Albinus' Metaphysics. an Attempt at Rehabilitation By

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Albinus' Metaphysics. an Attempt at Rehabilitation By ALBINUS' METAPHYSICS. AN ATTEMPT AT REHABILITATION BY J. H. LOENEN ' II. The sources of Albinus' metaphysics. In the first part of this article I have tried to show the originality of Albinus' interpretation of Plato's metaphysics as a whole. It re- mains to inquire in how far originality may be ascribed to him as regards the details of his interpretation. Here we touch on the ticklish subject of the sources. It is often assumed that an indi- cation of the sources is a sufficient explanation of a philosopher's system 1). Yet methodically one ought to start from the presumption of his originality. The question must therefore be put in this way: which certain, or very probable, results have been achieved by the study of the sources of Albinus and to what extent is his originality diminished by it? I shall divide this inquiry into two parts, by studying first the sources of Albinus in general, and then the sources of the elements out of which his metaphysics have been built up. In doing so one must pay special attention to the question what exactly it is one wants to prove and whether the data justify the conclusion. In my opinion scholars have not always been sufficiently discerning in this respect. It is e.g. of fundamental importance whether it can only be proved that a certain thinkers i ) It is tempting to cite here a passage from P. Thevenaz, L'dme du monde, le devenir et la matiere chez Plutarque (Th6se), Neuchâtel 1938, p. 125-6: "La fameuse m6thode de recherche des sources est venue fausser, me semble-t-il, 1'6tude des philosophes secondaires; elle se fonde souvent. sur un pr6jug6 vivace: un auteur secondaire ou eclectique n'est pas tres intelligent; sa pens6e manque d'unit6 et sa philosophie n'est pas vLcue. L'expliquer consiste a faire la somme de ses sources, a d6couper son oeuvre pour restituer leur bien a ceux qu'il a pilhss. On ne peut m6connattre plus. totalement ce qu'est une influence dans le domaine de 1'esprit. Les id6es ne se transmettent pas comme des pi6ces de monnaie, par simple distri- bution m6canique". He then refers to an inquiry of P. Boyanc6 concerning historical method in the study of Cicero (Rev. Et. latines 14 (1936), p. z88-- 309) and points out that more than one of his observations also applies to. the study of Plutarch. This is no less true for Albinus. 36 knew a preceding one, viz. read him (and was therefore more or less influenced by him), or that he used him in the strict sense as a source. And in the last case the influence may have been worked up into a personal system, so that his predecessor only served as a material source, or the author may have adopted the central thoughts and all the essential elements. The sources of Albinus in general. Two authors have been pointed out as the sources of Albinus: (i) Gaius, and (2) Antiochus of Askalon via Arius Didymus. We do not know anything for certain about Gaius' life and doctrine 1). Yet half a century ago Th. Sinko defended the thesis that Albinus and Apuleius, independently of each other, used Gaius as a source, so that from these two Gaius' doctrine might be reconstructed 2). This would imply for Albinus that he has no originality whatever. This hypothesis was also adopted in a more moderate form by Praechter. He, too, assumes for both authors a common dependence on Gaius, but he denies that in this way Gaius' doctrine might be reconstructed, because "ein unmittelbares Schiilerverhaltnis des Apuleius zu Gaios...., wenn auch moglich, so doch unerweislich ist" 3). Praechter, however, thinks that it "hbchstwahrscheinlich bleibt", that Albinus and Apuleius "in allem Wesentlichen auf Gaios zurfckgehen" (italics mine), because Albinus directly and Apuleius directly or indirectly (via a work of Albinus which cannot, however, have been the ,,Didaskalikos") have borrowed from Gaius'). Br6hier, too, thinks it impossible to dispense with the hypothesis of Sinko 5). In criticizing this hypothesis I do not have to dwell on the extreme thesis of Sinko, because Praechter's objection is fully justified, but I must consider whether the resemblances between Albinus and Apuleius are such that for the two of them dependence on Gaius (for Apuleius possibly in an indirect way) must be assumed 1) I refer to Louis, o.c., p. XIII-XIV, and to K. Praechter, Zum Pla- toniker Gaios, Hermes 51(1916), p. 510-29. 2) Th. Sinko, De Apulei et Albini doctrinae Platonicae adumbratione, Cracov. 1905, p. 42 sq. 3) Ueberweg-Praechter, p. 546. 4) Praechter, o.c. (Zum Platoniker Gaios), p. 510 n. 5) Br6hier, o.c., p. 41. .
Recommended publications
  • The Politics of Roman Memory in the Age of Justinian DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the D
    The Politics of Roman Memory in the Age of Justinian DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Marion Woodrow Kruse, III Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2015 Dissertation Committee: Anthony Kaldellis, Advisor; Benjamin Acosta-Hughes; Nathan Rosenstein Copyright by Marion Woodrow Kruse, III 2015 ABSTRACT This dissertation explores the use of Roman historical memory from the late fifth century through the middle of the sixth century AD. The collapse of Roman government in the western Roman empire in the late fifth century inspired a crisis of identity and political messaging in the eastern Roman empire of the same period. I argue that the Romans of the eastern empire, in particular those who lived in Constantinople and worked in or around the imperial administration, responded to the challenge posed by the loss of Rome by rewriting the history of the Roman empire. The new historical narratives that arose during this period were initially concerned with Roman identity and fixated on urban space (in particular the cities of Rome and Constantinople) and Roman mythistory. By the sixth century, however, the debate over Roman history had begun to infuse all levels of Roman political discourse and became a major component of the emperor Justinian’s imperial messaging and propaganda, especially in his Novels. The imperial history proposed by the Novels was aggressivley challenged by other writers of the period, creating a clear historical and political conflict over the role and import of Roman history as a model or justification for Roman politics in the sixth century.
    [Show full text]
  • Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources of the Central Christian Doctrine
    ! Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources ! of the Central Christian Doctrine Marian Hillar Center for Philosophy and Socinian Studies Houston, TX 77004 Paper published in A Journal from the Radical Reformation. A testimony to Biblical Unitarianism. Vol. 14, No.! 1, Spring 2007, pp. 3-31. Quis obsecro, nisi penitus amens logomachias has sine risu toleraret? Nec in Thalmud, nec in Alchoran, sunt tam horrendae blasfemiae. Haec nos hactenus audire ita sumus alsuefacti, ut nihil miremur. Futurae vero generationes stupenda haec iudicabunt. Stupenda sunt vere, plusquam ea daemonum inventa, quae Valentinianis tribuit Irenaeus. I implore you, who in his sane mind could tolerate such logomachias without bursting into laughter? Not in the Talmud, nor in the Qu’ran can one find such horrendous blasphemies. But we are accustomed to hear them to the point that nothing astonishes us. Future generations will judge them obscure. Indeed, they are obscure, much more than the diabolic inventions which Irenaeus attributed to the Valentinians. ! Michael Servetus Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. I. p. 46. Si locum mihi aliquem ostendas, quo verbum illud filius olim vocetur, fatebor me victum. Christianismi Restitutio, If you show me a single passage in which the Son was called the Word, I will give up. Michael Servetus, Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. III p. 108. ! Abstract This paper attempts to explain the sources of the central Christian doctrine about the nature of deity. We can trace a continuous line of thought from the Greek philosophy to the development of the doctrine of the Trinity. The first Christian doctrine was developed by Justin Martyr (114-165 C.E.).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Duae Patriae
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86331-5 - Ethnic Identity and Aristocratic Competition in Republican Rome Gary D. Farney Excerpt More information 1 duae patriae ᨠᨘᨠ 1. Partners in Empire “Because the Romans mixed with themselves Etruscans, Latins, and Sabines and regard there to be one blood from all of these, they have made one body from these various parts and one people composed of 1 all of them.” In this way, the second-century a.d. Roman historian Florus describes the traditional ethnic composition of Rome at the beginning of his chapter on the Social War, Rome’s war with its Italian allies which began in 91 b.c. Although he would judge the actions of the rebels to be criminal, he goes on to criticize Rome for not sharing 2 the citizenship with the deserving peoples of Italy sooner. After all, as a contemporary of Florus would echo in his history, the Italian upper classes had only led the revolt because they had desired to be “partners 3 in empire instead of subjects.” Implicit within these comments is that the Latins, Sabines, and Etruscans had dared to hope this before and had succeeded, and now they were the dominant groups within the Roman state. Their dominance, however, seemed to exclude men from dozens of other groups from a place in the state, notably Rome’s allies that had exerted so much on its behalf. 1 Epit. 2.6.1: quippe cum populus Romanus Etruscos, Latinos Sabinosque sibi miscuerit et unum ex omnibus sanguinem ducat, corpus fecit ex membris et ex omnibus unus est.
    [Show full text]
  • Alcinous' Reception of Plato
    chapter 10 Alcinous’ Reception of Plato Carl S. O’Brien* I Introduction It is clear now that the author of the Didaskalikos was indeed Alcinous, and the attribution to Albinus should be regarded as an error, resulting from a mis- guided conjecture by Freudenthal.1 Alcinous’ use of Plato can be characterized in terms of three central features. Firstly, his work is a handbook or instruction manual, although the level of instruction at certain points can seem relatively advanced. This suggests that it is not a handbook intended for beginners, but rather those who have already received some instruction in Platonism (pos- sibly as a refresher manual for teachers of Platonism).2 Secondly, Alcinous composed the Didaskalikos during the phase of Platonism identified as Mid- dle Platonic and, as is typical of the period, Aristotelian and Stoic strands and terminology are combined with his Platonic heritage (although one must also note that many of the Aristotelian and Stoic elements which find their way into Middle Platonism often had a Platonic inspiration to begin with). In light of the lack of a distinctive “orthodox” Platonism, a range of opinions was toler- ated and regarded as philosophically acceptable. This is undertaken from the dual perspective of modernizing or updating Plato, as well as claiming sub- sequent Aristotelian and Stoic advances for Plato himself; a good example is logic at Did. 5, which can be claimed to owe its origin to Platonic dialectic, although Plato himself never identified logic as a subdivision of philosophy. Thirdly, Plato is reduced by Alcinous to a series of dogmata or doctrines; he is stripped of his literary character and, although it is clear that Plato’s philoso- phy permeates the Didaskalikos, we do not get the sense of Alcinous drawing upon any dialogue in its entirety.
    [Show full text]
  • This Is for the Person About to Delve (Entunchanesthai) Into the Dialogues of Plato, It Is Appropriate First to Understand This: What a Dialogue Really Is
    CHS—How and why to read Plato in the early common era Fowler a. Albinus Introduction to Plato’s Dialogues (Eisagōgē or Prologos) 1 This is for the person about to delve (entunchanesthai) into the dialogues of Plato, it is appropriate first to understand this: what a dialogue really is. b. Plato Sophist 263e Stranger: Well, then, thought (dianoia) and speech (logos) are the same; only the former, which is a silent inner conversation (dialogos) of the soul with itself, has been given the special name of thought (dianoia). Is not that true? c. Lucian Literary Prometheus 6 For one thing, there was no great original connexion or friendship between Dialogue and Comedy; the former was a stay-at-home, spending his time in solitude, or at most taking a stroll with a few intimates; whereas Comedy put herself in the hands of Dionysus, haunted the theatre, frolicked in company, laughed and mocked and tripped it to the flute when she saw good; nay, she would mount her anapaests, as likely as not, and pelt the friends of Dialogue with nicknames--doctrinaires, airy metaphysicians, and the like. […] But Dialogue continued his deep speculations upon Nature and Virtue, till, as the musicians say, the interval between them was two full octaves, from the highest to the lowest note. d. Justin Martyr Dialogue with Trypho 3.3-4 “‘I delight,’ said I, ‘in such walks, where my attention is not distracted, for discussion (dialogos) with myself is uninterrupted; and such places are most fit for philology.’ “‘Are you, then, a philologian (phiologos),’ said he, ‘but no lover of deeds (philergos) or of truth (philalēthēs)? and do you not aim at being a practical man so much as being a sophist?’” e.
    [Show full text]
  • PROBLEMS CONCERNING JUSTIN MARTYR Did Justin Find A
    PROBLEMS CONCERNING JUSTIN MARTYR Did Justin find a Certain Continuity between Greek Philosophy and Christian Faith ? BY C. J. DE VOGEL During the last decad Justin Martyr has been the subject of a renewed discussion which, in some respects, went further or was more radical than the preceding ones. In 1966, the same year in which Henry Chadwick's small but highly interesting volume Early Christian Thought and the Classical Tradition appeared at Oxford, N. Hyldahl published quite a substantial study entitled Philosophie und Chyistentum. Eine Interpretation der Einleitung zum Dialog Justins at Copenhagen. In this handsome volume quite a revolutionary picture is given of what Justin's attitude towards Greek philosophy might have been. Briefly summarized Hyldahl's thesis is the following. Justin has never been a student of any school of Greek philos- ophy ; the story told in Dial. 2, of his passing through different philosophers' schools is just a literary fiction, well-known in those days; as to Platonism, Justin never heard any courses of philosophy in some Platonist school of his surroundings, nor did he ever adhere to any such school; what he meant by "true philosophy" was Christian faith, and this he opposed to any form of Greek pl-ilos- ophy,-except in so far as philosophy borrowed certain things from "Moses". For the rest, Hyldahl does grant that Justin had a fairly good idea of what Platonism is like; he knew several passages of Plato's works, either directly or indirectly, and interpreted the Timaeus in the way Albinus did, by identifying the Demiurge with the biblical God-Creator.
    [Show full text]
  • Proceedings Ofthe Danish Institute at Athens IV
    Proceedings ofthe Danish Institute at Athens IV Edited by Jonas Eiring and Jorgen Mejer © Copyright The Danish Institute at Athens, Athens 2004 The publication was sponsored by: The Danish Research Council for the Humanities Generalkonsul Gosta Enboms Fond. Proceedings of the Danish Institute at Athens General Editors: Jonas Eiring and Jorgen Mejer. Graphic design and production: George Geroulias, Press Line. Printed in Greece on permanent paper. ISBN: 87 7288 724 9 Distributed by: AARHUS UNIVERSITY PRESS Langelandsgade 177 DK-8200 Arhus N Fax (+45) 8942 5380 73 Lime Walk Headington, Oxford 0X3 7AD Fax (+44) 865 750 079 Box 511 Oakvill, Conn. 06779 Fax (+1)203 945 94 9468 Cover illustration: Finds from the Hellenistic grave at Chalkis, Aetolia. Photograph by Henrik Frost. The Platonic Corpus in Antiquity Jorgen Mejer Plato is the one and only philosopher particular edition which has determined from Antiquity whose writings have not only the Medieval tradition but also been preserved in their entirety. And our modern knowledge of Platonic dia not only have they been preserved, they logues, goes back to the Roman have been transmitted as a single col Emperor Tiberius' court-astrologer, lection of texts. Our Medieval manu Thrasyllus.2 Tarrant demonstrates rather scripts seem to go back to one particu convincingly that there is little basis for lar edition, an archetypus in two vol assuming that the tetralogical arrange umes, as appears from the subscript to ment existed before Thrasyllus, that it is the dialogue Menexenus, which is the possible to identify a philosophical posi last dialogue in the seventh tetralogy: tion which explains the tetralogies, that T8>iog toD JtQcbxou 6i6)dou.
    [Show full text]
  • Plotinus and the Platonic Metaphysical Hierarchy
    PLOTINUS AND THE PLATONIC METAPHYSICAL HIERARCHY G.S. BOWE Global Scholarly Publications New York, New York 2003 Published by Global Scholarly Publications Copyright © 2004 by G5. Bowe All rights reserved. No portion of this publication may be dupli­ cated in any way without the expressed written consent of the publisher, except in the form of brief excerpts or quotations for review purposes. Typeface: Garamond. Greek Typeface: Athenian Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data G.S. Bowe, 1969- Plotinus and the Platonic Metaphysical Hierarchy / G.S. Bowe. p.cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-9724918-4-8 1. Plotinus - Metaphysics. 2. Aristotle -- Metaphysics. 3. Plato - Metaphysics. 4. Greek Philosophy. I. Title Distributed by Global Scholarly Publications 220 Madison Avenue, Suite llG New York, New York 10016 www.gsp-online.org [email protected] Phone: (212) 679-6410 Fax: (212) 679-6424 For my buddy jlknur CONTENTS ACKl'lOWLEDGEMENTS INTRODUCTION iii CHAPTER I - THE PLATONIC METAPHYSICAL HIERARCHY CHAPTER II - iVIElliEXlS !li'lD THE PRINCIPLES OF EMj\NATION 33 t Positive Production 37 2. Non Convertibility 44 3. Indexed Unity 47 4. The Priority of the Simple 49 CHAPTER HI - PLOTINUS' RESPONSE TO ARISTOTLE'S UNMOVED MOVER 57 1. The Unmoved Mover as Substance 58 2. The Unmoved Mover as NolIS 69 CHAPTER IV - THE DIDASKAlJKOS AND NUMENIUS 87 1. The Didaskalikos 88 2. Numenius of Apamea 96 CHAPTER V - THE ONE OF PLOTINUS 105 CHAPTER VI - ErvlANATION AND THE SOUL 131 BIBLIOGRAPHY 155 INDEX 163 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I should thank a number of people who helped me do this.
    [Show full text]
  • Athenian Agora ® Athens at Studies CC-BY-NC-ND
    THE ATHENIANAGORA RESULTS OF EXCAVATIONS CONDUCTED BY THE AMERICAN SCHOOL OF CLASSICAL STUDIES AT ATHENS VOLUME II Athens COINS at FROM THE ROMAN THROUGH THE VENETIAN PERIOD BY Studies CC-BY-NC-ND. MARGARET THOMPSON License: Classical of fbj AP A J only. Ak~ use School personal American © For THE AMERICAN SCHOOL OF CLASSICAL STUDIES AT ATHENS PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY I954 American School of Classical Studies at Athens is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve, and extend access to The Athenian Agora ® www.jstor.org Athens at Studies CC-BY-NC-ND. License: Classical PRINTED of only. use IN School GERMANY ALL RIGHTS personal at American J.J.AUGUSTIN RESERVED © For GLOCKSTADT PREFACE Between the years 1931 and 1949 the American excavations in the Athenian Agora produced 55,492 coins of Roman and later periods. The catalogued entries in this publication, ranging in date from the last century of the Roman Republic to the declining years of the Republic of Venice, total 37,090 specimens; the remaining Islamic and Modern Greek pieces have been Athens listed summarily in order that the tally may be complete. This is an overwhelming amount of at coinage, which in sheer quantity represents a collection comparableto many in the numismatic museums of the world. Unfortunately very few of the Agora coins are museum pieces, but lamentable as is their general condition to the eye of the coin collector or the cataloguer, they do provide for the historian an invaluable record of the money circulating in one of the chief cities of from the time of Sulla to our own Studies antiquity present.
    [Show full text]
  • A Numismatic Iconographical Study of Julian the Apostate
    A Revolutionary or a Man of his Time? A Numismatic Iconographical Study of Julian the Apostate Master’s Thesis in Classical Archaeology and Ancient History, Spring 2018 Department of Archaeology and Ancient History Lund University Author: Nicolas Frendin Supervisor: Henrik Gerding 2 Abstract Julian the Apostate’s short rule has left in the historical records a clearly divisive picture. This thesis starts with that divisive nature of the reign of Rome’s last pagan emperor and aims to analyse some of the Apostate’s coinage iconography. Can the symbols used on the coins minted during his reign say something about his allegedly revolutionary rule? By choosing to focus on a set of ten symbols found of Julian’s coins, this thesis was subsequently divided in a three-phased analysis in order to approach the subject. Julian’s coin iconography was first analysed in comparison to the totality of the Roman Emperors, stretching back to Octavian/Augustus. The second step was to put Julian’s rule within its own context and compare his coinage iconography to that of his predecessors in his own family, the second Flavian dynasty. The last step was to observe the changes during Julian’s two periods of time in power: being first a Caesar – subordinate to his cousin Constantius II – and later on the sole ruler/Augustus. Julian’s iconography was also compared to Constantius’. The results tend to show that most of Julian’s coin iconography could be characterised as conventional. The true departures can be divided into either obvious or surprising ones. 3 Contents
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Lives: the Academics
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-30-1986 Philosophical Lives: The Academics Jorgen Mejer University of Copenhagen Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Mejer, Jorgen, "Philosophical Lives: The Academics" (1986). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 141. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/141 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Philosophical Lives : The Academics. J0rgen Mejer (San Antonio, University of Copenhagen. December 30, 1986) No philosophical school has had a longer life than the ancient Academy, founded by Plato in the early 380'es BC and continuing well beyond that NOTE f epoch-making year 529 AD. No ancient philosophical school has a history which is better documented ¡than the Academy, despite major gaps in our knowledge of the school (its activities and its members) in particular in the centuries around the birth of Christ. Although, or perhaps because, the ancient sources are so numerous, no modern ac­ count of the history of the school as a whole exists. This is not least regrettable for the period after 200 AD when the Greek commentators on Aristotle, and to some extent on Plato, as well as other sources supply a vast amount of material illustrating the activities of the school.
    [Show full text]
  • “Roman”: Creating Identity in an Expanding World by Claudia I. Arno
    How Romans Became “Roman”: Creating Identity in an Expanding World by Claudia I. Arno A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Greek and Roman History) in The University of Michigan 2012 Doctoral Committee: Professor David S. Potter, Co-Chair Professor Nicola Terrenato, Co-Chair Professor Bruce W. Frier Professor Raymond H. Van Dam © Claudia I. Arno 2012 To my family and friends, whose support is invaluable. ii Acknowledgements I owe a great many individuals and institutions thanks for their support and assistance during the years I have been researching and writing this dissertation. I would first like to thank the University of Michigan Interdepartment Program in Greek and Roman History, which promotes the interdisciplinary study of Classics and History, and with which I am very proud to be associated. I am also grateful to the University of Michigan History and Classics Departments, whose cooperation makes IPGRH possible. I would especially like to thank my graduate colleagues in IPGRH, Classics, and History, who have made my graduate experience so enjoyable and rewarding. The staffs at the Univeristy of Michigan and UCLA libraries, as well as the UCLA History Department, and in particular Professor David Phillips, were critical in helping me obtain access to research materials while I was living in Michigan, Los Angeles, and Boston. I would also like to express my deep admiration for Dr. Susan Lipshutz, who I unfortunately never had the opportunity to meet, but whose devotion to the success of women in academia inspired the creation of an award fund from which I received valuable support.
    [Show full text]