University of Groningen William of Conches and the Tradition Of
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
University of Groningen William of Conches and the tradition of Boethius' Consolatio Philosophiae Nauta, Lodewijk Willem IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult the publisher's version (publisher's PDF) if you wish to cite from it. Please check the document version below. Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Publication date: 1999 Link to publication in University of Groningen/UMCG research database Citation for published version (APA): Nauta, L. W. (1999). William of Conches and the tradition of Boethius' Consolatio Philosophiae: an edition of his Glosae super Boetium and studies of the Latin commentary tradition. s.n. Copyright Other than for strictly personal use, it is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). The publication may also be distributed here under the terms of Article 25fa of the Dutch Copyright Act, indicated by the “Taverne” license. More information can be found on the University of Groningen website: https://www.rug.nl/library/open-access/self-archiving-pure/taverne- amendment. Take-down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Downloaded from the University of Groningen/UMCG research database (Pure): http://www.rug.nl/research/portal. For technical reasons the number of authors shown on this cover page is limited to 10 maximum. Download date: 30-09-2021 INTRODUCTION william of Conches, one of the most brilliant mÍrstersof the first half of the twelfth century, has long been associatedwith the so- called School of Chartres, that reputedly unique centre where there emerged a humanistic study of classical texts, a rationalistic reading of the work of Nature secundum physicam, a daring approach to the Scriptures, and a Platonically inspired poetry. Although the concept of the school of chartres seenx to have outlived its usefulness,rit is still often (for better or worse) used as a short-hand term to characterize exciting intellectual innovations in the twelfth century.2 one of the fiercest opponents of this concept, Sir Richard Southern, does not consider it superfluous to reprint his earlier, controversial essaysin his latest book from 1995. As is well-known, in these essayssouthern tried to explode the myth, kept alive by generationsof scholars, of the School of chartres. His claim, to which he still adheres. is two- fold:3 (1) The historical evidence (charters, wills and contemporary reports) for the existenceof a school at Chartres as an institution is shaky to the extent that not all the famous masters such as Bernard of chartres, Thierry of chartres, william of conches and Gilbert of Poitiers, who have traditionally been associatedwith the school, can confidently be linked to it. His principal argument is that rhe appearance of a master as a witness to charters connected with Chartres is no evidence that that master was actually teaching in the cathedral school. ' This at least was the opinion of the majoriry of scholars gathered at a workshop on l2th-century natural philosophy at the warburg Institute (London) in April 1998. 2 'charrrian' The adjective appearsin almost every study on l2th-c. philosophy. See most recently A. Speer, Die entdeckte Natar. Untersuchungen zu Begriindungs- 'scientia versuchen einer naturalis' im 12. Jahrhunden, Leiden 1995, 14-15, who 'School 'nicht writes that although the concept of the of Charres' unumstritten ist, so steht sie doch ftir eine gemeinsameintellektuelle Tendenz, die eine bestimmte. auch lokal aufeinander bezogene Gruppe von Gelehrten des 12. Jahrhunderu 'Glosae verbindet...'. see also The super Platonem'of Bernard of chartres, ed.. wittr introd. by P. E. Dutton, Toronto 1991. 3 'Medieval 'Humanism R. W. Southern, Humanism' and and the School of Chartres', in his Medieval Humnnism and Other Studies, Oxford 1970; id., Platonism, Scholastic Method and the School of Chanres, Reading 1979; id., .The schools of Paris and the School of Charres', Renaissanceand Renewal in the Twelfth Century, eds. R. L. Benson and G. Constable, Cambridge, Mass. 19g2, ll3-37; id., scholastic Thought and the (Inification of Europe. vol. I. Foundations, Oxford 1995 (where the paper from 1970 on the School of Charnes is reprinted with a reply to his critics). xvi INTRODUCTION (2) The enonnous philosophical reputation of the masters argul 'all associatedwith the School of Chartres is unfounded, for their pictu thoughts', Southernwrote in characteristicallylapidary style, 'were force 'a old thoughts' and neither the method nor the outlook was matter char: for individual choice; they were imposed upon all mastersby theil Plat< common methods of interpretation, analysis and conflation oÍ the 'phi1 texts'.a This generation of twelfth-century masters, living as they did sapi just before the introduction of the Aristotelian co{pus, were at the l 'To end of a cul-de-sac: gather new material, to systematize the deb: new as they had systematizedthe old, to reach out to new patterns secc of thought, and to fill the vast empty spacesof ignorance, were not tasks that belonged to the future'.s But Southern too could not Íegz neglect the fact that the new Greco-Arabic learning, which at this trad time began to be translated from Arabic and Greek into Latin, had beel a strong appeal to the very same scholars. Where this ambiguity Mo could lead is well illustrated by the confusing use of metaphors. He bee 'youth', speaksof William and his contemporariesin terms of but that 'reaching also as men the end of the road because they had reached wol the end of the availablefacts', having'old thoughts', and in still 'bridge another place he refers to a between the meagre scientific of t resources(...) and the massive influx of new material'.6 In view Chr of Southern's principal motivation which, I think, has always been str< to stress a continuing reassertionof the claims of human dignity cen and the dignity of nature itself during the twelfth and thirteenrh der centuries, his final picture is neverthelessclear: these early twelfth- tho century scholars did not do a bad job, but given the time and Wi circumstances in which they had to work, it was a limited job, sch guided only by the light of Plato, who was soon to be replacedby Co his disciple Aristotle, and to witness the culmination of this process the 'Chartrian' generation,alas, was born too early. Criticisms were soon voiced. Two of Southern's most important critics, Peter Dronke and Nikolaus Háring, both pointed Me out a number of flaws and rash conclusions in Southern's Re' 261 InJ o Southern, Medieval Humanism,83, and Platonism,2l. pc 5 Southern, Medieval Humanism,83. 21 'Huizinga's 6 Southern, Medieval Humanism,77, 81,41. Cf. my Lente der Middeleeuwen. De plaats van de twaalfde-eeuwse renaissance in zijn werk', A Tijdschrift voor Geschiedenis108, 1995, 3-23 on 20-1 for a comparison between T Southern's viewpoint and Huizinga's similar though differently motivated ideason o the l2th-c.'renaissance'. L INTRODUCTION xvll masters arguments.TAlthough they too qualified the over-enthusiastic all rheir pictureof earlier generationsof historians, they continued to argue 'were 'Chartrian' e, forcefully for the existence of a philosophy, a matter characterized by a humanistic interest in classical texts and a by their Platonicworldview, one imbued with a poetic intuition, which in rtion of the words of Wetherbee, is finally the only means of linking 'philosophy and theology, pagan auctores and Christian doctrine, hey did sapíentiaand eloquentia'.8 e at the It is not my intention to review, let alone to resuscitate,these tize the debates.Briefly put, I think that for most scholars, Southern's 'all patterns secondargument, that their thoughts were old thoughts', has e, were not been acceptable,but that some scepticism was called for with uld not regardto the historical evidence for the existence of an unbroken Lat this traditionof teaching at Chartres, although on this point too it has tin, had beenshown that Southern was too sweeping in his statements.e rbiguity More importantly, the evidence of the manuscripts known to have ors. He beenin the cathedral library in the twelfth century clearly shows [h', but that Chanres was an important place for the assimilation of new reached worksinto the old curriculum.ro in still What is of relevancehere however is that the name of William ;ientific of Concheshas always loomed large in the debateon the School of h view Chartres and that an assessmentof his scholarship has been ys been stronglyinfluenced by historians' views on the place of the twelfth- 'Renaissance' dignity century (another tern that has been subject to some irteenth demystification) within the broader developments of medieval welfth- thought and culture. Some have stressed the new elements in ne and William's thought and his formative role in the emergence of 'Bei :d job, scholastic philosophy. As Flatten wrote: Wilhelm von ced by Conches sehen wir bereits einen Ansatz. ein Svstem der )rocess most 7 'New P. Dronke, Approaches to the School of Charres' , Anuario de Estudios ointed 'Chartres Medievales6, L969 lpubl. 1971], 117-40, and N. M. Hàring, and Paris hern's Revisited',Esscys in Honour of A. C. Pegis, ed. J. R. O'Donnell, Toronto 1974, 268-329. 8 W. Wetherbee, Platonism and Poetry in the Twelfth Century: The Literary Influenceof the School of Chanres, Princeton N.l. 1972, 4. e Seeesp. Háring,'Chartres and Paris Revisited'. Scepticismon this second point, however, has recently been reinforced by Dutton tnhis Bernard of Chartres, 2145, who has reviewed the skimpy evidence for Bernard's career.