The Role of Human Function in Defining Happiness

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Role of Human Function in Defining Happiness Universal Journal of Psychology 2(7): 218-223, 2014 http://www.hrpub.org DOI: 10.13189/ujp.2014.020702 The Role of Human Function in Defining Happiness Leria Ileana Boroş University of Bucharest, Romania *Corresponding Author: [email protected] Copyright © 2014 Horizon Research Publishing All rights reserved. Abstract In this paper I argue that the Aristotelian first book of Nicomachean Ethics that eudaimonia is the concept of “human function” is at the heart of understanding highest good1 and that to explain what happiness is one must the moral concept of “happiness” (ε δαιμονία). There are show what the human function (to ergon tou anthropou) is2. many controversies related to Aristotle’s account on The account on eudaimonia and ergon has given rise to happiness. My statement is that we canὐ gain a better insight many controversies caused by the ambiguous text of Book I on happiness by reference to “human function” (τ ργον of Nicomachean Ethics, as well as by some inconsistencies το νθρ που), provided that we understand what the between this book and Chapters 6, 7 and 8 of Book X, which philosopher meant by this latter concept. Accordingὸ ἔ to some authors even think were erroneously included in Aristotle,ῦ ἀ ώhappiness is the highest good for humans and the Aristotle’s work. In any case, Aristotle is assigned too many human good is a proper exercise of the human function. Thus, flaws and illogical statements or invalid judgments. The text the understanding of happiness relies on the understanding of should be understood, however, in the context of the human function, because human good and perfection depend, Aristotelian logic, not in the logic of each commentator. in Aristotle’s account, on the proper exercise of this function. I will further analyze the content of Chapter 7 of Book I of Aristotle gives a complex account on reason, but in the tenth Nicomachean Ethics, also calling at the Greek philosopher’s book of Nicomachean Ethics he seems to support an various works and I will argue that there is enough coherence intellectualist view on happiness, i.e. a view which only in his writings in order to understand what Aristotle’s makes reference to the activity in accordance with the virtue message about happiness was. I will not give a broad appropriate to the most elevated part of our soul. In other interpretation of eudaimonia, but I will limit myself to words, contemplation would equal happiness. However, explain the concept in the text of Chapter 7 of Book I of such a narrow view would contradict Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics and by reference to the concept of comprehensivist approach in the first book of Nicomachean function (ergon), which is actually at the heart of Ethics. An intellectualist account would be in contradiction understanding the meaning of happiness. I will endeavor to with Aristotle’s definition of eudaimonia from the first book show, through the analysis of Chapter 7 of the first book of of Nicomachean Ethics. Contemplation alone is not Nicomachean Ethics, that there is consistency between this happiness, but it is a special type of happy life. However, book and the tenth book, to this coherence also contributing happiness comprises other “goods” as well, since the human various passages from De Anima, Topics and Metaphysics. function refers to the complex part of the soul which is It is of utmost importance to keep in mind what Aristotle reason. tells us about happiness in the first book of Nicomachean Ethics in order not to err on a wrong path of argumentation. Keywords Happiness, Function, Reason, Aristotle has a peculiar technical vocabulary and thus we Comprehensivist Approach, Intellectualist View, have to pay attention to all the concepts he is using. We must Contemplation not forget that for Aristotle happiness (eudaimonia) is a type of good (agathon). Aristotle tells us that any activity, art, science and so on is done for the sake of a peculiar good (agathon). Thus, the 1. Introduction good is the end towards which all are aiming; in other words, the good is the final cause and for the sake of it is The seventh chapter of the first book of Aristotle’s everything done. There is no higher end, because it would Nicomachean Ethics is deemed to be a difficult text, because be absurd to go on a search so indefinitely. Achieving this it contains several ambiguities. These ambiguities are supreme good is of great importance to man and therefore primarily related to the way we understand happiness its knowledge is important. It is the subject of science. The (eudaimonia), which is the supreme good, and its relation to 1 The highest good is David Ross’ translation of the greek word ἄριστον human function, which is the specific activity of a human that appears in Aristotle’s text. Roger Crisp translates it by chief good. being. Aristotle himself tells us in the seventh chapter of the 2 Roger Crisp translates τὸ ἔργον τοῦ ἀνθρώπου by “the characteristic activity of a human being” and David Ross by “the function of man”. Universal Journal of Psychology 2(7): 218-223, 2014 219 knowledge of the good is the task of politics for it is eudaimonia and respectively ergon are in a very close responsible for determining the best activities in the state. connection and in a very profound mutual support. Instead, Other sciences, such as strategy, economics, rhetoric are for the comprehensivists, eudaimonia and ergon are simply subordinate to politics, but the latter is the most important amounts of other elements. According to the science because it deals with the peace of the city, whose comprehensivist view, happiness is a sum of elements such achievement is superior to the achievement of the individual as health, honors, financial security, satisfying relationships good. etc. Aristotle thinks that everybody agrees that the supreme There are some passages that seem to support this good is happiness (eudaimonia). However, when it comes to comprehensivist interpretation, but there are also others explain what happiness is, there is no agreement. People which seem rather to favor authors who interpret the conceive eudaimonia by their lifestyle and there are three concepts of eudaimonia and ergon in an intellectualist main ways to live life: to enjoy pleasure, to live a political manner. These latter rely mainly on excerpts from the tenth life, or to dedicate oneself to a contemplative life (theoretiké). book of Nicomachean Ethics where Aristotle comes back at But eudaimonia has to be defined by reference to human the idea of eudaimonia as an activity of the soul in function, for the human being’s good is the good exercise of accordance with the most perfect virtue – sophia, the his/her function (ergon), i.e. an optimal activity (energéia). intellectual wisdom, this activity being a contemplative The human function is the reason, because reason is the (theoretiké) one and belonging to the intellect (nous), which humans’ specific activity. Thus, happiness is the good is the highest element within us and whose objects are also exercise of activity? It is activity (exercise of function) the highest among the objects of knowledge. Under this according to the virtues of the rational part of the soul, since approach, human function is an activity of the intellect the human being’s function is the rational life. (nous) alone. Contemplation is happiness for it is a perfect end, it is not chosen for the sake of something else. But this approach, though seemingly favoured by Aristotle in the 2. The Main Approaches in Interpreting tenth book of Nicomachean Ethics, is not coherent with the Happiness and the Human Function philosopher’s account on the happy life as a life which implies ethical virtue, friends, honors, family, health and so The main interpretations resulting from the difficulties on. posed by Book I and Book X of Nicomachean Ethics can be Disputes between the two orientations – inclusivist and grouped into two main orientations: the inclusivist and the comprehensivist – originate as well in the difficulties raised intellectualist or monistic. There is a more radical in translating the Greek text. For instance, Aristotle tells us orientation, which considers that publishers have wrongly that happiness is teleion (Nicomachean Ethics 1097b20). introduced chapters 6, 7 and 8 in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Some authors translate teleion by “final” and others by Ethics. Timothy D. Roche contradicts those who support “complete”. Translation differences arise again in a passage this idea, arguing that the three chapters are prefigured even where we meet teleiotaten as an attribute of virtue, in Book I of the treaty (Roche, 1988). He also challenges translated by “the most complete” (Nicomachean Ethics the approaches of reviewers who claim that Aristotle 1098a15-17). In these circumstances differences in proposed a selfish version of happiness. This reviewer interpretation are unavoidable. The inclusivists will prefer believes that Aristotle was only interested in the intellectual the translation of “teleion” as "complete" for both the activity as a key of happiness. Roche (1988) is also attributes of eudaimonia and of virtue, while intellectualists criticizing other authors who have argued something more will opt for "perfect". absurd namely that according to the intellectualist vision of Most commentators have insisted on some alleged eudaimonia there are allowed even immoral actions if they incompatibility between Book I, in particular the seventh serve the philosophical activity. We cannot accept such an chapter, and Chapters 6, 7 and 8 of Book X, ignoring the interpretation since Aristotle pays so much attention to very close connection between the first chapters of Book X ethics. Even the name of his work – Nicomachen Ethics – is and those considered problematic.
Recommended publications
  • Virtue and Happiness: a Philosophical Inquiry
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Wits Institutional Repository on DSPACE VIRTUE AND HAPPINESS: A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY Muhammad Assadallah Schuitema 320900 A Research Report submitted to the Faculty of Humanities, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, Applied Ethics for Professionals University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, 16th March 2015 1 Abstract The position that holds that virtue, as a good, is sufficient for happiness has had illustrious exponents in the past. We will refer to this position as the sufficiency thesis. In recent times however this position has fallen into disfavour. This is largely due to the strong intuition that certain goods other than virtue are necessary for happiness. We will refer to this as the problem of external goods. The point of this paper is to respond to the problem of external goods by articulating an understanding of virtue as involving the ability to occupy a “distanced perspective” within which the virtuous agent becomes detached from external goods insofar as he comes to view them as indifferent. My articulation of this understanding of virtue will be based upon what I take to be the core of the Stoic description of virtue. 2 Declaration I declare that this research report is my own unaided work. It is submitted for the degree of Master of Arts in the University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg. It has not been submitted before for any other degree or examination in any other university.
    [Show full text]
  • Sexual Orientation and the Law. by Richard D. Mohr. Harry V
    University of Minnesota Law School Scholarship Repository Constitutional Commentary 1991 Book Review: Sexual Orientation and the Law. by Richard D. Mohr. Harry V. Jaffa Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Jaffa, Harry V., "Book Review: Sexual Orientation and the Law. by Richard D. Mohr." (1991). Constitutional Commentary. 395. https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/concomm/395 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Constitutional Commentary collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1991] BOOK REVIEW 313 ical context, Karst illuminates their connection to the creation of a system of caste. Having given judges the tools to work with, Karst renews the argument for the centrality of the federal judiciary, and particularly the Supreme Court, in remedying the hurt of exclusion. Judicial enforcement of the equal citizenship principle vindicates the central tenets of the American civic culture, invites outsiders into the na­ tional community, and promotes the national good by assuring that no group is a permanent loser in the political process. As we begin the 1990s, this prescription seems hauntingly sad. A court that could tell Native Americans that their religious prac­ tices (and everyone else's, for that matter) were the proper subject of political brokering7 is an unlikely candidate for spiritual leader in the quest for constitutional equality. But as Karst himself points out, the strength of the judicial commitment to equality has never been the measure of its pull on American consciousness-else how could Brown v.
    [Show full text]
  • Voegelin and Strauss on Thomas Hobbes
    A Comparison and Evaluation of Interpretation: Voegelin and Strauss on Thomas Hobbes Copyright 2002 Jeremy J. Mhire In the beginning of his essay on Thomas Hobbes in What is Political Philosophy, Leo Strauss asks the rather salient question of why we, as students of political philosophy in contemporary times, should read Hobbes?29 [1] The simplicity of this question, to say nothing of its relevance, cannot be overlooked. To study Hobbesian political philosophy is to say that it is relevant to us in some way; it speaks to us precisely because it allows us the ability to understand ourselves more fully. As our self‐ understanding is at least partially informed through the modern perspective, it makes sense to return to the thoughts of one who was influential in creating that perspective. This was certainly the standpoint of both Strauss and Eric Voegelin, two of the most influential political philosophers of the last century. By returning to Hobbes�s thought, both Strauss and Voegelin wished to revive those insights that 29 [1] Leo Strauss, What is Political Philosophy (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1959), p. 170. played a crucial role in defining how we understand ourselves today. This essay, then, is first and foremost a general attempt to understand the ways in which both Eric Voegelin and Leo Strauss used Hobbes�s political philosophy as a means through which the modern project, or modernity more simply, could be better understood. This will involve an examination of the key themes that both Voegelin and Strauss thought important to properly understand Hobbes�s political philosophy in particular, and its relationship to modernity more generally.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Ethics
    15 BONNIE KENT Augustine’s ethics Augustine regards ethics as an enquiry into the Summum Bonum: the supreme good, which provides the happiness all human beings seek. In this respect his moral thought comes closer to the eudaimonistic virtue ethics of the classical Western tradition than to the ethics of duty and law associated with Christianity in the modern period. But even though Augustine addresses many of the same problems that pagan philosophers do, he often defends very different answers. For him, happiness consists in the enjoyment of God, a reward granted in the afterlife for virtue in this life. Virtue itself is a gift of God, and founded on love, not on the wisdom prized by philosophers. The art of living In Book 8 of De civitate Dei Augustine describes “moral philosophy” (a Latin expression), or “ethics” (the Greek equivalent), as an enquiry into the supreme good and how we can attain it. The supreme good is that which we seek for its own sake, not as a means to some other end, and which makes us happy. Augustine adds, as if this were an uncontroversial point, that happiness is the aim of philosophy in general.1 Book 19 opens with a similar discussion. In his summary of Varro’s treatise De philosophia, Augustine reports that no school of philosophy deserves to be considered a distinct school unless it differs from others on the supreme good. For the supreme good is that which makes us happy, and the only purpose of philosophizing is the attainment of happiness.2 Both of these discussions cast philosophy as a fundamentally practical discipline, so that ethics appears to overshadow logic, metaphysics, and other comparatively abstract areas as a philosopher’s chief concern.
    [Show full text]
  • Confessions, by Augustine
    1 AUGUSTINE: CONFESSIONS Newly translated and edited by ALBERT C. OUTLER, Ph.D., D.D. Updated by Ted Hildebrandt, 2010 Gordon College, Wenham, MA Professor of Theology Perkins School of Theology Southern Methodist University, Dallas, Texas First published MCMLV; Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 55-5021 Printed in the United States of America Creator(s): Augustine, Saint, Bishop of Hippo (345-430) Outler, Albert C. (Translator and Editor) Print Basis: Philadelphia: Westminster Press [1955] (Library of Christian Classics, v. 7) Rights: Public Domain vid. www.ccel.org 2 TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction . 11 I. The Retractations, II, 6 (A.D. 427) . 22 Book One . 24 Chapter 1: . 24 Chapter II: . 25 Chapter III: . 25 Chapter IV: . 26 Chapter V: . 27 Chapter VI: . 28 Chapter VII: . 31 Chapter VIII: . 33 Chapter IX: . 34 Chapter X: . 36 Chapter XI: . 37 Chapter XII: . 39 Chapter XIII: . 39 Chapter XIV: . 41 Chapter XV: . 42 Chapter XVI: . 42 Chapter XVII: . 44 Chapter XVIII: . 45 Chapter XIX: . 47 Notes for Book I: . 48 Book Two . .. 50 Chapter 1: . 50 Chapter II: . 50 Chapter III: . 52 Chapter IV: . 55 Chapter V: . 56 Chapter VI: . 57 Chapter VII: . 59 Chapter VIII: . 60 Chapter IX: . .. 61 3 Chapter X: . 62 Notes for Book II: . 63 Book Three . .. 64 Chapter 1: . 64 Chapter II: . 65 Chapter III: . 67 Chapter IV: . 68 Chapter V: . 69 Chapter VI: . 70 Chapter VII: . 72 Chapter VIII: . 74 Chapter IX: . .. 76 Chapter X: . 77 Chapter XI: . 78 Chapter XII: . 80 Notes for Book III: . 81 Book Four . 83 Chapter 1: . 83 Chapter II: . 84 Chapter III: .
    [Show full text]
  • A Nietzschean Critique of Kant's Highest Good
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1988 A Nietzschean critique of Kant's highest good. Donald M. Schneier University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Schneier, Donald M., "A Nietzschean critique of Kant's highest good." (1988). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2029. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2029 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A NIETZSCHEAN CRITIQUE OF KANT’S HIGHEST GOOD A Dissertation Presented by DONALD M. SCHNEIER Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September I988 Philosophy Copywright by Donald M. Schneier I988 All Rights Reserved A NIETZSCHEAN CRITIQUE OF KANT’S HIGHEST GOOD A Disser'ta'fcion Presented by DONALD M. SCHNEIER Approved as to style and content by: Sara Lennox, Member Michael Jubien, Department Head Philosophy ACKNOV/LEDGEMENTS I would like to thank the members of my committee, es- pecially Bob Wolff, for their guidance, the AT for offering a constructive environment, my other friends for their change of pace, and Karen and my father for their steady support over this long haul. IV ABSTRACT A NIETZSCHEAN CRITIQUE OF KANT'S HIGHEST GOOD SEPTEMBER I988 DONALD M. SCHNEIER, B.A. , UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS M.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Aryeh Kosman, the Divine in Aristotle's Ethics
    THE DIVINE IN ARISTOTLE’S ETHICS Aryeh Kosman Haverford College [email protected] What role does the notion of the divine play in Aristotle’s account of a good life? This is not an obvious question; god appears relatively infrequently, for example, in the Nicomachean Ethics. But it might interest us, if only because of the perplexing appearance of the divine in Book 10 of that treatise, as that which appears to underwrite the choice of a contemplative life. The cognate question, what role does god play in Aristotle’s understanding of being, is obvious and is more understandable, given Metaphysics Lambda. That question yields a variety of answers. Some interpreters see the entire Metaphysics as directed toward the discussion of divine being in Lambda. Others see Lambda as an addendum to the central books of the Metaphysics, perhaps the residuum of a youthful view outgrown in the course of Aristotle’s maturation. In fact, Lambda’s discussion of god perfects the analysis of substance. It does so, however, not by revealing something about substance and being that the central books do not see, but by making clear that the principle articulated in those books is divine. I think that the same is true with Aristotle’s ethics: the divine is a principle that governs the discourse of the ethical treatises. Stewart put it nicely when he proposed to translate Aristotle’s doctrine “into the language of modern philosophy, and say that Aristotle makes ‘the Idea of God’ the ‘regulative principle’ in man’s life.”1 That neo-Kantian description (“the language of modern philosophy”) may now seem quaint, but it captures Aristotle’s view of god as a formal principle of our normative lives, and it does so without abandoning our commitment to read his ethics as naturalistic and human- centered.
    [Show full text]
  • NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Gabriel Richardson Lear
    Happy Lives and the Highest Good This page intentionally left blank Happy Lives and the Highest Good AN ESSAY ON ARISTOTLE'S NICOMACHEAN ETHICS Gabriel Richardson Lear PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRINCETON AND OXFORD Copyright © 2004 by Princeton University Press Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 3 Market Place, Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1SY All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Richardson Lear, Gabriel, 1971– Happy lives and the highest good : an essay on Aristotle’s Nicomachean ethics / Gabriel Richardson Lear. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-691-11466-8 (alk. paper) 1. Aristole, Nicomachean ethics. 2. Ethics, Ancient. I. Title. B430.L43 2004 171′.3—dc21 2003042899 British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available This book has been composed in Sabon and American Gothic Printed on acid-free paper. ∞ www.pupress.princeton.edu Printed in the United States of America 10987654321 FOR MY PARENTS Dale and Leslie Richardson This page intentionally left blank Contents ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ix CHAPTER ONE Introduction 1 CHAPTER TWO The Finality Criterion 8 1. Introduction 8 2. What It Is to Be an Aristotelian Telos 11 3. Teleology in the Nicomachean Ethics 15 4. Teleology, Desire, and Middle-Level Ends 31 5. The Puzzle in NE I.7 and Two Possible Solutions 37 6. Ackrill’s Inclusivist Solution 40 CHAPTER THREE The Self-Sufficiency of Happiness 47 1. Self-Sufficiency: Three Problems for a Monistic Reading of Eudaimonia 48 2. Self-Sufficiency as a Mark of Finality 51 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Morals of Metaphysics: Kant's Groundwork As Intellectual Paideia
    The Morals of Metaphysics: Kant’s Groundwork as Intellectual Paideia Author(s): Ian Hunter Source: Critical Inquiry, Vol. 28, No. 4 (Summer 2002), pp. 908-929 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/341237 . Accessed: 07/10/2015 20:38 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Critical Inquiry. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 23.235.32.0 on Wed, 7 Oct 2015 20:38:26 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions The Morals of Metaphysics: Kant’s Groundwork as Intellectual Paideia Ian Hunter In fact this satisfies a longing for the transcendent, because in so far as people believe they can see the ‘limits of human understanding’, they believe of course that they can see beyond these. Work in philosophy ...isreally more work on oneself. —Ludwig Wittgenstein, Culture andValue To approach philosophy as a way of working on the self means to begin not with the experience it clarifies and the subject it discovers, but with the acts of self-transformation it requires and the subjectivity it seeks tofashion.
    [Show full text]
  • The Politics of Transcendence: the Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism
    On Dubious Conceptions of Transcendence The Politics of Transcendence: The Pretentious Passivity of Platonic Idealism Claes G. Ryn The Catholic University of America Plato and Aristotle are still approached with deference by many political thinkers who have not abandoned the notion of moral universality. Some of them treat Plato as the ultimate philosophi- cal authority and even regard substantial criticisms of him as a sign of not really having understood him. Yet Plato and Aristotle are philosophers with human flaws, and their weaknesses, too, have influenced Western political philosophy and practice. It is possible to argue, specifically, that certain dubious tendencies in Greek philosophy, especially in Plato, have deeply affected the Western way of thinking about political morality, even among philosophers who disagree with them. Those same tendencies may help explain the strong prejudice against the notion of moral universality in modern political thought. One reason for revisit- ing Plato and Aristotle is to separate persuasive from question- able elements in their legacy and to remove obstacles to a recon- sideration of the issue of moral universality. This article and the one that follows challenge widely held assumptions. It may be appropriate to remind readers that HUMANITAS is always open to publishing scholarly responses to articles in its pages. 4 • Volume XII, No. 2, 1999 Claes G. Ryn Present-day admirers of the Greeks typically assume that criti- cisms of Plato and Aristotle must stem from nihilism or relativ- ism. Most of their critics, as well as academia in general, do in- deed reject the idea of a universal good for politics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hellenistic Ideal of the Good Or Virtuous Life
    East Tennessee State University Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University Undergraduate Honors Theses Student Works 12-2012 The elH lenistic Ideal of the Good or Virtuous Life. Bernadette Monaco East Tennessee State University Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.etsu.edu/honors Part of the Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Monaco, Bernadette, "The eH llenistic Ideal of the Good or Virtuous Life." (2012). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 158. https://dc.etsu.edu/honors/158 This Honors Thesis - Open Access is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Works at Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. East Tennessee State University The Honors College Philosophy Honors in Discipline Program History Honors in Discipline Program English Honors in Discipline Program The Hellenistic Ideal of the Good or Virtuous Life Bernadette Monaco December 2012 _______________________________ _______________________________ Dr. William Burgess Dr. Jeffrey Gold Faculty Advisor Philosophy Honors Coordinator _______________________________ _______________________________ Dr. Thomas Crofts Dr. Jessie Graves Faculty Advisor English Honors Coordinator _______________________________ Dr. Jeffrey Gold Faculty Advisor INTRODUCTION In studying the history of different civilizations it is easy to begin in medias res, in the middle of things, without taking stock of what came before and influenced a particular period and without acknowledging the influences it had on what came after. Both are vital to gaining an understanding of what was going on in the past.
    [Show full text]
  • Meeting Ethical Dilemmas in Health Care: Some Basic Criteria William E
    The Linacre Quarterly Volume 49 | Number 3 Article 10 August 1982 Meeting Ethical Dilemmas in Health Care: Some Basic Criteria William E. May Follow this and additional works at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq Recommended Citation May, William E. (1982) "Meeting Ethical Dilemmas in Health Care: Some Basic Criteria," The Linacre Quarterly: Vol. 49: No. 3, Article 10. Available at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq/vol49/iss3/10 Meeting Ethical Dilemmas in Health Care: Some Basic Criteria William E. May The author, who is the book review editor for Linacre Quarterly, is a faculty member in the department of theology at the Catholic Uni­ versity of America. In their efforts to care for the sick and the dying and to protect and improve the health of the public, those engaged in the medical, nurs­ ing, and allied professions have traditionally been greatly concerned with moral questions. Nurses and doctors certainly want to apply professional expertise to the treatment of diseases and cases, but in addition, they want to respond to the needs of their patient-persons. They are, moreover, not mechanical robots but sensitive, conscien­ tious, and responsible persons. As such, they want to do what is right and good and not merely what is professionally competent and tech­ nically efficient. The problem they - and all of us - face is to determine just what is really right and good. There are times when this determination is exceedingly difficult. An ethical or moral dilemma arises when there are apparently good reasons for different and, at times, contradictory courses of action, when one is perplexed about what one ought or ought not to do.
    [Show full text]