Divisibility of Magnitude in De Generatione Et Corruptione I.2 GC I

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Divisibility of Magnitude in De Generatione Et Corruptione I.2 GC I Divisibility of Magnitude in De Generatione et Corruptione I.2 GC I.2 is principally dedicated to the presentation and subsequent refutation of an argument alleging that magnitude is indivisible. Offered at 316a14-316b18, the argument has the form of a reductio ad absurdum and appears to prove that the divisibility thesis implies absurd consequences. The reductio is refuted later in the chapter (317a2-12), with the refutation becoming a vehicle for a proper characterization of what it is for magnitude to be divisible, or so I ague. ‘Magnitude’ here refers both to bodily and mathematical magnitude, by which it is meant lines, planes and geometrical solids. Since Philoponus, the reductio is thought to be an argument by Democritus and Aristotle’s aim in this chapter to refute the Democritean ontology.1 Commentators insist on attributing it to Democritus, even though they acknowledge that it relies heavily on Aristotelian doctrine.2 Skeptical voices have been raised, but they have been few and unconvincing,3 the chief reason being that they fail to present Aristotle with an alternative motivation for rehearsing and refuting the argument. Two aporiai form the backbone of the chapter. The first, at 315b20-3, warns of a threat to the divisibility thesis and outlines the aim of the chapter as being to remove it. The second, at 316b19-27, explains this threat. Correctly understood, the first aporia also lays it down that the atomist ontology is already refuted, with no prospect of being resurrected. It is unlikely to be the threat of which that aporia warns. Still a further refutation of atomism would not therefore serve the chapter’s aims. Moreover, the chapter’s use of the terms ‘σῶµα’ and ‘µέγεθος’ casts further doubt on the claim that the reductio is by Democritus. Fimally, the argument is all too obviously flawed to have been used by Democritus, or anyone for that matter, in support of atomism. To the extent that GC I.2 has been used as evidence for 1See Joachim (1922), 76; Williams (1982); Luria (1933), 129-133; 23 ff.; Schramm (1962), 245-264; Miller (1982), 87-111; Barnes (1982); 356 ff.; Makin (1993), 49-62; Furley (1967), 85-87. Also Sedley (2004): “Why this elaborately contrived refutation of Democritean atomism?” (p. 82). 2 Rosen & Malink (2012) correctly point out that the reductio is based on a view Aristotle says was “discovered by himself, as the result of substantial theoretical work on his part”. But neither can resist the temptation of attributing the argument to Democritus: the argument says Rosen & Malink “can be regarded as a combination of Democritean and Aristotelian elements” (p. 31). They do not explain what the Democritean element is, though one may assume they take it to be the argument’s apparent support for atomism. 3 Cherniss (1935), 113, remarks that the reductio is offered as a reasoning that makes people think there are atomic bodies. Mau (1954), 25-6, is also skeptical that it is by Democritus. Democritean doctrine and in particular the view that Democritus rejected mathematical divisibility,4 the results of this part of the paper will have a bearing on that question too. The reductio could be an argument by atomist sympathizers of Speusippean or Xenocratean persuasion and familiar with Aristotelian doctrine. It could even be by Aristotle himself. Be that as it may, I worry that focusing on it as Democritean completely misses the key issue with which Aristotle is here most anxious to grapple. As the second of the two aporiai mentioned above makes clear, this is to remove a threat to the grounds for the position of Physics III.6 that the infinite is an attribute of magnitude (206b5-9). Prima facie, the difficulty is a reductio argument alleging that the proposed grounding is incoherent, thereby threatening the divisibility thesis. But this is a ploy Aristotle uses in order to expose a view on point assumed by the reductio that conflicts with his conception of magnitude and sharply to dissociate it from his own, which he then articulates. On that basis, he is able coherently to ground the position of Physics III.6 that the infinite is an attribute of magnitude. I In the first chapter of the GC Aristotle outlines important goals for this work. Chief among them is to offer accounts of unqualified generation and corruption (περὶ γενέσεως καὶ φθορᾶς τῆς ἁπλῆς) doing justice to the intuition that they are radically different form each other and, no less importantly, each is likewise different from alteration (ἀλλοίωσιν). Properly being able to account for all three and for bringing out their differences, he considers an adequacy test for any physical theory (314b12-17).5 Generation and corruption are discussed in chapter I.3 and alteration in I.4, which naturally raises this question; why does the discussion of the items on the agenda broadcasted in the first chapter not begin here? What is the important issue with which must GC I.2 must deal before the announced program can be set under way? GC I.2 begins by recalling the extended criticisms GC I.1 levels against previous thinkers for failing to account properly for 4‘Mathematical divisibility’ refers to the view that what Aristotle calls intelligible magnitude or intelligible body, namely the lines, planes and solids studied by geometers are divisible. If Democritus denies that atoms considered as mathematical solids are divisible or that parts can be marked in an atom, he is likely to be committed to mathematical indivisibility. 5 So in GC I.1 Aristotle offers detailed criticisms of previous thinkers for failing to account for generation, corruption and alteration. Some, he says, claim that everything is really one (ἕν τι τὸ πᾶν), and consequently think of generation and corruption as being merely alteration; others, as for instance Anaxagoras (314a13-6) and Empedocles (314b6-8) fail to distinguish between generation, corruption and alteration even though they postulate the existence of more than one elements. 2 generation, corruption and alteration. But unlike GC I.1, it singles out one thinker for praise. Democritus is applauded for offering accounts of generation and corruption and appreciating the difference between them as wells as the difference of each from alteration. On Democritus’ account, as Aristotle reports it, generation happens by association (σύγκρισις) and corruption by dissociation (διάκρισις) (315b6-9). There is generation when atoms associate to form stable configurations and corruption when they dissociate, with the configurations they previously formed being destroyed. In alteration, we have merely a change of position of the atoms comprising a particular configuration they jointly form, one that does not, however, bring about the destruction of that configuration.6 Here we have, one might think, the motivation for postponing the account of generation and corruption to the next chapter. Democritus offers competing accounts of generation, corruption and alteration. If atomism is left standing, Aristotle’s forthcoming account will have a competitor. Consequently, one might think, this chapter is dedicated to refuting Democritean and Leucippean atomism7 in order for Aristotle’s account to get the spoils. But this interpretation faces an obstacle. Nowhere in this chapter does Aristotle signal that he needs to refute atomism to serve his purpose. On the contrary, he signals that he has refuted atomism already. He says early on and long before the reductio that the Democritean ontology defies reason (πολλὴν ἔχει ἀλογίαν; 315b33). Also, the first horn of the aporia at 315b20-3, states that if generation happens by association, impossible consequences follow. These impossible consequences are certain to include the atomist ontology. Generation as association is the account of the Atomists, and of no other as far as we know. In context, then, generation as association implies atomism, and so what Aristotle says here, if only by implication, is that he has already shown atomism to be impossible. And he unequivocally confirms that he is already done with proving that when he says a little later in the chapter, at 316b16-8, that he has proved in other works that atomism is impossible.8 GC I.2 presupposes, 6 Democritus would presumably account for natural growth (αὔξησις) and diminution (φθίσις) by means of a similar mechanism he accounts for generation and corruption. A configuration grows bigger when additional atoms join in, or smaller when some of the atoms forming it depart, while the configuration itself persists, becoming larger or smaller respectively. 7 With ‘atomism’ I refer to the views of Democritean and Leucippean and by ‘Atomists’ to Democritus and Leucippus. I assume there is no difference between the views of the two men. So, using the name of only one of them, when I do, is no indication that I’m referring to his view as opposed to those of the other. 8Οὐ µὴν ἀλλὰ καὶ ταῦτα θεµένοις οὐχ ἧττον συµβαίνει ἀδύνατα. Ἔσκεπται δὲ περὶ αὐτῶν ἐν ἑτέροις. See for instance Phys. VI and more importantly De Caelo 303a3 ff. One of the previous work referred to here could well be the De Caelo, of which the Generatione et Corruptione, is presumably the sequel. If so, there is still less of a reason to engage anew in a recently undertaken task. 3 and says in so many words in several passages, that atomism is both unworkable and already refuted, which makes it odd that it should be dedicated to yet another refutation. We will be better able to understand the issue to be addressed in this chapter, if we return to the aporia at 315b20-3. We recall the first horn broadcasting impossible consequences to follow if generation is association, and identified the ontology on which this account rests as such a consequence.
Recommended publications
  • 15 Famous Greek Mathematicians and Their Contributions 1. Euclid
    15 Famous Greek Mathematicians and Their Contributions 1. Euclid He was also known as Euclid of Alexandria and referred as the father of geometry deduced the Euclidean geometry. The name has it all, which in Greek means “renowned, glorious”. He worked his entire life in the field of mathematics and made revolutionary contributions to geometry. 2. Pythagoras The famous ‘Pythagoras theorem’, yes the same one we have struggled through in our childhood during our challenging math classes. This genius achieved in his contributions in mathematics and become the father of the theorem of Pythagoras. Born is Samos, Greece and fled off to Egypt and maybe India. This great mathematician is most prominently known for, what else but, for his Pythagoras theorem. 3. Archimedes Archimedes is yet another great talent from the land of the Greek. He thrived for gaining knowledge in mathematical education and made various contributions. He is best known for antiquity and the invention of compound pulleys and screw pump. 4. Thales of Miletus He was the first individual to whom a mathematical discovery was attributed. He’s best known for his work in calculating the heights of pyramids and the distance of the ships from the shore using geometry. 5. Aristotle Aristotle had a diverse knowledge over various areas including mathematics, geology, physics, metaphysics, biology, medicine and psychology. He was a pupil of Plato therefore it’s not a surprise that he had a vast knowledge and made contributions towards Platonism. Tutored Alexander the Great and established a library which aided in the production of hundreds of books.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Two Democritus and the Different Limits to Divisibility
    CHAPTER TWO DEMOCRITUS AND THE DIFFERENT LIMITS TO DIVISIBILITY § 0. Introduction In the previous chapter I tried to give an extensive analysis of the reasoning in and behind the first arguments in the history of philosophy in which problems of continuity and infinite divisibility emerged. The impact of these arguments must have been enormous. Designed to show that rationally speaking one was better off with an Eleatic universe without plurality and without motion, Zeno’s paradoxes were a challenge to everyone who wanted to salvage at least those two basic features of the world of common sense. On the other hand, sceptics, for whatever reason weary of common sense, could employ Zeno-style arguments to keep up the pressure. The most notable representative of the latter group is Gorgias, who in his book On not-being or On nature referred to ‘Zeno’s argument’, presumably in a demonstration that what is without body and does not have parts, is not. It is possible that this followed an earlier argument of his that whatever is one, must be without body.1 We recognize here what Aristotle calls Zeno’s principle, that what does not have bulk or size, is not. Also in the following we meet familiar Zenonian themes: Further, if it moves and shifts [as] one, what is, is divided, not being continuous, and there [it is] not something. Hence, if it moves everywhere, it is divided everywhere. But if that is the case, then everywhere it is not. For it is there deprived of being, he says, where it is divided, instead of ‘void’ using ‘being divided’.2 Gorgias is talking here about the situation that there is motion within what is.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonist Philosopher Hypatia of Alexandria in Amenabar’S Film Agorá
    A STUDY OF THE RECEPTION OF THE LIFE AND DEATH OF THE NEO- PLATONIST PHILOSOPHER HYPATIA OF ALEXANDRIA IN AMENABAR’S FILM AGORÁ GILLIAN van der HEIJDEN Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirement for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS In the Faculty of Humanities School of Religion, Philosophy and Classics at the UNIVERSITY OF KWAZULU-NATAL, DURBAN SUPERVISOR: PROFESSOR J.L. HILTON MARCH 2016 DECLARATION I, Gillian van der Heijden, declare that: The research reported in this dissertation, except where otherwise indicated, is my original research; This dissertation has not been submitted for any degree or examination at any other university; This dissertation does not contain other persons’ data, pictures, graphs or other information, unless specifically acknowledged as being sourced from other persons; The dissertation does not contain other persons’ writing, unless specifically acknowledged as being sourced from other researchers. Where other written sources have been quoted, then: a) their words have been re-written but the general information attributed to them has been referenced; b) where their exact words have been used, their writing has been paragraphed and referenced; c) This dissertation/thesis does not contain text, graphics or tables copied and pasted from the Internet, unless specifically acknowledged, and the source being detailed in the dissertation/thesis and in the References sections. Signed: Gillian van der Heijden (Student Number 209541374) Professor J. L. Hilton ii ABSTRACT The film Agorá is better appreciated through a little knowledge of the rise of Christianity and its opposition to Paganism which professed ethical principles inherited from Greek mythology and acknowledged, seasonal rituals and wealth in land and livestock.
    [Show full text]
  • Democritus (460-370 BC) on Embryology, Anatomy and Pediatrics: the Unknown Aspects of the Greek Atomic Scientist
    IJAE Vol. 117, n. 3: 199-204, 2012 ITALIAN JOURNAL OF ANATOMY AND EMBRYOLOGY Research Article: History Of Anatomy and Embryology Democritus (460-370 BC) on Embryology, Anatomy and Pediatrics: the unknown aspects of the Greek atomic scientist Gregory Tsoucalas, Marianna Karamanou*, Antonis A. Kousoulis, George Androutsos History of Medicine Department, Medical School, University of Athens, Greece Submitted January 29, 2012; accepted June 17, 2012 Abstract Democritus was born in Abdera, Thrace, in the 5th century BC. He travelled to the East while being the student of famous philosophers. His philosophical ideas and the establishment of particles, “the atoms”, gave him a leading position in world history. However, his medical knowledge was vast especially in the field of pediatric pharmacology. Numerous are also the reports of his passion for anatomy. Democritus’ views regarding the issue of Human Nature and Anatomy are depicted in a letter he sent to Hippocrates of Kos. He died in old age, possi- bly of infection after having totally neglected his personal hygiene. Keywords Democritus; philosophy; atom; embryology; pediatrics; anatomy. Note: for ancient authors, citations in the text do not include the year of publication of the original writings; the reference list reports the year of publication of the critical edition which was used for this study. Introductory note and brief biography Democritus of Igisistratos or Athinocratos or Damasippos (Precope, 1961; Marcov- ich, 1999) was born in Abdera, Thrace, Greece, around the 80th Olympic Games, 460- 457 BC (Herodotus; Strabo) or earlier (Anaksagoras Klazomenios). He visited Egypt where, in the sanctuary of Memphis, he was initiated to Jewish spirituality by a sage woman named Maria.
    [Show full text]
  • The Combinatorics of Stoic Conjunction: Hipparchus Refuted, Chrysippus Vindicated
    Created on 10 January 2011 at 16.23 hours THECOMBINATORICSOFSTOIC CONJUNCTION:HIPPARCHUS REFUTED,CHRYSIPPUSVINDICATED SUSANNEBOBZIEN Dieser Aufsatz ist dem Andenken von Michael Frede gewid- met — einem wahren Philosophen und wahren Freund. Ohne sein grundlegendes Werk über die stoische Logik und ihre Entwicklung in der Antike wäre dieser Aufsatz nicht möglich. Introduction [Chrysippus] says that the number of conjunctions [constructible] from ten assertibles exceeds one million . Yet many mathematicians have refuted Chrysippus; among them is Hipparchus, who has demonstrated that his error in the calculation is huge, since the affirmative produces , con- joined assertibles, and the negative ,. (Plut. Stoic. repugn. –) Chrysippus says that the number of conjunctions [constructible] from only ten assertibles exceeds one million. However, Hipparchus refuted this, demonstrating that the affirmative encompasses , conjoined assert- ibles and the negative ,. (Plut. Quaest. conv. – ) Chrysippus, third head of the Stoa and one of the two greatest lo- gicians in antiquity, made his statement about the number of con- junctions in the third century . Hipparchus, famous astronomer and writer of a work in which he discussed combinatorics, flour- ished in the second half of the second century . The claims of © Susanne Bobzien This paper has profited greatly from detailed written comments by Fabio Acerbi and István Bodnár. An early version was presented at the Seminar ‘Hellenistic Science and Scholarship’ at the Radcliffe Institute, Harvard, in May , and I am grateful to the participants for their helpful remarks, in particular to Alexander Jones and the late Ian Mueller. Thanks go also to my brother Matthias Bobzien for first bringing the tree-structure method to my attention.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reading of Porphyry's on Abstinence From
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Classics by Alexander Press 2020 © Copyright by Alexander Press 2020 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings by Alexander Press Doctor of Philosophy in Classics University of California, Los Angeles, 2020 Professor David Blank, Chair Abstract: Presenting a range of arguments against meat-eating, many strikingly familiar, Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings (Greek Περὶ ἀποχῆς ἐµψύχων, Latin De abstinentia ab esu animalium) offers a sweeping view of the ancient debate concerning animals and their treatment. At the same time, because of its advocacy of an asceticism informed by its author’s Neoplatonism, Abstinence is often taken to be concerned primarily with the health of the human soul. By approaching Abstinence as a work of moral suasion and a work of literature, whose intra- and intertextual resonances yield something more than a collection of propositions or an invitation to Quellenforschung, I aim to push beyond interpretations that bracket the arguments regarding animals as merely dialectical; cast the text’s other-directed principle of justice as wholly ii subordinated to a self-directed principle of purity; or accept as decisive Porphyry’s exclusion of craftsmen, athletes, soldiers, sailors, and orators from his call to vegetarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics and Cosmology in Plato's Timaeus
    apeiron 2021; aop Andrew Gregory* Mathematics and Cosmology in Plato’s Timaeus https://doi.org/10.1515/apeiron-2020-0034 Published online March 18, 2021 Abstract: Plato used mathematics extensively in his account of the cosmos in the Timaeus, but as he did not use equations, but did use geometry, harmony and according to some, numerology, it has not been clear how or to what effect he used mathematics. This paper argues that the relationship between mathematics and cosmology is not atemporally evident and that Plato’s use of mathematics was an open and rational possibility in his context, though that sort of use of mathematics has subsequently been superseded as science has progressed. I argue that there is a philosophically and historically meaningful space between ‘primitive’ or unre- flective uses of mathematics and the modern conception of how mathematics relates to cosmology. Plato’s use of mathematics in the Timaeus enabled the cosmos to be as good as it could be, allowed the demiurge a rational choice (of which planetary orbits and which atomic shapes to instantiate) and allowed Timaeus to give an account of the cosmos (where if the demiurge did not have such a rational choice he would not have been able to do so). I also argue that within this space it is both meaningful and important to differentiate between Pythagorean and Platonic uses of number and that we need to reject the idea of ‘Pythagorean/ Platonic number mysticism’. Plato’s use of number in the Timaeus was not mystical even though it does not match modern usage.
    [Show full text]
  • Speusippus and Xenocrates on the Pursuit and Ends of Philosophy
    chapter 1 Speusippus and Xenocrates on the Pursuit and Ends of Philosophy Phillip Sidney Horky I Introduction The educational and institutional structure of the Academy after Plato’s death is one of the great unknowns in the history of ancient philosophy.1 Harold Cherniss, who thought the answer might lie in the educational curriculum out- lined in Republic VII, dubbed it the great “riddle of the early Academy”;2 con- trariwise, in considering the external evidence provided by Plato’s students and contemporaries, John Dillon speaks of a “fairly distinctive, though still quite open-ended, intellectual tradition.”3 One would think, especially given the extent of Plato’s discussion of the problem of educational and institution- al structures (not to mention the pedagogic journey of the individual teacher and student) that those figures who took over supervision of the Academy after Plato’s death – notably his polymath nephew Speusippus of Athens and his pop- ular and brilliant student Xenocrates of Chalcedon4 – would have devoted some attention to this issue of educational theory and practice in their writings. Af- ter all, several pseudepigraphical texts that are usually considered to have been written in the Academy and were ascribed to Plato – Theages, Alcibiades I (if inau- thentic), Alcibiades II, Epinomis, Rival Lovers, On Virtue, the Seventh Letter – do, indeed, devote significant space to elaborating pedagogical methods, practices, 1 Special thanks are owed to Mauro Bonazzi, Giulia De Cesaris, and David Sedley, each of whom read this piece with care and attention. I cannot promise to have responded suffi- ciently to their challenges in all circumstances, but I can say with confidence that this paper is much improved owing to their critical acumen.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Elements in the Myth of Plutarch's De Facie
    CHAPTER EIGHT ARISTOTELIAN ELEMENTS IN THE MYTH OF PLUTARCH'S DE FACIE As the material dealt with in chapter 7 showed, recovery of the sources of Plutarch's myth in the De facie is a perilous undertaking. Like Plato, Plutarch is first and foremost a creative author of great literary talent who is quite capable of developing and using entirely new motifs in his writings to further his philosophical or literary aims. Where he does not expressly mention his sources, certainty about older authors which he may have used cannot be gained. At the same time it is to be assumed that Plutarch made repeated use of themes and stories found in the literature of his time, which he collected and studied assiduously. As far as Plato's work is concerned, this is borne out by almost every page of Plutarch's writings. Influence is likely in the case of other writers, but difficult to determine because their works have been lost. One thinks of such figures as Speusippus, Xenocrates, Heraclides Ponticus, and Stoics like Posidonius. Matters are even more complicated as far as Aristotle is concerned. Although passages in Plutarch's writings often recall texts from the Corpus Aristotelicum, it cannot be established conclusively that Plutarch drew on them. F. H. Sandbach, on the other hand, has argued strongly that Plutarch had no knowledge of the Corpus and was only acquainted with Aristotle's published work, now lost.1 Where Plutarch does not name his source, however, it is difficult to ascertain what he derived from these published works.
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Pythagoreanism
    Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò Faculty of Classics University of Cambridge Clare Hall February 2018 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Alla nonna Ninni, che mi ha insegnato a leggere e scrivere Abstract Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò The sixth-century-BCE Pythagorean communities included both male and female members. This thesis focuses on the Pythagorean women and aims to explore what reasons lie behind the prominence of women in Pythagoreanism and what roles women played in early Pythagorean societies and thought. In the first chapter, I analyse the social conditions of women in Southern Italy, where the first Pythagorean communities were founded. In the second chapter, I compare Pythagorean societies with ancient Greek political clubs and religious sects. Compared to mainland Greece, South Italian women enjoyed higher legal and socio-political status. Similarly, religious groups included female initiates, assigning them authoritative roles. Consequently, the fact that the Pythagoreans founded their communities in Croton and further afield, and that in some respects these communities resembled ancient sects helps to explain why they opened their doors to the female gender to begin with. The third chapter discusses Pythagoras’ teachings to and about women. Pythagorean doctrines did not exclusively affect the followers’ way of thinking and public activities, but also their private way of living. Thus, they also regulated key aspects of the female everyday life, such as marriage and motherhood. I argue that the Pythagorean women entered the communities as wives, mothers and daughters. Nonetheless, some of them were able to gain authority over their fellow Pythagoreans and engage in intellectual activities, thus overcoming the female traditional domestic roles.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Aquinas Stopped Commenting on Boethius's De Trinitate
    Studia Gilsoniana 9, no. 1 (January–March 2020): 167–188 ISSN 2300–0066 (print) ISSN 2577–0314 (online) DOI: 10.26385/SG.090106 Faustinus Ik. Ugwuanyi* Why Aquinas Stopped Commenting on Boethius’s De Trinitate Over the last decade, Aquinas’s commentaries on the two works of Boethius, De Trinitate and De Hebdomadibus, has prompted worries among scholars. The central question is why Aquinas had to comment upon these works of Boethius nearly seven hundred years after the death of Boethius. Having made my submission in the ongoing debate,1 I was yet confronted with another problem of why Aquinas did not con- tinue the commentary on Boethius’s De Trinitate. Note that Aquinas’s commentary stops at question six, article four without any explanation as to why, and this is before the point in the text where Boethius gets to the heart of the subject matter. This question sounds unlikely and, as such, I do not think it can be shown answered directly from the texts. Nevertheless, I believe that from the absence of a separate text on Aqui- nas’s reason for not continuing with the treatise of Boethius one may not conclude that such reasons do not exist. That such a conclusion would be premature can be clarified by comparison with the debate on the reasons behind his two commentaries on Boethius. Like the former, Aquinas produces no account for his reasons, but the intentions of changing the structural method of argument and the bid to establish the *Fr. Faustinus Ik. Ugwuanyi — John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin, Poland e-mail: [email protected] ▪ ORCID: 0000-0003-4755-2825 1 See Faustinus Ugwuanyi, “Aquinas’ Commentaries on Boethius’ Treatises: A Modi- fication or Interpretation?” Roczniki Kulturoznawcze 10, no.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity
    THE CAMBRIDGE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY IN LATE ANTIQUITY The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity comprises over forty specially commissioned essays by experts on the philosophy of the period 200–800 ce. Designed as a successor to The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy (ed. A. H. Armstrong), it takes into account some forty years of schol- arship since the publication of that volume. The contributors examine philosophy as it entered literature, science and religion, and offer new and extensive assess- ments of philosophers who until recently have been mostly ignored. The volume also includes a complete digest of all philosophical works known to have been written during this period. It will be an invaluable resource for all those interested in this rich and still emerging field. lloyd p. gerson is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Toronto. He is the author of numerous books including Ancient Epistemology (Cambridge, 2009), Aristotle and Other Platonists (2005)andKnowing Persons: A Study in Plato (2004), as well as the editor of The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus (1996). The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity Volume II edited by LLOYD P. GERSON cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao˜ Paulo, Delhi, Dubai, Tokyo, Mexico City Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 8ru,UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521876421 C Cambridge University Press 2010 This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
    [Show full text]