Political Philosophy Bibliography Andrew F

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Political Philosophy Bibliography Andrew F Islamic Political Philosophy Bibliography Andrew F. March Introduction By “political philosophy” we mean not all political thought or theory in the Islamic tradition, but the specific tradition formed by the translation of classical Greek philosophy into Arabic. The boundaries should not be drawn too sharply here (since philosophical methods and themes were also integrated into “orthodox” theology and law, and because many philosophers did see themselves as providing philosophical account of certain creedal commitments from Islamic and Jewish theology), but this entry focuses primarily on works recognizably within the “falsafa” tradition as understood in classical Islamic learning. General Surveys of Islamic Political Philosophy Peter Adamson and Richard C. Taylor, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005), particularly the chapter by Charles Butterworth, “Ethical and Political Philosophy.” Brague, Rémi. The Law of God: The Philosophical History of an Idea, trans. Lydia G. Cochrane (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007). Butterworth, Charles, ed., The Political Aspects of Islamic Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992) [see references to specific chapters below]. E. Gannagé et al. (eds), The Greek Strand in Islamic Political Thought, special issue of Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 62 (2004). Butterworth, Charles E. “Philosophy of Law in Medieval Judaism and Islam,” in Fred D. Miller Jr., ed., A History of the Philosophy of Law from the Ancient Greeks to the Scholastics (vol. 6 of A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence; Dordrecht: Springer, 2007). Crone, Patricia, God’s Rule: Six Centuries of Medieval Islamic Political Thought (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004), Ch. 14, “The Greek Tradition and ‘Political Science.” Majid Fakhry, A History of Islamic Philosophy (New York: Columbia University Press, 3rd ed., 2004). History of Islamic Philosophy, Seyyed Hossein Nasr and Oliver Leaman, eds., (London: Routledge, 1996). Daiber, Hans. “Political Philosophy,” in History of Islamic Philosophy, Seyyed Hossein Nasr and Oliver Leaman, eds., (London: Routledge, 1996). 1 Kraemer, Joel L. “The Jihād of the Falāsifa,” Jerusalem Studies in Arabic and Islam”, 10 (1987). History of Greek Philosophy and the Translation Movement Gutas, Dimitri. Greek Thought, Arabic Culture: The Graeco-Arabic Translation Movement in Baghdad and Early ʿAbbāsid society (2nd-4th/8th-10th centuries) (New York: Routledge, 1998). ________. “The Study of Arabic Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: An Essay on the Historiography of Arabic Philosophy,” British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies (2002). Readers and Anthologies of Primary Texts in Translation John McGinnis and David C. Reisman, Classical Arabic Philosophy: An Anthology of Sources (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2007) Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, 1st, Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi, eds., (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1972). Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, 2nd, Joshua Parens and Joseph C. Macfarland, eds. (Cornell University Press, 2011). Farabi Primary Texts in Translation: Alfarabi, Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, Muhsin Mahdi trans., (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001) Alfarabi, the political writings: selected aphorisms and other texts, Charles E. Butterworth trans. and ed. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press), including: Al-Farabi, “Selected Aphorisms” in Alfarabi, the political writings: selected aphorisms and other texts. Ithaca: Cornell University Press (2001). ________. “Enumeration of the Sciences” in Alfarabi, the political writings: selected aphorisms and other texts. Ithaca: Cornell University Press (2001). ________. “Book of Religion” in Alfarabi, the political writings: selected aphorisms and other texts. Ithaca: Cornell University Press (2001). 2 ________. “The Harmonization of the Two Opinions of the Two Sages: Plato the Divine and Aristotle” in in Alfarabi, the political writings: selected aphorisms and other texts. Ithaca: Cornell University Press (2001). Al-Farabi, On the Perfect State (Mabadiʾ araʾ al-madina al-fadila), Richard Walzer ed. and trans., (Chicago, IL: Kazi Publications, 1988). Secondary Literature: David C. Reisman, “Al-Fārābī and the Philosophical Curriculum,” in Adamson and Taylor, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy. Patricia Crone, “Al-Fārābī’s Imperfect Constitutions,” in Gannagé et al. (eds), The Greek Strand in Islamic Political Thought. Dimitri Gutas, “The Meaning of madanī in al-Fārābī’s ‘Political’ Philosophy,” in Gannagé et al. (eds), The Greek Strand in Islamic Political Thought. Gutas, “Galen’s Synopsis of Plato’s Laws and Farabi's Talkhis,” in The ancient tradition in Christian and Islamic Hellenism : studies on the transmission of Greek philosophy and sciences dedicated to H. J. Drossaart Lulofs on his ninetieth birthday Nelly Lahoud, “Al-Fārābī: On Religion and Philosophy,” in Gannagé et al. (eds), The Greek Strand in Islamic Political Thought) Fauzi M. Najjar, “al-Fārābī and Political Science,” The Muslim World 48.2 (1958) pp. 94- 103. Fauzi M. Najjar, “Fārābī's Political Philosophy and Shīʿism,” Studia Islamica (1961) Ulrich Rudolph, “Reflections on al-Fārābī’s, Mabādiʾ ārāʾ ahl al-madīna al-fāḍila,” in Peter Adamson, ed., In The Age of Al-Fārābī: Arabic Philosophy in The Fourth-Tenth Century (London : Warburg Institute, 2008). Leo Strauss, “How Fārābī read Plato’s Laws,” in What is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988) and Persecution and the Art of Writing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980). Muhsin Mahdi, Alfarabi and the Foundation of Islamic Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001) Miriam Galston, Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1990). 3 Hans Daiber, The Ruler as Philosopher: A New Interpretation of al-Fārābī’s View (Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co., 1986). Christopher A. Colmo, Breaking with Athens: Alfarabi as Founder (Lexington Books, 2005). Ibn Sina (Avicenna): Primary Texts in Translation: Avicenna, The Metaphysics of The Healing, trans. Michael E. Marmura (Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press, 2005. Secondary Literature: McGinnis, Jon. Avicenna (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010). Miriam Galston, “Realism and Idealism in Avicenna’s Political Philosophy,” The Review of Politics, 41:4 (1979), pp. 561-577 James W. Morris, “The Philosopher-Prophet in Avicenna’s Political Philosophy,” in Butterworth, ed., The Political Aspects of Islamic Philosophy Charles E. Butterworth, “The Political Teaching of Avicenna,” Topoi 19 (2000), pp. 35- 44. M. Cüneyt Kaya, “In the Shadow of ‘Prophetic Legislation’: The Venture of Practical Philosophy after Avicenna,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy, 24: 2 (September 2014), pp. 269-296. Ibn Bajja (Avempace): Primary Texts in Translation: Ibn Bajja. “Governance of the Solitary,” trans. Berman in Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, eds. Joshua Parens and Joseph C. Macfarland. Cornell University Press (2011). _______. “Risalat al-wadaʿ.” In Rasaʾil Ibn Bajja al-ilahiyya. Ed. Majid Fakhry. Beirut: Dar al-Nahar, 1968. _______. “Risalat ittisal al-ʿaql bi’l-insan.” In Rasaʾil Ibn Bajja al-ilahiyya. Ed. Majid Fakhry. Beirut: Dar al-Nahar, 1968. Secondary Literature: 4 D.M. Dunlop, “Remarks on the Life and Works of Ibn Bājjah (Avempace),” Proceedings of the Twenty-Second Congress of Orientalists (Leiden: Brill, 1957), pp. 188-196. Erwin I.J. Rosenthal, “The Place of Politics in the Philosophy of Ibn Bājja,” Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, 15:2 (1953), pp. 246-278. Goodman, Lenn E. “Ibn Bajjah,” in History of Islamic Philosophy, Seyyed Hossein Nasr and Oliver Leaman, eds., (London: Routledge, 1996). Steven Harvey, “The Place of the Philosopher in the City According to Ibn Bājjah,” in Butterworth, ed., The Political Aspects of Islamic Philosophy, pp. 199-233. Ibn Tufayl: Primary Texts in Translation: Lenn E. Goodman, Ibn Tufayl’s Hayy ibn Yaqzan (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009). Secondary Literature: Carra de Vaux, B. “Ibn Tufayl,” in Encyclopedia of Islam 2. Lawrence I. Conrad, “An Andalusian Physician at the Court of the Muwahhids: Some Notes on the Public Career of Ibn Tufayl,” Al-Qantara: Revista de estudios árabes, 16:1 (1995), pp. 3-14. Lenn E. Goodman, Ibn Tufayl’s Hayy ibn Yaqzan (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2009), introduction. Hillel Fradkin, “The Political Thought of Ibn Ṭufayl,” in Butterworth, ed., The Political Aspects of Islamic Philosophy, pp. 234-261. Michael S. Kochin, “Weeds: Cultivating the Imagination in Medieval Arabic Political Philosophy,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 60.3 (1999), pp. 399-416. Murad Idris, “Ibn Ṭufayl’s Critique of Politics,” Journal of Islamic Philosophy, 7 (2011), pp. 67-101. Ibn Rushd (Averroës): Primary Texts in Translation: Averroës, Tahafut al-tahafut (The Incoherence of the Incoherence), trans. Simon van den Bergh (Oxford: Oxford University Press). 5 ________. Decisive Treatise and Epistle Dedicatory, trans. Charles E. Butterworth (Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press, 2002). ________. Bidayat al-mujtahid/ The Distinguished Jurist’s Primer trans. Nyazee. ________. Commentaire moyen à la Rhétorique d’Aristote/Averroès (Ibn Rus̆ d), trans. and ed. Maroun Aouad (Paris: Vrin, 2002.). ________. Averroes on Plato’s Republic, trans. Ralph Lerner (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1974).
Recommended publications
  • Classical Age”
    THE CULTURE OF DIVERSITY AND MUTUAL UNDERSTANDING IN ARAB ISLAMIC THOUGHT DURING THE “CLASSICAL AGE” Said Bensaid al Alaoui I – Introduction he “Classical Age” – in the sense that we use the term – refers to the period between the birth Tof Arab Islamic culture and the stage when it reached the pinnacle of its power and prosperity. Today we usually describe it as the “Arab Islamic heritage”. When we consider that heritage, we find that – regardless of how dynamic and productive it has been at certain times during the course of its existence – we are unable to place it in a particular historical period. For example, while we can say that “’Asr al Tadris” (the “Age of Scholarship”) saw the birth and burgeoning of numerous branches of Islamic knowledge – all of them related to the Holy Qur’an and the Sunnah of the Prophet (particularly Hadith) – it would also be true to say that numerous other sciences associated with the Islamic heritage did not reach their zenith until later, when they began to emerge fully fledged in various parts of the Islamic world. Academic from Morocco. 35 THE CULTURE OF DIVERSITY AND MUTUAL UNDERSTANDING IN ARAB ISLAMIC It would also be wrong to tie the heritage exclusively to “’Asr al Tadwin” (the “Age of Literary Output”), since this would ignore the numerous Islamic sciences that saw the light of day during the fourth and fifth centuries AH, as well as the previously unrecognized centres of learning – such as Cairo, Cordoba and Fez (to name but a few) – in which those sciences came to fruition.
    [Show full text]
  • Anna Karenina the Truth of Stories “ How Glorious Fall the Valiant, Sword [Mallet] in Hand, in Front of Battle for Their Native Land.” —Tyrtaeus, Spartan Poet the St
    The CollegeSUMMER 2014 • ST. JOHN’S COLLEGE • ANNAPOLIS • SANTA FE Anna Karenina The Truth of Stories “ How glorious fall the valiant, sword [mallet] in hand, in front of battle for their native land.” —Tyrtaeus, Spartan poet The St. John’s croquet team greets the cheering crowd in Annapolis. ii | The College | st. john’s college | summer 2014 from the editor The College is published by St. John’s College, Annapolis, MD, Why Stories? and Santa Fe, NM [email protected] “ He stepped down, trying not to is not just the suspense, but the connection made Known office of publication: through storytelling that matters: “Storytelling Communications Office look long at her, as if she were ought to be done by people who want to make St. John’s College the sun, yet he saw her, like the other people feel a little bit less alone.” 60 College Avenue In this issue we meet Johnnies who are story- Annapolis, MD 21401 sun, even without looking.” tellers in modern and ancient forms, filmmakers, Periodicals postage paid Leo Tolstoy, ANNA KARENINA poets, even a fabric artist. N. Scott Momaday, at Annapolis, MD Pulitzer Prize winner and artist-in-residence on Postmaster: Send address “Emotions are what pull us in—the character’s the Santa Fe campus, says, “Poetry is the high- changes to The College vulnerabilities, desires, and fears,” says screen- est expression of language.” Along with student Magazine, Communications writer Jeremy Leven (A64); he is one of several poets, he shares insights on this elegant form Office, St. John’s College, 60 College Avenue, alumni profiled in this issue of The College who and how it touches our spirits and hearts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Agent Intellect As" Form for Us" and Averroes's. Critique of Al-Farabi
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Taylor, Richard C. The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's. Critique of al-Farabi Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 29, 2005, pp. 29-51 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323027318003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's Critique of al-FarabT Richard C. Taylor Marquette University This article explicates Averroes's understanding of human knowing and abstraction in this three commentaries on Aristotle's De Anima. While Averroes's views on the nature of the human material intellect changes through the three commentaries until he reaches is famous view of the unity of the material intellect as one for all human beings, his view of the agent intellect as 'form for us' is sustained throughout these works. In his Long Commentary on the De Anima he reveals his dependence on al-Farabi for this notion and provides a detailed critique of the Farabian notion that the agent intellect is 'form for us' only as agent cause, not as our true formal cause. Although Averroes argues that the agent intellect must somehow be intrinsic to us as our form since humans 2tieper se rational and undertake acts of knowing by will, his view is shown to rest on an equivocal use of the notion of formal cause.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded File
    See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/329572822 Interpretation in Muslim Philosophy Book · January 2012 CITATIONS READS 0 323 1 author: Abduljaleel Alwali United Arab Emirates University 3 PUBLICATIONS 0 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE All content following this page was uploaded by Abduljaleel Alwali on 11 December 2018. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. Interpretation in Muslim Philosophy By Prof. Abdul Jaleel Kadhim Al Wali Philosophy Department Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences United Arab Emirates University Al Ain Abu Dhabi UAE Phone: +971-50-663-6703 [email protected] Abstract Muslim philosophers had been preoccupied with the question of interpretation since the Islamic Philosophy was first developed by its founder Al Kindi till its interpretative maturity by Ibn Rushd who represents the maturity of rationalism in Islamic Arab philosophy. Rational option was the most suitable for Arab Muslim civilization as it expresses the vitality of civilization and its ability to interact with other contemporary civilizations and trends. Islamic philosophy interpretation themes are various as they adopted the following terms: 1. Interpreting the approval of the Greek philosophy in Muslim culture. 2. Interpreting the relationship between religion and philosophy. 3. Interpreting the relationship between Mind and Mind ( Plato and Aristotle ) 4. Interpreting the relationship between nature and Metaphysics. The goals of interpretation for Muslim philosophers are different as Al Kind pointed that they are oriented towards the Greek philosophy in general and towards religion and philosophy in particular while Al Farabi pointed that they are oriented towards the Greek philosophy in general and towards Plato and Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • B Philosophy (General) B
    B PHILOSOPHY (GENERAL) B Philosophy (General) For general philosophical treatises and introductions to philosophy see BD10+ Periodicals. Serials 1.A1-.A3 Polyglot 1.A4-Z English and American 2 French and Belgian 3 German 4 Italian 5 Spanish and Portuguese 6 Russian and other Slavic 8.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z Societies 11 English and American 12 French and Belgian 13 German 14 Italian 15 Spanish and Portuguese 18.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z 20 Congresses Collected works (nonserial) 20.6 Several languages 20.8 Latin 21 English and American 22 French and Belgian 23 German 24 Italian 25 Spanish and Portuguese 26 Russian and other Slavic 28.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z 29 Addresses, essays, lectures Class here works by several authors or individual authors (31) Yearbooks see B1+ 35 Directories Dictionaries 40 International (Polyglot) 41 English and American 42 French and Belgian 43 German 44 Italian 45 Spanish and Portuguese 48.A-Z Other. By language, A-Z Terminology. Nomenclature 49 General works 50 Special topics, A-Z 51 Encyclopedias 1 B PHILOSOPHY (GENERAL) B Historiography 51.4 General works Biography of historians 51.6.A2 Collective 51.6.A3-Z Individual, A-Z 51.8 Pictorial works Study and teaching. Research Cf. BF77+ Psychology Cf. BJ66+ Ethics Cf. BJ66 Ethics 52 General works 52.3.A-Z By region or country, A-Z 52.5 Problems, exercises, examinations 52.65.A-Z By school, A-Z Communication of information 52.66 General works 52.67 Information services 52.68 Computer network resources Including the Internet 52.7 Authorship Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Hayy Ibn Yaqzan: Una Novela Filosófica De Ibn Tufayl
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Repositorio Institucional de la Universidad de Córdoba ISSN: 0213-1854 Hayy ibn Yaqzan: Una novela filosófica de Ibn Tufayl (Hayy ibn Yaqzan: A Philosophical Novel by Ibn Tufayl) ROY JACKSON [email protected] University of Gloucestershire Fecha de recepción: 21 de febrero de 2017 Fecha de aceptación: 31 de marzo de 2017 Resumen: Trabajo que aborda el relato filosófico Hayy ibn Yaqzan, titulado así por el héroe de la historia y escrito por el filósofo musulmán Ibn Tufayl (1105- 1185). Fue la primera novela árabe y se anticipó a obras europeas como Robinson Crusoe, de Daniel Defoe, y Emile, de Jean-Jacques Rousseau, así como al pensamiento de varios filósofos occidentales, incluidos Locke y Kant. Este artículo investiga los temas filosóficos contenidos en la novela, centrados en las cuestiones filosóficas clave de “¿qué podemos saber?” Y “¿cómo podemos saber?” Estas preguntas acompañan al ser humano desde el comienzo de la filosofía y siguen siendo importantes actualmente con un debate tan polémico sobre la veracidad de la experiencia no empírica. Palabras clave: Neoplatonismo. Iluminacionismo. Marifa. Orientalismo. Abstract: This is the philosophical tale Hayy ibn Yaqzan, named after the hero of this story and written by the Muslim philosopher Ibn Tufayl (1105-1185). It was the first Arabic novel, and anticipated such European works as Daniel Defoe’s Robinson Crusoe and Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s Emile, as well as the thought of a number of western philosophers including Locke and Kant. This paper will bring out the philosophical themes contained within the novel, centred on those key philosophical questions of ‘what can we know?’ and ‘how can we know?’.
    [Show full text]
  • In Memoriam: Muhsin S. Mahdi
    The Review of Politics 69 (2007), 511–512. Copyright # University of Notre Dame DOI: 10.1017/S0034670507001192 Printed in the USA In Memoriam: Muhsin S. Mahdi https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms Muhsin S. Mahdi, James Richard Jewett Emeritus Professor of Arabic at Harvard University, died on July 9 in Brookline, Massachusetts, after a pro- tracted illness. Professor Mahdi was born June 21, 1926 in Kerbala, Iraq. Following early studies there, he finished secondary school in Baghdad and then received a government scholarship to the American University in Beirut. A year later, he was sent to study economics at the University of Chicago. There, his encounter with Arnold Bergstra¨sser, Yves Simon, Nabia Abbott, and Leo Strauss led to economics being replaced by philosophy. Mahdi fin- ished his Ph.D. in 1954, and his dissertation was published as “Ibn Khaldun’s Philosophy of History: A Study in the Philosophical Foundation of the Science of Culture.” After an interlude at the University of Freiburg , subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at im Breisgau and at the University of Baghdad, he returned to the University of Chicago in 1957. There he remained until being appointed the James Richard Jewett Professor of Arabic at Harvard University in 1969, a position he held until his retirement in 1996. Professor Mahdi conducted postdoctoral study at universities in the United 29 Sep 2021 at 20:53:48 States, Europe, North Africa, and the Middle East. He was the founding , on member of the Socie´te´ Internationale pour l’Histoire des Sciences et de la Philosophie Arabes et Islamiques (SIHSPAI) and of the Middle East Studies Association, served on the editorial boards of several learned journals, was an officer in numerous other learned societies, and became the first corre- 170.106.202.126 sponding member of the Cairo Academy of Arabic Language.
    [Show full text]
  • The Fourteenth and Seventeenth Century Project of Mathematical Physics
    ORG ANON 41:2009 Elżbieta Jung (Łódź, Poland) THE FOURTEENTH AND SEVENTEENTH CENTURY PROJECT OF MATHEMATICAL PHYSICS. CONTINUITY OR DISCONTINUITY?* Introduction Medieval philosophers while commenting on Aristotle's works on natural philosophy noticed many apporiai in his physics. What is more, inspired by William of Ockham (ca. 1280-1349), they rejected Aristotelian prohibition of metabasis limiting the use of geometry only to scientice media? (intermediate sciences), such as optics or astronomy, which deal only with quantified aspects of natural phenomena and not the whole phenomenon'. In the 14th century the members of the famous English School, so-called Oxford Calculators introduced to physics both: mathematics, understood as a proper language of science, and logic understood as the convenient way to pose problems. Therefore, it seems interesting to examine if they have any project of mathematical physics and if so whether it made them stand any closer to modern science. Since it is no more doubtful that Galileo, while proving a proper rule of accelerate motion, used the Mean Speed Theorem, formulated by one of the Calculators, William Heytesbury (ca. 1313-1372)2, and that Newton employed the 14lh century theory of compounding ratios3, it seems attractive to go back to a continuity/discontinuity in the history of natural science. One of the most distinguished historians of medieval science, Annelise Maier, regarded the history of natural philosophy from the thirteenth to the 181'1 century as the history of the gradual rejection of Aristotelianism. She claimed that it did not evolve uniformly from century to century, but it " The paper is a revised version of an article titled: Why vra.v Medieval Mechanics Doomed? The Failure lo Substitute Mathematical Physics for Aristotelianism in: Miscellanea Mediaevalia: Herbst des Mittelalters? Fragen zur Bewertimg des 14, und 15.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Islam
    Istanbul 1437 / 2016 © Erkam Publications 2016 / 1437 H HISTORY OF ISLAM Original Title : İslam Tarihi (Ders Kitabı) Author : Commission Auteur du Volume « Histoire de l’Afrique » : Dr. Said ZONGO Coordinator : Yrd. Doç. Dr. Faruk KANGER Academic Consultant : Lokman HELVACI Translator : Fulden ELİF AYDIN Melda DOĞAN Corrector : Mohamed ROUSSEL Editor : İsmail ERİŞ Graphics : Rasim ŞAKİROĞLU Mithat ŞENTÜRK ISBN : 978-9944-83-747-7 Addresse : İkitelli Organize Sanayi Bölgesi Mahallesi Atatürk Bulvarı Haseyad 1. Kısım No: 60/3-C Başakşehir / Istanbul - Turkey Tel : (90-212) 671-0700 (pbx) Fax : (90-212) 671-0748 E-mail : [email protected] Web : www.islamicpublishing.org Printed by : Erkam Printhouse Language : English ERKAM PUBLICATIONS TEXTBOOK HISTORY OF ISLAM 10th GRADE ERKAM PUBLICATIONS Table of Contents TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER I THE ERA OF FOUR RIGHTLY GUIDED CALIPHS (632–661) / 8 A. THE ELECTION OF THE FIRST CALIPH .............................................................................................. 11 B. THE PERIOD OF ABU BAKR (May Allah be Pleased with him) (632–634) ....................................... 11 C. THE PERIOD OF UMAR (May Allah be Pleased with him) (634–644) ............................................... 16 D. THE PERIOD OF UTHMAN (May Allah be Pleased with him) (644–656) ........................................ 21 E. THE PERIOD OF ALI (May Allah be pleased with him) (656-661) ...................................................... 26 EVALUATION QUESTIONS .........................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Science in the Medieval Islamic World Was the Science Developed And
    Science in the medieval Islamic world was the science developed and practised during the Islamic Golden Age under the Umayyads of Córdoba, the Abbadids of Seville, the Samanids, the Ziyarids, the Buyids in Persia, the Abbasid Caliphate and beyond, spanning the period roughly between 786 and 1258. Islamic scientific achievements encompassed a wide range of subject areas, especially astronomy, mathematics, and medicine. Medieval Islamic science had practical purposes as well as the goal of understanding. For example, astronomy was useful for determining the Qibla, the direction in which to pray, botany had practical application in agriculture, as in the works of Ibn Bassal and Ibn al-'Awwam, and geography enabled Abu Zayd al- Balkhi to make accurate maps. Islamic mathematicians such as Al- Khwarizmi, Avicenna and Jamshīd al-Kāshī made advances in algebra, trigonometry, geometry and Arabic numerals. Islamic doctors described diseases like smallpox and measles, and challenged classical Greek medical theory. Al-Biruni, Avicenna and others described the preparation of hundreds of drugs made from medicinal plants and chemical compounds. Islamic physicists such as Ibn Al-Haytham, Al-Bīrūnī and others studied optics and mechanics as well as astronomy, criticised Aristotle's view of motion. The significance of medieval Islamic science has been debated by historians. The traditionalist view holds that it lacked innovation, and was mainly important for handing on ancient knowledge to medieval Europe. The revisionist view holds that it constituted a scientific revolution. Whatever the case, science flourished across a wide area around the Mediterranean and further afield, for several centuries, in a wide range of institutions.
    [Show full text]
  • Alexander Green- Portrait of Spinoza
    A PORTRAIT OF SPINOZA AS A MAIMONIDEAN RECONSIDERED Alexander Green ABSTRACT Warren Zev Harvey wrote a bold and now famous paper over thirty years ago entitled “A Portrait of Spinoza as a Maimonidean,” defending the dominant influ- ence of the philosophy of the medieval Jewish philosopher Moses Maimonides on the thought of Baruch Spinoza. However, since then, he further developed his thesis by publishing numerous articles showing that Spinoza was not only developing the ideas of Maimonides, but also was unique in synthesizing many different competing strands within medieval Jewish philosophy more generally, including those of Abraham Ibn Ezra, Levi Gersonides, and Hasdai Crescas. In other words, one can even be a Maimonidean by adapting the views of Mai- monides’s critics who nonetheless continued his philosophic legacy within the discourse that he began. While the thought and character of Baruch Spinoza has been continually scrutinized and reinterpreted in every generation since his death, I argue that Harvey’s emphasis on the diversity of Jewish sources within Spinoza’s thought aims to be a model for a political liberalism that is rooted within the texts of the Jewish tradition, while also one that advocates an intellectual pluralism. Over thirty years ago, Warren Zev Harvey wrote a bold and now famous paper entitled “A Portrait of Spinoza as a Maimonidean” in the Journal of the History of Philosophy, defending the dominant influence of the philosophy of the medi- eval Jewish philosopher Moses Maimonides on the thought of Baruch Spinoza.1 Since then, he further developed his thesis by publishing numerous articles showing that Spinoza was not only developing the ideas of Maimonides, but that of the tradition of medieval Jewish philosophy more generally, and even of the occasional kabbalist.
    [Show full text]
  • Tyranny and Political Philosophy
    TYRANNY AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY David Moreno Guinea, Ph. D. University of Dallas, 2021 Dr. Joshua Parens Tyranny is a theme that reverberates in politico-philosophical scholarship since the post- war era of the twentieth century and it has been taken up with a renewed interest in recent years. Aside from Leo Strauss, only very few scholars have focused on the link between ancient and modern tyranny, and even fewer on how the concept of tyranny might give insight into the study of political philosophy itself. In this dissertation, I argue that the concept of tyranny can make us aware of the permanent character of the problems that arise between philosophy and politics, and help us distinguish between the core and the peripheral tenets of political philosophy. On this basis, I contend that it is possible to draw a closer connection between Socratic and Machiavellian political philosophy. Through a close reading of select passages of Xenophon, Plato and Aristotle, on the one hand, and of Machiavelli, on the other, I address the main differences that separate the philosophic from the political way of life. I first analyze the concept of tyranny from the viewpoint of the city and of “real men” (andres), and then contrast it with the perspective of the philosopher. I assert that the praise of kalokagathia is more of a concession than the real essence of the classics’ philosophic teachings. Although I show that there is a close connection between the philosopher and the tyrant, I also explain what sets them apart. The subtle distinction that the classics made between the principles of their philosophic politics as opposed to the principles of philosophy itself, I argue, helps us to understand the classics better and to read Machiavelli in a different, more benevolent and more philosophical light.
    [Show full text]