Thesis Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Thesis Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Bath PHD Empathy for education: a naturalist utilitarian argument Walters, Timothy Award date: 2016 Awarding institution: University of Bath Link to publication Alternative formats If you require this document in an alternative format, please contact: [email protected] General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 27. Sep. 2021 Empathy for education: a naturalist utilitarian argument Timothy John Walters A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Bath Department of Education June 2015 COPYRIGHT Attention is drawn to the fact that copyright of this thesis rests with the author. A copy of this thesis has been supplied on condition that anyone who consults it is understood to recognise that its copyright rests with the author and that they must not copy it or use material from it except as permitted by law or with the consent of the author. This thesis may be available for consultation within the University Library and may be photocopied or lent to other libraries for the purposes of consultation with effect from 1 June 2015. Signed on behalf of the Department of Education of the University of Bath Table of Contents Chapter 1: Introduction 1.1. The core argument 11 1.2. Overview of the scope and sequence of this work: Three EfE accounts 16 1.2.1 Philosophical/normative (“should”) accounts (Chapters 2 – 5) 17 1.2.2. Empirical (“can”) accounts (Chapter 6) 19 1.2.3. Narrative or “how” accounts (Chapters 7 - 9) 21 1.3. A moral life narrative experience in Cambodia 23 1.3.1. History education in Cambodia 25 1.3.2. The workshop: Narrative and empathy 26 1.3.3. Moral autonomy and helplessness 29 1.4. The Perceived Crisis in Moral Education 31 1.5. EfE in Moral Education: the Philosophy of Education Discourse 33 (Five Debates) 1.5.1. Empathy or Virtue as a Core Value for Moral Education? 34 1.5.2. Moral Education for a Multicultural Context 38 2 1.5.3. Moral Inquiry or Moral Formation? 38 1.5.4. The Future of Education: Human, Natural or Neuroscience? 41 1.5.5. Narrative and "Educating the Emotions" 46 Chapter 2: A Pluralist Philosophical Naturalism 2.1. The Role of Philosophical Naturalism in this Research 48 2.2. Philosophical Naturalisms 53 2.2.1. Papineau’s Physicalism 57 2.3. Midgley’s Objections to Naturalism 58 2.4. Supervenience and Reduction 62 2.5. Dewey’s “Half-Hearted Naturalism” 64 2.6. Scruton’s Cognitive Dualism and Aesthetic Experience 67 2.7. Contemporary Pluralist Compromise 69 2.8. Hume’s Naturalism and Relevance to this Research 71 2.8.1. Hume’s Sceptical/Sentimental Project 74 2.9. Contemporary Perspectives on Affect and Intuition 77 2.9.1. Embodied Brains in Embedded Bodies 78 2.10. Reduction and Physicalism 80 3 Chapter 3: Empathy and Moral Realism 3.1. The Role of Moral Realism in this Research 82 3.2. (Moral) Realism and (Philosophical) Naturalism 83 3.3. From Scientific to Moral Realism 84 3.4. Railton’s Ethical Naturalism 85 3.5. Moral Principles and Reality 85 3.6. Pluralist Good and Monist Right 86 Chapter 4: A Classical Utilitarian Normative Ethical Theory 4.1. The Importance of Utilitarian Normative Theory to this Research 90 4.2. Utilitarianism and Empirical Construals of Moral Cognition 91 4.3. Bentham’s Utilitarianism 94 4.4. Against Singer’s Utilitarianism 95 4.4.1. Singer’s Unconditional Proscription of Partiality is Unrealistic 95 4.4.2. Singer’s Account of Moral Psychology is too Ambitious Overall 100 4.4.3. Singer’s Account of Moral Psychology is Unrealistically Rationalist 103 4.4.4. Singer’s Asocial Construal 105 4 4.5. Moral Equality and Partiality in Classical and Contemporary Utilitarianism 106 4.5.1. Bentham and Mill on Moral Equality and Partiality 106 4.5.2. Singer on Moral Equality and Partiality 109 Chapter 5: Objections to Utilitarianism 5.1. The Primary Objections Introduced 111 5.2. Utilitarianism Especially Endorses Pursuit of Base or Superficial Pleasures 112 5.3. Utilitarianism is Unjust and Potentially Tyrannical 116 5.3.1. Some Initial Points on “The Tyranny of the Majority” 116 5.3.2. Nozick’s “Utility Monster” 117 5.4. Tyranny and “Security” 119 5.5. Mill on Tyranny 121 5.6. Bentham on Tyranny 123 5.7. Utilitarianism Entails “Boundless Moral Obligation” 124 Chapter 6: Convergent Construals of Moral Cognition 6.1. The Goals and Design of this Chapter 129 6.2. Defining the “Affective Revolution” (AR) 129 5 6.3. “Revolution” and Hyperbole: “Moral Molecules” and “Mind-Reading” Neurons 130 6.4. The “Revolution” in Historical Context 132 6.5. Moral Cognition and the Possibility of Change 133 6.6. An Interdisciplinary Overview of AR 133 6.6.1. Behavioural Business Ethics/Behavioural Finance 134 6.6.2. Emerging and Traditional Models of Economic Behaviour 135 6.6.3. Rational Models and Efficient Markets 136 6.6.4. A More Social Economic Model 137 6.7. Haidt’s Model of Adaptive Morality 139 6.8. Disgust, “Moral Dumbfounding” and Arational Moral Cognition 139 6.9. Haidt’s Social Intuitionist Ethics 141 6.10. Greene’s Dual Process Model of Moral Cognition 142 6.10.1. Greene on “Me versus Us” and “Us versus Them” 143 6.11. The Normativity of Greene’s “Deep Pragmatism” 146 6.11.1. “Action Tendencies” and Moral Motivation 147 6.12. Moral Narrative and/in Batson’s Empathy-Altruism Hypothesis 148 6.13. Against Batson: Cialdini on Self-in-Other Merging 149 6 Chapter 7: Life as Narrative 7.1. The Goals and Design of this Chapter 153 7.2. Life and Narrative 153 7.2.1. Bruner on Life as Narrative 153 7.2.2. Hardy: Narrative as “Primary Act of Mind” 155 7.3. Nussbaum and Gadamer on Literature, Education and Insight 156 7.4. MacIntyre: Narrative and Life Unity 158 7.5. Lamarque on The Limitations of Narrative 160 7.5.1. “Narratives are Necessarily Selective and Perspectival” 160 7.5.2. “Narrative is often Prosaic and Trivial” 164 Chapter 8: Moral Life Narrative Education 8.1. The Goals and Design of this Chapter 165 8.2. Assessing the “Moral” in Moral Life Narrative 165 8.3. Tappan and Brown on “Authorship” as Moral Development 166 8.4. Stories and Empathy-building: Contemporary examples 168 8.5. The Utilitarian Basis of Empathy 169 7 8.5.1. Utilitarianism and the Moral Emotions 169 8.5.2. Empathy from Utility 170 Chapter 9: Realism, Rationalism and Contemporary Moral Education 9.1. The Goals and Design of this Chapter 173 9.2. Kohlberg’s Model of Cognitive Moral Development 175 9.2.1. “Progress” from Affective to Rational Moral Judgment 177 9.3. (Anti-Realist) Values Clarification 182 9.4. Kirschenbaum on Value Neutrality 183 9.5. Character Education and Socialisation 185 9.6. Gibbs’ New Synthesis 188 9.6.1. Gibbs’ Critique of Haidt 190 9.6.2. From Affect-led to Story-led 197 Chapter 10: Stories for Thinking 10.1. The Goals and Design of this Chapter 199 10.2. “Vivid and Memorable” Learning 200 10.3. Egan on Useful Abstraction 200 8 10.4. Philosophy for Children and “Caring Thinking” 201 10.5. Fisher on Learner Construction and Useful Innuendo 204 10.6. “Humanising Stories” and Empathy 205 11. Conclusions 206 Bibliography 209 9 Abstract In this work I argue that opportunities exist to develop frameworks for moral or empathy education (hereafter EfE) more consistent with emerging understandings of the way we arrive at moral judgments. I argue that a rapidly evolving construal of moral judgment is more accurate than (still influential) rationalist accounts. The essence of this shifting perspective is a construal of moral judgment as characterised by (1) "primacy of affect" and (2) heightened emphasis on the socially embedded nature of moral judgments. While variously compatible with long established traditions in moral philosophy (particularly the moral sense theories of, inter alia, David Hume or Adam Smith) this distinct view of human moral nature is emerging across a range of empirical disciplines with renewed vigour and enhanced empirical support. Moral psychology and neuroscience play leading, but not exclusive, roles in this emphatically interdisciplinary process. Shifting paradigms in economics, anthropology, and moral psychology are converging on strikingly similar construals of human moral nature. I will argue that the potential of these insights to explain and justify particular approaches to teaching and learning have yet to be fully exploited in contemporary moral education discourse. It will be argued that encouraging the development of dispositional empathy in learners is a choice-worthy and attainable goal of EfE. EfE approaches used to elicit affective/empathic responses and social reflection, such as moral life narrative and other storytelling techniques, comport with emerging views of moral experience and judgment. It is argued that these approaches are, therefore, potentially more effective than rationality-centred systems given a goal of increased dispositional empathy.
Recommended publications
  • Climate Change, Consequentialism, and the Road Ahead
    Chicago Journal of International Law Volume 13 Number 2 Article 8 1-1-2013 Climate Change, Consequentialism, and the Road Ahead Dale Jamieson Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cjil Recommended Citation Jamieson, Dale (2013) "Climate Change, Consequentialism, and the Road Ahead," Chicago Journal of International Law: Vol. 13: No. 2, Article 8. Available at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cjil/vol13/iss2/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chicago Journal of International Law by an authorized editor of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Climate Change, Consequentialism, and the Road Ahead Dale Jamieson* Abstract In this paperI tell the stoy of the evolution of the climate change regime, locating its origins in "the dream of Rio," which supposed that the nations of the world would join in addressing the interlocking crises of environment and development. I describe the failure at Copenhagen and then go on to discuss the "reboot" of the climate negoiations advocated by Eric A. Posner and David Weisbach. I bring out some ambiguides in their notion of InternationalPareianism, which is supposed to effectively limit the influence of moral ideals in internationalaffairs, and pose a dilemma. I go on to discuss the foundations of their views regarding climate justice, arguing that the most reasonable understandings of their favored theoretical views would not lead to some of their conclusions. Finaly, I return to the climate regime, and make some observations about the road ahead, concluding thatfor theforeseeable future the most important climate change action will be within countries rather than among them.
    [Show full text]
  • Universalist Ethics in Extraterrestrial Encounter Seth D
    Universalist Ethics in Extraterrestrial Encounter Seth D. Baum, http://sethbaum.com Department of Geography & Rock Ethics Institute, Pennsylvania State University Published in: Acta Astronautica, 2010, 66(3-4): 617-623 Abstract If humanity encounters an extraterrestrial civilization, or if two extraterrestrial civilizations encounter each other, then the outcome may depend not only on the civilizations’ relative strength to destroy each other but also on what ethics are held by one or both civilizations. This paper explores outcomes of encounter scenarios in which one or both civilizations hold a universalist ethical framework. Several outcomes are possible in such scenarios, ranging from one civilization destroying the other to both civilizations racing to be the first to commit suicide. Thus, attention to the ethics of both humanity and extraterrestrials is warranted in human planning for such an encounter. Additionally, the possibility of such an encounter raises profound questions for contemporary human ethics, even if such an encounter never occurs. Keywords: extraterrestrials, ethics, universalism 1. Introduction To date, humanity has never encountered extraterrestrial life, let alone an extraterrestrial civilization. However, we can also not rule out the possibility that such an encounter will occur. Indeed, insights from the Drake equation (see e.g. [1]) suggest that such an encounter may be likely. As human exploration of space progresses, such an encounter may become increasingly likely. Thus analysis of what would happen in the event of an extraterrestrial encounter is of considerable significance. This analysis is particularly important for the astronautics community to consider given that it is on the leading edge of space exploration.
    [Show full text]
  • Sharing the World with Digital Minds1
    Sharing the World with Digital Minds1 (2020). Draft. Version 1.8 Carl Shulman† & Nick Bostrom† [in Clarke, S. & Savulescu, J. (eds.): Rethinking Moral Status (Oxford University Press, forthcoming)] Abstract The minds of biological creatures occupy a small corner of a much larger space of possible minds that could be created once we master the technology of artificial intelligence. Yet many of our moral intuitions and practices are based on assumptions about human nature that need not hold for digital minds. This points to the need for moral reflection as we approach the era of advanced machine intelligence. Here we focus on one set of issues, which arise from the prospect of digital minds with superhumanly strong claims to resources and influence. These could arise from the vast collective benefits that mass-produced digital minds could derive from relatively small amounts of resources. Alternatively, they could arise from individual digital minds with superhuman moral status or ability to benefit from resources. Such beings could contribute immense value to the world, and failing to respect their interests could produce a moral catastrophe, while a naive way of respecting them could be disastrous for humanity. A sensible approach requires reforms of our moral norms and institutions along with advance planning regarding what kinds of digital minds we bring into existence. 1. Introduction Human biological nature imposes many practical limits on what can be done to promote somebody’s welfare. We can only live so long, feel so much joy, have so many children, and benefit so much from additional support and resources. Meanwhile, we require, in order to flourish, that a complex set of physical, psychological, and social conditions be met.
    [Show full text]
  • Care Ethics and Politcal Theory
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi Care Ethics and Political Theory OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi Care Ethics and Political Theory Edited by Daniel Engster and Maurice Hamington 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries # Oxford University Press 2015 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2015 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2015932776 ISBN 978–0–19–871634–1 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Moral Theories: Introduction to Contemporary Consequentialism Syllabus [Kian Mintz-Woo]
    Contemporary Moral Theories: Introduction to Contemporary Consequentialism Syllabus [Kian Mintz-Woo] Course Information In this course, I will introduce you to some of the ways that consequentialist thinking leads to surprising or counterintuitive moral conclusions. This means that I will focus on issues which are controversial such as vegetarianism, charity, climate change and health-care. I have tried to select readings that are both contemporary and engaging. Hopefully, these readings will make you think a little differently or give you new ideas to consider or discuss. This course will take place in SR09.53 from 15.15-16.45. I have placed all of the readings for the term (although there might be slight changes), along with questions in green to help guide your reading. Some weeks have a recommended reading as well, which I think will help you to see how people have responded to the kinds of arguments in the required text. Please look over the descriptions and see which readings you are most interested in presenting for class for our first session on 10.03.2016. (Please tell me if you ever find a link that does not work or have any problems accessing content on this Moodle page.) I have a policy that cellphones are off in class; we will have a 5-10 minute break in the course and you can check messages only during the break. As a bonus, I have included at least one fun thing each week which relates to the theme of that week. Marking The course has three marked components: 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Overpopulation and the Quality of Life’
    X OVERPOPULATION AND THE QUALITY OF LI FE DEREK PARFIT How many people should there be? Can there be overpopulation: too many people living? I shall present a puzzling argument about these questions, show how this argument can be strengthened, then sketch a possible reply.* I QUALITY AND QUANTITY Consider the outcomes that might be produced, in some part of the world, by two rates of population growth. Suppose that, if there is faster growth, there would later be more people, who would all be worse off. These outcomes are shown in Fig. i . The width of the Fig. i Derek Parfit, ‘Overpopulation and the Quality of Life’. © 1986 Derek Parfit. Printed by permission of the author. * The first half of this (hitherto unpublished) essay summarizes a longer discussion in my Reasons and Persons (Oxford, 1984). Ihave been greatly helped by J. McMahan, J. R. Richards, L. Temkin, K. Kalafski, and R. Jones. For further reading on this subject, see Obligations to Future Generations, ed. R. I. Sikora and B. Barry (Philadelphia, 1978) and McMahan's long review of this anthology in Ethics 92, No. 1, 1981. 146 DEREK PARFIT blocks shows the number of people living; the height shows how well off these people are. Compared with outcome A, outcome B would have twice as many people, who would all be worse off. To avoid irrelevant complications, I assume that in each outcome there would be no inequality: no one would be worse off than anyone else. I also assume that everyone’s life would be well worth living.
    [Show full text]
  • Overpopulation and the Quality of Life
    DEREK PARFIT OVERPOPULATION AND THE QUALITY OF LIFE How many people should there be? Can there be overpopulation: too many people living? I shall present a puzzling argument about these questions, show how this argument can be strengthened, then sketch a possible reply.1 1. QUALITY AND QUANTITY Consider the outcomes that might be produced, in some part of the world, by two rates of population growth. Suppose that, if there is faster growth, there would later be more people, who would all be worse off. These outcomes are shown in Fig. I. A B Fig.1 The width of the blocks shows the number of people living; the height shows how well off these people are. Compared with outcome A, outcome B would have twice as many people, who would all be worse off. To avoid irrelevant complications, I assume that in each outcome there would be no inequality: no one would be worse off than anyone else. I also assume that everyone's life would be well worth living. There are various ways in which, because there would be twice as many people in outcome B, these people might be all worse off than the people in A. There might be worse housing, overcrowded schools, more pollution, less unspoilt 7 J. Ryberg and T. Tännsjö (eds.), The Repugnant Conclusion, 7-22. © 2004 All Rights Reserved. Printed in the Netherlands. 8 D. PARFIT countryside, fewer opportunities, and a smaller share per person of various other kinds of resources. I shall say, for short, that in B there is a lower quality of life.
    [Show full text]
  • Future Generations And
    Future Generations and Interpersonal Compensations Moral Aspects of Energy Use by Gustaf Arrhenius and Krister Bykvist Acknowledgements Several people have helped us to write this essay. Our greatest debt is to Wlodek Rabinowicz, who has been an excellent supervisor of the project. He spent a lot of time and energy reading drafts of the essay. Without his painstaking criticism and helpful comments this essay would lack in precision, relevance, and logical correctness. Earlier drafts of the essay were discussed in Sven Danielsson and Wlodek Rabinowicz's seminar at the Department of Philosophy, University of Uppsala. The participants of the seminar contributed with helpful criticisms. Apart from Sven and Wlodek, we would like to thank Thomas Anderberg, Erik Carlson, Tomasz Pol, Peter Ryman, Rysiek Sliwinski, and Jan Österberg. We are especially grateful to Erik Carlson. His critical eye detected many flaws in earlier versions of our theory. A summary of this essay was presented in a seminar at Hässelby Castle, June 1994, organised by NUTEK (Näringsutvecklingsverket), where Bengt Hansson and Lars Ingelstam made interesting comments. Parts of Chapter 3 were presented at Australian National University, Canberra; Monash University, Melbourne; and Queensland University, Brisbane, February 1994. We would especially like to thank Peter Singer and Yew-Kwang Ng for their helpful suggestions. Parts of Chapter 4 were presented at University of Toronto, Department of Philosophy, Toronto, May 1994 and 1995, and at the Learned Society, Canadian Philosophical Association, Montreal, June 1995. We are especially grateful to Danny Goldstick, Tom Hurka, Andrew Latus, Howard Sobel and Wayne Sumner for their valuable comments. Bengt Bykvist, Rebecca Fodden, John Gibson, Wlodek Rabinowicz and Pura Sanchez checked and improved our English.
    [Show full text]
  • Utilitarianism
    Utilitarianism From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Utilitarianism is the ethical doctrine that the moral worth of an action is solely determined by its contribution to overall utility. It is thus a form of consequentialism, meaning that the moral worth of an action is determined by its outcome—the ends justify the means. Utility — the good to be maximized — has been defined by various thinkers as happiness or pleasure (versus sadness or pain), though preference utilitarians like Peter Singer define it as the satisfaction of preferences. It can be described by the phrase "the greatest good for the greatest number", though the 'greatest number' part gives rise to the problematic mere addition paradox. Utilitarianism can thus be characterized as a quantitative and reductionistic approach to ethics. Utilitarianism can be contrasted with deontological ethics (which focuses on the action itself rather than its consequences) and virtue ethics (which focuses on character), as well as with other varieties of consequentialism. Adherents of these opposing views have extensively criticized the utilitarian view, though utilitarians have been similarly critical of other schools of ethical thought. In general use the term utilitarian often refers to a somewhat narrow economic or pragmatic viewpoint. However, philosophical utilitarianism is much broader than this, for example some approaches to utilitarianism consider non-human animals in addition to people. Contents 1 History 2 Origin of the term 3 Types 3.1 Act vs. rule 3.2 Motive 3.3 Two-level 3.4 Negative 3.5 Average vs. total 3.6 Other species 3.7 Combinations with other ethical schools 4 Biological explanation 5 Criticism and Defense 5.1 Comparing happiness 5.2 Predicting consequences 5.3 Importance of intentions 5.4 Human rights 5.5 Individual interests vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Information to Users
    Searching for theory X: A quality-only approach to the problem of future generations. Item Type text; Dissertation-Reproduction (electronic) Authors Merten, Gail. Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 03/10/2021 19:40:16 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/186375 INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleed through, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand corner and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. Each original is also photographed in one exposure and is included in reduced form at the back of the book. Photographs included in the original manuscript have been reproduced xerographically in this copy.
    [Show full text]
  • Just Better Utilitarianism
    Article Just Better Utilitarianism MATTI HÄYRY https://doi.org/10.1017/S0963180120000882 . Abstract: Utilitarianism could still be a viable moral and political theory, although an emphasis on justice as distributing burdens and benefits has hidden this from current conversations. The traditional counterexamples prove that we have good grounds for rejecting classical, aggregative forms of consequentialism. A nonaggregative, liberal form of utilitarianism is immune to this rejection. The cost is that it cannot adjudicate when the basic needs of individuals or groups are in conflict. Cases like this must be solved by other methods. This is not a weakness in liberal utilitarianism, on the contrary. The theory clarifies what we should admit to begin with: that ethical doctrines do not have universally acceptable solutions to all difficult problems or hard cases. The theory also reminds us that not all problems are in this sense difficult or cases hard. We could alleviate the plight of nonhuman https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms animals by reducing meat eating. We could mitigate climate change and its detrimental effects by choosing better ways of living. These would imply that most people’s desire satisfaction would be partly frustrated, but liberal utilitarianism holds that this would be justified by the satisfaction of the basic needs of other people and nonhuman animals. Keywords: utilitarianism; consequentialism; liberal utilitarianism; nonhuman animals; climate change The purpose of this article is to remind readers and commentators that utilitarianism could still provide a basis for moral and political choices in bioethics and elsewhere. After a brief historical overview, I will describe where I see that the “justice turn” in normative thinking has left us in terms of views on ethics and social policy.
    [Show full text]
  • Barbara Mackinnon – Utilitarianism and Kant's Moral Theory
    Barbara MacKinnon – Utilitarianism and Kant’s Moral Theory Ethical Theory • An ethical theory is a general theory about which actions are right or wrong, and why those actions are right or wrong. An ethical theory will provide criteria for determining whether an action is right or wrong, and it will claim that the action’s meeting those criteria explains why the action is right or wrong. – An ethical theory will entail various particular ethical judgments: for instance, that you have a duty to donate money to charity, that affirmative action is unjust, or that it is impermissible to go to a prostitute. ∗ A particular ethical judgment is just a judgment about what is right or wrong in a particular case. It doesn’t tell us anything about how to behave in other cases. Only an ethical theory will do that. – There are many particular ethical questions that we’re unsure about. We can use our general ethical theory to guide us through these difficult questions. That is, we can use our ethical theory to form particular ethical judgments: Ethical Theory j # Ethical Judgment – However, there are many particular ethical questions that we’re much more confident about. We’re confident, for instance, that torturing babies for fun is pretty much always immoral, that using the elderly for target practice is impermissible, and that enslaving human beings for profit is unjust. We can therefore use judgments like these to test our ethical theories. Ethical Theory " j Ethical Judgment – So there’s a two-way street between our ethical judgments and our ethical theory – we can use the theory to form our judgments, and use our judgments to form the theory.
    [Show full text]