Lies, Bullshit, and Deception in Agent-Oriented Programming Languages

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lies, Bullshit, and Deception in Agent-Oriented Programming Languages Lies, Bullshit, and Deception in Agent-Oriented Programming Languages 2 1 Alison R. Panisson ,S, tefan Sarkadi Peter McBurney1, Simon Parsons1, and Rafael H. Bordini2 1 PUCRS, School of Technology, Porto Alegre, Brazil 2 King's College London, Department of Informatics, London, UK [email protected], [email protected] fstefan.sarkadi,peter.mcburney,[email protected] Abstract. It is reasonable to assume that in the next few decades, intel- ligent machines might become much more proficient at socialising. This implies that the AI community will face the challenges of identifying, understanding, and dealing with the different types of social behaviours these intelligent machines could exhibit. Given these potential challenges, we aim to model in this paper three of the most studied strategic social behaviours that could be adopted by autonomous and malicious software agents. These are dishonest behaviours such as lying, bullshitting, and deceiving that autonomous agents might exhibit by taking advantage of their own reasoning and communicative capabilities. In contrast to other studies on dishonest behaviours of autonomous agents, we use an agent- oriented programming language to model dishonest agents' attitudes and to simulate social interactions between agents. Through simulation, we are able to study and propose mechanisms to identify and later to deal with such dishonest behaviours in software agents. 1 Introduction Agent-Oriented Programming Languages (AOPL) and platforms to develop Multi-Agent Systems (MAS) provide suitable frameworks for modelling agent communication in AI. We can reasonably say that one of the main purposes of AI research is to represent as accurately as possible the way humans use in- formation to perform actions. Actions of humans are sometimes performed by applying dishonest forms of reasoning and behaviour such as lying, bullshitting, and deceiving. In this paper, we model lies, bullshit and deception in an AOPL named Ja- son [3], which is based on the BDI (Belief-Desire-Intention) architecture. Mod- elling these dishonest attitudes in MAS allows us to simulate agent interactions in order to understand how agents might behave if they have reasons to adopt these dishonest behaviours. Understanding such behaviours also allows us to identify and deal with such phenomena, as proposed by [7]. Even though the AI community has investigated computational models of lies [31], \bullshit", and deception [6], to the best of our knowledge, our work is one of the first attempts to model these types of agent attitudes in the practical context of an AOPL. AOPLs offer an attractive way of improving the research of dishonest agent behaviour through simulations of agent interactions with explicit representation of relevant mental states. Our study has two main contributions: (i) A comparative model of lies, bull- shit, and deception in an AOPL based on the BDI architecture, which allows us to define and simulate these dishonest behaviours. (ii) Making the respective model practical, by implementing an illustrative scenario to show how an agent called car dealer is able to deceive other agents called buyers in buying a car3. In this scenario, the car dealer also tells lies and bullshit in order to make the buyers believe a car is suitable for them, when in fact it is not. 2 Background 2.1 Lie, Bullshit, Deception We will start by describing what lying is from an agent-based perspective. We define lying similar to [6]. A lie is a false statement about something that is intended to make someone believe the opposite of what is actually true. Lying cannot be reduced to linguistic communication only. Liars give out information to others in various forms, such as social behaviour, facial expressions, physiological responses to questions, and manipulation of the environment [11, 5]. Definition 1 (Lying). The dishonest behaviour of an agent Agi to tell another agent Agj that : is the case, when in fact Agi knows that is the case. Bullshit is different from lying in the sense that it is not intended to make someone believe the opposite from the truth. A bullshiter agent will give an answer to a question in such a way that the one who asked the question is left with the impression that the bullshiter agent knows the true answer [12], when in fact it does not. Definition 2 (Bullshit). The dishonest behaviour of an agent Agi to tell an- other agent Agj that is the case, when in fact Agi does not know if is the case. Deception is more complex than bullshit or lying. We define deception as the intention of an agent (Deceiver) to make another agent (Interrogator) believe something is true that it (the Deceiver) thinks is false, with the scope of reaching an ulterior goal or desire. The complexity arises due to the fact that an agent requires Theory-of-Mind (henceforth ToM) to deceive [17]. ToM is not needed to tell a lie or to bullshit (although there are cases in which liars or bullshitters can make use of ToM). The Deceiver has to let the Interrogator reach the conclusion by itself. For example, if the Deceiver wants the Interrogator to believe that q is the case, instead of directly telling the Interrogator that q is the case, the Deceiver uses some knowledge that the Interrogator possesses, let's say p ! q, 3 The implementation of this work is available at https://tinyurl.com/ybrmkqg9. and tells the Interrogator that p is the case. Having told the Interrogator that p is the case, the Deceiver then knows that if the Interrogator is a rational agent that has the ability to apply Modus Ponens, then it will conclude that q is the case. Levine and McCornack call this interplay Pars Pro Toto (the information the Deceiver decides to feed the Interrogator) and Totum Ex Parte (the knowledge the Interrogator derives from the information sent by the Deceiver) [21]. One can argue that liars and bullshitters might have some types of moti- vations or goals. However, compared to deceivers, these goals do not contain ulterior motives. A liar, for example, can have the goal to speak falsely about a state of the world without taking into consideration the state of mind of the agent it speaks to. It can also be argued that a good liar would take into account its target's mind, although by definition a liar is constrained by one single strat- egy which is to speak falsely about a state of the world. A bullshitter can have the goal to make the agent it speaks to believe it (the bullshitter) is speaking the truth independently of the state of the world it is speaking about. Most of the times, however, bullshitters do not take into consideration the target's mental activity in order to deliver a bullshit. Definition 3 (Deception). The intended dishonest behaviour of an agent Agi to tell another agent Agj that is the case, when in fact Agi knows that : is the case, in order to make Agj conclude that ' given that Agi knows that Agj knows that ! ' and Agi also knows that Agj is rational. 2.2 Agent Oriented Programming Language Among the many AOPL and platforms, such as Jason, Jadex, Jack, AgentFac- tory, 2APL, GOAL, Golog, and MetateM, as discussed in [2], we chose the Jason platform [3] for our work. Jason extends the AgentSpeak language, an abstract logic-based AOPL introduced by Rao [27], which is one of the best-known lan- guages inspired by the BDI architecture. In Jason, the agents are equipped with a library of pre-compiled plans that have the following syntax: triggering_event : context <- body. where the triggering event represents the way agents react to events, for ex- ample, a new goal for the agent to pursue, or a new belief in case the plan is to be triggered by reaction to perceived changes in the world; the context has the preconditions for the plan to be deemed applicable for achieving that goal given the current circumstances, and the body is a sequence of actions and sub-goals to achieve the goal. Besides specifying agents with well-defined mental attitudes based on the BDI architecture, the Jason platform [3] has some other features that are partic- ularly interesting for our work, for example: strong negation, belief annotations, and (customisable) speech-act based communication. Strong negation helps the modelling of uncertainty, allowing the representation of things that the agent: (i) believes to be true, e.g., safe(car1); (ii) believes to be false, e.g., :safe(car1); (iii) is ignorant about, i.e., the agent has no information about whether the car is safe or not. Also, Jason automatically generates annotations for all the beliefs in the agents' belief base about the source from where the belief was obtained (which can be from sensing the environment, communication with other agents, or a mental note created by the agent itself). The annotation has the following format: safe(car1)[source(seller)], stating that the source of the belief that car1 is safe is the agent seller. The annotations in Jason can be easily ex- tended to include other meta-information, for example trust and time as used in [22, 25]. Another interesting feature of Jason is the communication between agents, which is done through a predefined (internal) action. There are a num- ber of performatives allowing rich communication between agents in Jason, as explained in detail in [3]. Further, new performatives can be easily defined (or redefined) in order to give special meaning to them4. 3 Running Example To show the difference between the agents' attitudes of telling a lie, telling bull- shit and deceiving, we will present an approach to model these three agent attitudes in an agent-oriented programming language using a running example of a car dealer scenario5, inspired by [20, 23, 31].
Recommended publications
  • Lying and Asserting
    Lying and Asserting Andreas Stokke — penultimate version, published in Journal of Philosophy, CX(1), 2013, 33–60 — Abstract The paper argues that the correct definition of lying is that to lie is to assert some- thing one believes to be false, where assertion is understood in terms of the notion of the common ground of a conversation. It is shown that this definition makes the right pre- dictions for a number of cases involving irony, joking, and false implicature. In addition, the proposed account does not assume that intending to deceive is a necessary condition on lying, and hence counts so-called bald-faced lies as lies. 1 Introduction This paper argues for a definition of lying. The definition is that you lie when you assert something you believe to be false. This definition is not new, and many philosophers have held it. Yet these proposals differ from each other in relying on different views of assertion. I argue that the account of assertion needed to define lying is the one familiar from the work of Stalnaker (1978), (1998), (2002) according to which to assert that p is to propose that p become common ground. So my definition of lying is that you lie when you say something you believe to be false and thereby propose that it become common ground. Traditionally, many philosophers – e.g., Augustine (1952 [395]b), Bok (1978), Williams (2002), Frankfurt (2005 [1986]) – have defined lying as saying what you believe to be false with the intent to deceive. But as pointed out by Carson (2006), Sorensen (2007), Fallis (2009), and others, this definition fails to do justice to the phenomenon of what Sorensen calls bald- faced lies.
    [Show full text]
  • Memetics of Deception: Spreading Local Meme Hoaxes During COVID-19 1St Year
    future internet Article Memetics of Deception: Spreading Local Meme Hoaxes during COVID-19 1st Year Raúl Rodríguez-Ferrándiz 1,* , Cande Sánchez-Olmos 1,* , Tatiana Hidalgo-Marí 1 and Estela Saquete-Boro 2 1 Department of Communication and Social Psychology, University of Alicante, 03690 Alicante, Spain; [email protected] 2 Department of Software and Computing Systems, University of Alicante, 03690 Alicante, Spain; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] (R.R.-F.); [email protected] (C.S.-O.) Abstract: The central thesis of this paper is that memetic practices can be crucial to understanding deception at present when hoaxes have increased globally due to COVID-19. Therefore, we employ existing memetic theory to describe the qualities and characteristics of meme hoaxes in terms of the way they are replicated by altering some aspects of the original, and then shared on social media platforms in order to connect global and local issues. Criteria for selecting the sample were hoaxes retrieved from and related to the local territory in the province of Alicante (Spain) during the first year of the pandemic (n = 35). Once typology, hoax topics and their memetic qualities were identified, we analysed their characteristics according to form in terms of Shifman (2014) and, secondly, their content and stance concordances both within and outside our sample (Spain and abroad). The results show, firstly, that hoaxes are mainly disinformation and they are related to the pandemic. Secondly, despite the notion that local hoaxes are linked to local circumstances that are difficult to extrapolate, our conclusions demonstrate their extraordinary memetic and “glocal” capacity: they rapidly adapt Citation: Rodríguez-Ferrándiz, R.; other hoaxes from other places to local areas, very often supplanting reliable sources, and thereby Sánchez-Olmos, C.; Hidalgo-Marí, T.; demonstrating consistency and opportunism.
    [Show full text]
  • Assertion and Hearsay
    Volume 125 Issue 2 Winter 2021 Assertion and Hearsay Richard Lloret Follow this and additional works at: https://ideas.dickinsonlaw.psu.edu/dlr Part of the Civil Law Commons, Civil Procedure Commons, Common Law Commons, Courts Commons, Criminal Law Commons, Criminal Procedure Commons, Evidence Commons, Judges Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, Legal Education Commons, Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility Commons, Legal Profession Commons, Legal Writing and Research Commons, Litigation Commons, State and Local Government Law Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation Richard Lloret, Assertion and Hearsay, 125 DICK. L. REV. 347 (2021). Available at: https://ideas.dickinsonlaw.psu.edu/dlr/vol125/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews at Dickinson Law IDEAS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dickinson Law Review by an authorized editor of Dickinson Law IDEAS. For more information, please contact [email protected]. \\jciprod01\productn\D\DIK\125-2\DIK202.txt unknown Seq: 1 10-FEB-21 13:14 Assertion and Hearsay Richard A. Lloret* ABSTRACT This article explores the characteristics and functions of as- sertion and considers how the term influences the definition of hearsay under Federal Rule of Evidence 801. Rule 801(a) de- fines hearsay by limiting it to words and conduct intended as an assertion, but the rule does not define the term assertion. Courts and legal scholars have focused relatively little attention on the nature and definition of assertion. That is unfortunate, because assertion is a robust concept that has been the subject of intense philosophic study over recent decades.
    [Show full text]
  • Information Warfare, International Law, and the Changing Battlefield
    ARTICLE INFORMATION WARFARE, INTERNATIONAL LAW, AND THE CHANGING BATTLEFIELD Dr. Waseem Ahmad Qureshi* ABSTRACT The advancement of technology in the contemporary era has facilitated the emergence of information warfare, which includes the deployment of information as a weapon against an adversary. This is done using a numBer of tactics such as the use of media and social media to spread propaganda and disinformation against an adversary as well as the adoption of software hacking techniques to spread viruses and malware into the strategically important computer systems of an adversary either to steal confidential data or to damage the adversary’s security system. Due to the intangible nature of the damage caused By the information warfare operations, it Becomes challenging for international law to regulate the information warfare operations. The unregulated nature of information operations allows information warfare to Be used effectively By states and nonstate actors to gain advantage over their adversaries. Information warfare also enhances the lethality of hyBrid warfare. Therefore, it is the need of the hour to arrange a new convention or devise a new set of rules to regulate the sphere of information warfare to avert the potential damage that it can cause to international peace and security. ABSTRACT ................................................................................................. 901 I. INTRODUCTION ......................................................................... 903 II. WHAT IS INFORMATION WARFARE? .............................
    [Show full text]
  • Lies, Bullshit and Fake News: Some Epistemological Concerns
    Postdigital Science and Education https://doi.org/10.1007/s42438-018-0025-4 COMMENTARIES Open Access Lies, Bullshit and Fake News: Some Epistemological Concerns Alison MacKenzie1 & Ibrar Bhatt1 # The Author(s) 2018 What is the difference between a lie, bullshit, and a fake news story? And is it defensible to lie, bullshit, or spread fake stories? The answers are, unsurprisingly, complex, often defy simple affirmative or negative answers, and are often context dependent. For present purposes, however, a lie is a statement that the liar knows or believes to be false, stated with the express intention of deceiving or misleading the receiver for some advantageous gain on the part of the liar. On the standard definition of a lie, the liar’s chief accomplishment is deception—and it can be artful: When we undertake to deceive others intentionally, we communicate messages meant to mislead them, meant to make them believe what we ourselves do not believe. We can do so through gesture, through disguise, by means of action or inaction, even through silence. (Bok 1999[1978]: 13) The standard definition has, in the Western philosophical tradition, antecedents stretching all the way back to St Augustine. However, the classic definition may be too restrictive as not all lies are stated with the intention to deceive. Any number of statements can mislead through misapprehension, incomprehension, poor understand- ing of, or partial access to the facts. To mislead, further, is not the same as lying, or as serious, and we can rely less on a liar than we can on a person who misleads.
    [Show full text]
  • Many People Are Saying…”: Applying the Lessons of Naïve Skepticism to the Fight Against Fake News and Other “Total Bullshit”1
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers “Many people are saying…”: Applying the lessons of naïve skepticism to the fight against fake news and other “total bullshit”1 Jake Wright, Ph.D. [email protected] Abstract: ‘Fake news’ has become an increasingly common refrain in public discourse. The term itself has several uses, at least one of which constitutes Frankfurtian bullshit. After examining what sorts of fake news appeals do and do not count as bullshit, I discuss strategies for overcoming our openness to such bullshit. I do so by drawing a parallel between openness to bullshit and naïve skepticism—one’s willingness to reject the concept of truth on unsupported or ill- considered grounds—and suggest that this parallel indicates three principles for how we ought to combat our openness to fake news and other bullshit. First, the root causes of bullshit openness are not monolithic; we should adopt anti-bullshit strategies in recognition of this fact. Second, our efforts to overcome bullshit openness should be collaborative efforts to create an environment that allows for sustained interrogation of our bullshit openness, rather than a confrontational provision of contrary evidence, despite the fact that such strategies are more time- intensive. Third, social media is unlikely to be a fertile ground on which we will make meaningful progress in the fight against bullshit because of the inherent nature of social media platforms as spaces for short, declarative, confrontational claims. Keywords: fake news, bullshit, naïve skepticism, social media, epistemology of ignorance 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Mass Media and the Transformation of American Politics Kristine A
    Marquette Law Review Volume 77 | Issue 2 Article 7 Mass Media and the Transformation of American Politics Kristine A. Oswald Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr Part of the Law Commons Repository Citation Kristine A. Oswald, Mass Media and the Transformation of American Politics, 77 Marq. L. Rev. 385 (2009). Available at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr/vol77/iss2/7 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Marquette Law Review by an authorized administrator of Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MASS MEDIA AND THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN POLITICS I. INTRODUCTION The importance of the mass media1 in today's society cannot be over- estimated. Especially in the arena of policy-making, the media's influ- ence has helped shape the development of American government. To more fully understand the political decision-making process in this coun- try it is necessary to understand the media's role in the performance of political officials and institutions. The significance of the media's influ- ence was expressed by Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn: "The Press has become the greatest power within Western countries, more powerful than the legislature, the executive, and the judiciary. One would then like to ask: '2 By what law has it been elected and to whom is it responsible?" The importance of the media's power and influence can only be fully appreciated through a complete understanding of who or what the media are.
    [Show full text]
  • V. 2.1 Gaslighting Citizens Eric Beerbohm and Ryan Davis1
    v. 2.1 Gaslighting Citizens Eric Beerbohm and Ryan Davis1 [L]eaders...have argued that if their followers or subjects are not strong enough to stick to the resolution themselves, they—the leaders—ought to help them avoid contact with the misleading evidence. For this reason, they have urged or compelled people not to read certain books, writings, and the like. But many people need no compulsion. They avoid reading things, and so on. — Saul Kripke, “On Two Paradoxes of Knowledge” Politics invariably involves disagreement—some of it, unreasonable. If deep enough and fundamental enough, disagreement might be taken as a sign not only that one of the opposing disputants must be incorrect, but that someone may be somehow failing to respond to the available evidence in a minimally rational way. So begins a much sharper allegation: that one’s opponent is not just mistaken, but crazy. In a partisan world, the rhetorical force of this accusation is easily weaponized. If one’s opponents lack basic epistemic capacities, one does them no wrong by ignoring them, and encouraging others to ignore them as well. “Gaslighting”—or attempting to cause people to doubt their own attitudes or capacities—has quickly gained popularity as an explicitly political charge.2 Antagonists on the right and left both mutually accuse each other of gaslighting. They define the term similarly, so the disagreement looks substantive.3 But the opposing outlooks may share little besides the concept. This essay aims to understand gaslighting as a political phenomenon. It proceeds in six parts. First, we will sketch the concept of gaslighting as it has been developed in the philosophical literature.
    [Show full text]
  • On Bullshit in Cultural Policy Practice and Research: Notes from the British
    Original citation: Belfiore, Eleonora, 1975-. (2009) On bullshit in cultural policy practice and research : notes from the British case. International Journal of Cultural Policy, Vol.15 (No.3). pp. 343-359. ISSN 1028-6632 Permanent WRAP url: http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/41199/ Copyright and reuse: The Warwick Research Archive Portal (WRAP) makes the work of researchers of the University of Warwick available open access under the following conditions. Copyright © and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable the material made available in WRAP has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full items can be used for personal research or study, educational, or not-for- profit purposes without prior permission or charge. Provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. Publisher’s statement: This article is available under License to Publish, based upon the Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) license. Under this license others may download your works and share them with others as long as they credit you, but they can’t change them in any way or use them commercially. The License to Publish also allows for text- and data-mining of your works. A note on versions: The version presented in WRAP is the published version or, version of record, and may be cited as it appears here.
    [Show full text]
  • S:\FULLCO~1\HEARIN~1\Committee Print 2018\Henry\Jan. 9 Report
    Embargoed for Media Publication / Coverage until 6:00AM EST Wednesday, January 10. 1 115TH CONGRESS " ! S. PRT. 2d Session COMMITTEE PRINT 115–21 PUTIN’S ASYMMETRIC ASSAULT ON DEMOCRACY IN RUSSIA AND EUROPE: IMPLICATIONS FOR U.S. NATIONAL SECURITY A MINORITY STAFF REPORT PREPARED FOR THE USE OF THE COMMITTEE ON FOREIGN RELATIONS UNITED STATES SENATE ONE HUNDRED FIFTEENTH CONGRESS SECOND SESSION JANUARY 10, 2018 Printed for the use of the Committee on Foreign Relations Available via World Wide Web: http://www.gpoaccess.gov/congress/index.html U.S. GOVERNMENT PUBLISHING OFFICE 28–110 PDF WASHINGTON : 2018 For sale by the Superintendent of Documents, U.S. Government Publishing Office Internet: bookstore.gpo.gov Phone: toll free (866) 512–1800; DC area (202) 512–1800 Fax: (202) 512–2104 Mail: Stop IDCC, Washington, DC 20402–0001 VerDate Mar 15 2010 04:06 Jan 09, 2018 Jkt 000000 PO 00000 Frm 00001 Fmt 5012 Sfmt 5012 S:\FULL COMMITTEE\HEARING FILES\COMMITTEE PRINT 2018\HENRY\JAN. 9 REPORT FOREI-42327 with DISTILLER seneagle Embargoed for Media Publication / Coverage until 6:00AM EST Wednesday, January 10. COMMITTEE ON FOREIGN RELATIONS BOB CORKER, Tennessee, Chairman JAMES E. RISCH, Idaho BENJAMIN L. CARDIN, Maryland MARCO RUBIO, Florida ROBERT MENENDEZ, New Jersey RON JOHNSON, Wisconsin JEANNE SHAHEEN, New Hampshire JEFF FLAKE, Arizona CHRISTOPHER A. COONS, Delaware CORY GARDNER, Colorado TOM UDALL, New Mexico TODD YOUNG, Indiana CHRISTOPHER MURPHY, Connecticut JOHN BARRASSO, Wyoming TIM KAINE, Virginia JOHNNY ISAKSON, Georgia EDWARD J. MARKEY, Massachusetts ROB PORTMAN, Ohio JEFF MERKLEY, Oregon RAND PAUL, Kentucky CORY A. BOOKER, New Jersey TODD WOMACK, Staff Director JESSICA LEWIS, Democratic Staff Director JOHN DUTTON, Chief Clerk (II) VerDate Mar 15 2010 04:06 Jan 09, 2018 Jkt 000000 PO 00000 Frm 00002 Fmt 5904 Sfmt 5904 S:\FULL COMMITTEE\HEARING FILES\COMMITTEE PRINT 2018\HENRY\JAN.
    [Show full text]
  • Read Book the Daily Show and Philosophy : Moments of ZEN In
    THE DAILY SHOW AND PHILOSOPHY : MOMENTS OF ZEN IN THE ART OF FAKE NEWS PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Jason Holt | 280 pages | 11 Dec 2007 | John Wiley and Sons Ltd | 9781405163149 | English | Chicester, United Kingdom The Daily Show and Philosophy : Moments of ZEN in the Art of Fake News PDF Book It also describes a type of Buddhism in which meditation is used to stay present and non-judgmental. Roy Wood, Jr. When you are sitting in a secluded spot, close your eyes. Public Excess was a segment hosted by correspondent Rich Brown. This organization of organization does not operate at the level of actual action or plain intimidation but on that of anxiety and inadequacy; not by confinement or demanding obedience to the rules and being afraid of their violation, but by setting expectations, moods, opinion climates, standards of communication and cooperation. Arby's also made a 'Goodbye Jon Stewart' video for Stewart's last show, which was a small compilation of all the jokes that Stewart's made about them. Back in Black with Lewis Black is a popular segment on the show, where "America's foremost commentator on everything" and comedian Lewis Black catches the stories that, according to his introduction, "fall through the cracks", and comments on them in a humorous rant. The original host of the segment was Michael Blieden until Then, when the basis for such a comparison was developed, I began to realize how firmly rooted the show is in the grand philosophical tradition. Sign in Create an account. To keep careful tabs on the time without an alarm, grab a mala string of beads and use it to count the breaths and stay focused.
    [Show full text]
  • Running Head: BULLSHIT MAKES the ART GROW PROFOUNDER
    Judgment and Decision Making, Vol. 14, No. 6, November 2019, pp. 658–670 Bullshit makes the art grow profounder Martin Harry Turpin∗ Alexander C. Walker† Mane Kara-Yakoubian† Nina N. Gabert† Jonathan A. Fugelsang† Jennifer A. Stolz† Abstract Across four studies participants (N = 818) rated the profoundness of abstract art images accompanied with varying categories of titles, including: pseudo-profound bullshit titles (e.g., The Deaf Echo), mundane titles (e.g., Canvas 8), and no titles. Randomly generated pseudo-profound bullshit titles increased the perceived profoundness of computer-generated abstract art, compared to when no titles were present (Study 1). Mundane titles did not enhance the perception of profoundness, indicating that pseudo-profound bullshit titles specifically (as opposed to titles in general) enhance the perceived profoundness of abstract art (Study 2). Furthermore, these effects generalize to artist-created abstract art (Study 3). Finally, we report a large correlation between profoundness ratings for pseudo-profound bullshit and “International Art English” statements (Study 4), a mode and style of communication commonly employed by artists to discuss their work. This correlation suggests that these two independently developed communicative modes share underlying cognitive mechanisms in their interpretations. We discuss the potential for these results to be integrated into a larger, new theoretical framework of bullshit as a low-cost strategy for gaining advantages in prestige awarding domains. Keywords: pseudo-profound bullshit, impression management, abstract art, meaning, social navigation 1 Introduction has been shown to be positively associated with a liking of modern art (Feist & Brady, 2004). Despite these individual An experience that may be familiar to visitors of modern differences, in general, people find a lack of meaning aver- art museums is finding oneself before a sprawling arrange- sive.
    [Show full text]