophically. Unit I Ontology of Philosophy and Film Philosophy-in-Film, Philosophy-of-Film, Film Studies, Film Theories and Film Criticism Unit II Film Theories Auteur Theory, Marxist Film Theory, Feminist Film Theory, Formalist Film Theory and Screen Theory Unit III Philosophy Through Films Knowledge and Truth - Film Text: The Matrix; Problem of Identity - Film Text: Momento, Hindi Movies with themes of Duplicates; Ethics and Moral Responsibility - Film Text: Crimes and Misdemeanor, Social Political genre films; Philosophy of Religion - Film Text: The Rapture, Saint Films, Mythological films (Jai Santoshi Maa, Ramayan: The legend of Prince Ram, In the Name of the Rose); and Philosophy of Sci-Fiction Film – Film Text: Star Wars, Gravity Unit IV Praxis of Philosophy of Film 1 Film and Ethics – Film Text: Crime and Punishment, Deewar; Film and Psychoanalysis – Film Text: Psycho, Karthik Calling Karthik; Film and Society – Film Text: Corporate, Fashion, Page 3; Commercial vsArt Film – Mera Naam Joker, Anand; and Off-beat or Art Film – Film Text: Duvidha, Paar References: 1. Mary. M. Litch. Philosophy Through Film, 2002, New York : Routledge. 2. Paisly Livingstone and Carl Plantinga (ed) The Routledge Companion of Film and Philosophy. 2009 New York: Routledge 3.
    [Show full text]
  • PHILOSOPHY 364 – Summer 2011 Aesthetics of Film
    PHILOSOPHY 364 – Summer 2011 Aesthetics of Film Instructor: Richard Dub E-mail: [email protected] Class location: Scott Hall 102 Class meeting time: TTh 6:00{9:55 Office: 1 Seminary Place, room 002 Office hours: W 4:00{5:30 Course Description and Goals This course is an introduction to the philosophy of film. We will discuss questions such as: What is film? Can film produce aesthetic value in ways that other artistic media can't? Are motion pictures illusions? Is the intent of the director important in producing the meaning of a film? How and why do films move us emotionally? Can documentaries be free of bias? By the conclusion of the course, you will have: • become familiar with current debates in aesthetics. • become more knowledgable about what makes motion pictures unique. • become more adept at extracting arguments from philosophical papers and criticizing them. • discovered new ways to think about films and new ways to have discussions about them. Course Materials We'll be reading two or three papers for each class. Reading the papers, and reading them suffi- ciently closely that you are prepared to discuss them, is mandatory. Readings will be available in a shared folder on Dropbox. If you don't currently have a Dropbox account, you can sign up for free at http://db.tt/waBhdmI. Once you have an account, please send me the e-mail address that is linked to your account, and I will give you access to the shared folder. In the shared folder, you'll also find additional optional readings for most classes.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy of Film and Film As Philosophy
    11 THE PHILOSOPHY OF FILM AND FILM AS PHILOSOPHY Tom McClelland (University of Sussex) There are two key respects in which the medium of film and the discipline of philosophy can intersect. First, the philosophy of film is an established sub- discipline that asks philosophical questions about the nature of film: What, if anything, are the necessary and sufficient conditions of being a film? How do audiences engage imaginatively with films? What cognitive or emotional value does the viewing of motion pictures have? Here the philosophical practice of clarifying concepts and exploring abstract problems simply takes film as its object. Second, the more controversial notion of film as philosophy suggests that films themselves can take up philosophical issues, and can contribute to a range of philosophical debates. Here the object of investigation might be the epistemic problem of skepticism, the metaphysical problem of personal identity or the ethical problem of why we should be moral.1 But on this approach the film itself participates in the philosophical investigation. This paper is primarily concerned with the idea of film as philosophy (FAP) and explores some of the problems that this notion raises. Putting documentary and art films aside, I will focus on the idea that popular narrative film can “be” philosophy.2 The two over-arching issues surrounding FAP can be captured by way of an analogy. Someone suggests that you go to the cinema tonight to see a popular new film. In response to this suggestion there are two questions you might naturally ask: whether there are any tickets available, and whether the film is any good.
    [Show full text]
  • BFI Future Film Member Joe Steen Recommends the Third Man (1949, Dir
    BFI Future Film member Joe Steen recommends The Third Man (1949, dir. Carol Reed) From the first creeping, whimsical note of Anton Karas’ infamously seductive zither soundtrack, The Third Man announces itself as a quaint and curious masterpiece of British cinema. The quintessentially English narrator provides a brief vignette of post-war Vienna, delivered in a haughty and jarringly buoyant tone that will prove all the more strange as we embark on a cryptic journey through the slippery streets of Vienna. For our hero, Holly Martins, ancient ideas about good and evil seem about as distant and uncertain as the identity of this enigmatic ‘Third Man’. Though it is commonly categorised as film noir or British noir, The Third Man is not quite composed of the same pulpy ingredients as its Hollywood influences. Our femme fatale is no malevolent spider- woman, our detective hero constantly out of his depth, and the forces of law and order no less bewildered and ineffective. Where The Third Man remains fundamentally film noir, however, is in its evocative and striking visual character: Graham Greene’s tense and enigmatic picture of post-war alienation is brought vividly to life by the skewed and suspicious eye of the camera, searching desperately down Vienna’s dark alleyways and through the rubble of its bombed-out buildings. The film’s conclusion, although unforgettable in terms of visual splendour, remains painfully uncompromising and powerful – aching with uncertainty and the betrayal of our expectations. Though the film has moments of great tension and sporadic comedy, they are sparsely measured and subordinate to the moral intrigue that skirts the plot’s shadowy surfaces, culminating in perhaps the most notorious (certainly the most incredible) examples of ad-libbing in cinema – the ‘cuckoo clock speech’.
    [Show full text]