Freeing Althusser from Spinoza

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Freeing Althusser from Spinoza C ABSTRACT: C R R I The concept of structural causality, associated with the work I S of Louis Althusser, was, one can say, short-lived: even its foremost S I I Freeing AlthusserS advocates seemed to drop it just about as quickly as they picked it up, S while other concepts in Althusser’s work continued to be popular. This & & paper proposes to discuss both the problems with and the merits of C C R the concept, calling particular attention to the philosophical work it R I was supposed to do, which was both critical and constructive, negative I from Spinoza: T T I and positive. Critical and negative in that it offered a way to avoid I Q both a naturalistic mechanism and a Hegelian expressivism. In other Q U U E words, it aimed to avoid both a naïve materialism and a naïve idealism. E Constructive and positive, in that it was contributing to a new picture of A Reconsidera- # # 3 the relationship between structure and what is structured, by trying to 3 give an account of the manner in which structure was present and “in the real”: and, I will add, thereby providing the groundwork for a better version of dialectical materialism. There is no doubt that Spinoza’s tion of Structural philosophy provided Althusser with the model for thinking of this form of causality. But the use of Spinoza as a model can also be identified as the source of many of the problems with the concept. An essay by Warren Montag dealing with an exchange between Althusser and Pierre Causality Macherey will serve as the basis for my discussion of Spinoza and structural causality. Keywords: Althusser, Hegel, Macherey, Montag, Spinoza, structural causality. “Thought must begin by placing itself at the standpoint of Ed Pluth Spinozism; to be a follower of Spinoza is the essential commencement of all Philosophy” (Hegel 1994, p. 257) “But if Spinoza is called an atheist for the sole reason that he does not distinguish God from the world, it is a misuse of the term. Spinozism might really just as well or even better have been termed ACOSMISM… Spinoza maintains that there is no such thing as what is known as the world; it is merely a form of God, and in and for itself it is nothing. The world has no true reality, and all this that we know as the world has been cast into the abyss of the one identity. There is therefore no such thing as finite reality, it has no truth whatever” (Hegel 1994, p. 281) 336 Freeing Althusser from Spinoza: A Reconsideration of Structural Causality 337 Freeing Althusser from Spinoza: A Reconsideration of Structural Causality In so many ways, for so many reasons, Spinoza seems to be a C Spinoza, since it will lead to a different way of evaluating the relationship C R R philosopher who is preferable to Hegel – non-totalitarian, radically I between the apparent and the real. The way to get at this is through a I democratic, a seemingly communist, horizontal ontology… So why S reconsideration of structural causality. S I I try to free Althusser from Spinoza? In 1979 Pierre Macherey asked, S S intentionally messing with the chronology, “Hegel or Spinoza”? His The foremost criticisms of the concept of structural causality & & answer, of course, was “Spinoza,” and his reason for putting Spinoza target its fatal circularity. As Ted Benton argued, the concept seems C C after Hegel was to suggest that Spinoza had been capable of reading R to do either too little or too much: it cannot do much to help us to R Hegel in a certain sense, and was in fact a better reader of Hegel than I understand specific causal relations among elements of an event or a I T T Hegel had been of Spinoza. At the end of his book, he claims that I totality– and so it is essentially useless as far as political and critical I the choice for Spinoza is made, not without some reservations, in Q practice goes. And if structural causality is about the causality of Q U U the expectation that Spinoza’s work would aid in the development of E something like a totality itself, then it makes structure way too strong, E a non-Hegelian dialectic, one that would avoid, among other things, external, and transcendent – yet again making the concept theoretically # # what Macherey called the “evolutionism” of Hegel’s. I will assume this 3 uninteresting, tautological, and as far as practice goes, even debilitating 3 criticism of Hegel is familiar enough. Also, Spinoza’s work could, it was (Benton 1984, pp. 64-5). On this view, the Spinozism that inspired hoped, serve as a better basis for materialism. Yet it is fair to say that the structural causality would make the concept a bit too God-drunk. jury is still out on all this. Such objections to structural causality seem to follow a Popperian There are some obvious reasons why a Spinozistic model line of attack, and this seems to be the consensus view of its problems. is problematic for any project that wishes to continue with both What Gregory Elliot calls Althusser’s “rationalist epistemology” is materialism and dialectics. Such necessary conceptual tools as time, described by him as “untenable – condemned by an internalism which change, negation…these all have a shaky status in Spinoza’s philosophy insulated theoretical discourse from empirical evidence and severs it – or, strictly speaking, on the Hegelian interpretation of Spinoza at from its real referent” (Elliot 1987, p. 329). Since there is nothing that least, they have no status at all. Then there is the theism. This is why could count as a refutation of the theory of structural causality, this Hegel called Spinoza’s philosophy an ACOSMISM. The God-drunk account goes, the concept cannot really be considered to do all that philosopher was certainly no atheist: what he did deny, Hegel argued, much. What is philosophical and rationalist about it, which Elliot calls was the reality of the world itself. By denying the reality of time, the its “internalism,” dooms it to the status of a pseudo-science. reality of human experience itself is called into question. Thus, “the For a similar conclusion in slightly different terms, we can also world,” such as we know it and experience it, it can be fairly argued, turn to Jacques Rancière, who, in an interview about the Cahiers project, does not exist, Spinoza’s philosophy must hold. Macherey does not ever was asked by Peter Hallward: really address this aspect of Hegel’s criticism. Perhaps that is because And this idea of structural causality, central to analysis of the the denunciation of the apparent world in Spinoza actually goes ‘action of the structure’ (to use the Cahiers’ phrase)…could it have, in quite well with the Althusserian critique of ideology and its embrace principle, served as mediation between theory and practice, once all of science as a radical break with the empirical. Isn’t something like reference to consciousness, to the subject, to militant will, etc. was Spinoza’s acosmism entirely appropriate as a model for a wide range of removed? And this way, through the analysis of causality, it would contemporary approaches to human experience, from psychoanalysis be possible not only to study history but to understand how to make to Marxism, all of which are suspicious of what is merely apparent and history. (Rancière 2012, p. 269) seemingly obvious? To which Rancière replied: My reconsideration of the question “Hegel or Spinoza” here is Yes, certainly, it allowed for a kind of double attitude. First one in large part driven by concerns about acosmism. Freeing Althusser could say, here we are presenting theory, as far as can be from any from Spinoza, I am arguing, means freeing Althusser from Spinozistic thought of engagement, of lived experience; this theory refutes false “acosmism”. And this, I believe, brings his work closer to Hegel than to ideas, idealist ideas about the relation between theory and practice. But 338 Freeing Althusser from Spinoza: A Reconsideration of Structural Causality 339 Freeing Althusser from Spinoza: A Reconsideration of Structural Causality one could also hope that theoretical practice itself might open up other C model, time, space, or structure to which it is applied – such as, most C R R fields for new ways of thinking about political practice… In fact it didn’t I notably, the capitalist mode of production, its origins, its conditions, its I open any such fields. (p. 269) S future. A theory of structural causality on its own will not tell us much S I I And although Rancière does not in this interview go into specific S about the particulars of the social movements, transformations, etc. S reasons for why the concept did not open up ways for thinking about that are associated with that mode of production’s appearance. Yet, & & the links between theory and practice, one can easily imagine that the philosophically speaking, the concept continues to do much more than it C C circularity problem would be a major one. R seems at first blush. R But it is Jean-Claude Milner, interviewed by Knox Peden in the I I T T same volume, who refers explicitly to what he thinks was the lamentable I It seems that no discussion of structural causality can get started I absence of Popper for those working in France during this period. Now Q without turning to how Althusser himself developed it as an alternative Q U U that Popper’s line of questioning is better known in France, Milner E to other views of causality, called mechanism and expressivism.
Recommended publications
  • A Love Knowing Nothing: Zen Meets Kierkegaard
    Journal of Buddhist Ethics ISSN 1076-9005 http://blogs.dickinson.edu/buddhistethics/ Volume 22, 2015 A Love Knowing Nothing: Zen Meets Kierkegaard Mary Jeanne Larrabee DePaul University Copyright Notice: Digital copies of this work may be made and distributed provided no change is made and no alteration is made to the content. Reproduction in any other format, with the exception of a single copy for private study, requires the written permission of the author. All en- quiries to: [email protected]. A Love Knowing Nothing: Zen Meets Kierkegaard Mary Jeanne Larrabee 1 Abstract I present a case for a love that has a wisdom knowing nothing. How this nothing functions underlies what Kier- kegaard urges in Works of Love and how Zen compassion moves us to action. In each there is an ethical call to love in action. I investigate how Kierkegaard’s “religiousness B” is a “second immediacy” in relation to God, one spring- ing from a nothing between human and God. This imme- diacy clarifies what Kierkegaard takes to be the Christian call to love. I draw a parallel between Kierkegaard’s im- mediacy and the expression of immediacy within a Zen- influenced life, particularly the way in which it calls the Zen practitioner to act toward the specific needs of the person standing before one. In my understanding of both Kierkegaard and Zen life, there is also an ethics of re- sponse to the circumstances that put the person in need, such as entrenched poverty or other injustices. 1 Department of Philosophy, DePaul University. Email: [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • Ateísmo, Panteísmo, Acosmismo Y Monoteísmo En La Filosofía De Hegel | Javier Fabo Lanuza
    Ateísmo, panteísmo, acosmismo y monoteísmo en la filosofía de Hegel | Javier Fabo Lanuza Ateísmo, panteísmo, acosmismo y monoteísmo en la filosofía de Hegel (Comentario de un conocido pasaje sobre Spinoza) PhD. Javier Fabo Lanuza. Universidad Complutense de Madrid ([email protected]) Resumen Abstract Ateísmo y panteísmo son sistemáticamente Atheism, pantheism, acosmism and rechazados por Hegel a lo largo de su obra. monotheism in Hegel's philosophy Testimonio paradigmático de este rechazo es la (Commentary on a well-known Anm. del § 573 de la Enz., en la que el filósofo critica duramente el panteísmo, a la vez que se passage on Spinoza) desmarca netamente del ateísmo. Ello no ha impedido que los más afines a su filosofía Atheism and pantheism have been vieran en su crítica de la religión una systematically rejected by Hegel throughout his declaración de ateísmo, ni tampoco que su work. The Anm. of § 573 of the Enz. is a idealismo absoluto apareciera a ojos de los más paradigmatic testimony of this rejection, in críticos como una suerte de panteísmo which the philosopher strongly criticizes soterrado, sospechosamente afín a lo que Heine pantheism, and at the same time he clearly 267 llamaba «la religión secreta de Alemania». El distances himself from atheism. This has not Nº 101 propósito de este artículo es mostrar los prevented those closest to his philosophy from Julio-agosto 2021 malentendidos que subyacen a estas seeing in his critique of religion a declaration of interpretaciones, analizando los pasajes que atheism, nor has his absolute idealism appear to han contribuido a suscitarlas, de entre los que the most critical eyes as a kind of buried destaca el célebre elogio a Spinoza de las pantheism, suspiciously akin to what Heine Lecciones berlinesas, erróneamente tomado called «the secret religion of Germany».
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Philosophy Of
    L- ,o C| L> t ty- NUI MAYNOOTH Ollacali •• atiraann Wt Huad BOHM E AND HEGEL: A STUDY OF THEIR INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT AND SHARED READINGS OF TWO CHRISTIAN THEOLOGOUMENA NEIL O’DONNELL SUBMITTED WITH A VIEW TO OBTAIN THE DEGREE OF M.LITT. NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF IRELAND, MAYNOOTH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, FACULTY OF ARTS, CELTIC STUDIES, AND PHILOSOPHY OCTOBER 2008 ACTING HEAD OF DEPARTMENT DR MICHAEL DUNNE SUPERVISED BY DR CYRIL MCDONNELL CONTENTS Preface IV Abstract v Abbreviations and Conventions vii INTRODUCTION CHAPTER I THE DEVELOPMENT OF BÖHME AND HEGEL’S PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Section One Reaction Against Christian Orthodoxy 6 § 1. 1. The Development o f Böhme ’s Theological Vision in the Face o f Protestant Orthodoxy 7 § 1. 2. Hegel, Tübingen, and Protestant Orthodoxy 16 Section Two Heterodox Leanings 27 § 2. 1. Böhme ’s Period o f Silence and the Failure o f Hermeticism 28 § 2. 2. Hegel's Swabian Heritage 38 Section Three The Return to the Reformation 53 § 3. 1. Böhme ’s Return to the Reformation 54 § 3. 2. Hegel the Reformer? 68 § 3. 3. 1. Liberating Religion from Representation 76 CHAPTER II THE CONCEPT OF GOD 86 Section One The Father 91 § 1. 1. Böhme 's Conception o f the Deus Absconditus 96 § 1. 2. Hegel’s Treatment o f Böhme 's Trinitarian Dynamic 107 § 1. 3. H eg e l’s G od and its H istorical Traces 112 Section Two The Son 119 § 2. 1. The Personhood o f the Trinity 120 §2. 2. The Incarnation 130 Section Three The Holy Spirit 144 § 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza's Acosmism in Another Light
    THE DAY IN WHICH ALL COWS ARE WHITE: SPINOZA’S ACOSMISM IN ANOTHER LIGHT Jason DOCKSTADER* Abstract. In this essay, I aim to defend Spinoza against Hegel’s claim that he annihilated finite things and the real differences they instantiate. To counter Hegel’s charge of acosmism, I try to conceive of a Spinozist kind of acosmism that would mean not a metaphysical eliminativism or nihilism about finitude and diversity, but rather a metaphysical fictionalism about finitude that entails a latent application of the principle of the discernibility of identicals. I do this by focusing on the correspondence between Spinoza’s three kinds of knowledge – imagination, intellection, and intuition – and his understanding of things as being finite, infinite in kind, and absolutely infinite. In the process, I also entertain Yitzhak Melamed’s argument that Hegel was wrong to accuse Spinoza of acosmism, but was onto something by noting the lack of full or self-subsistent existence on the part of finite modes. Melamed offers a reading that claims Spinozist individuals are weak and functional properties that follow from God as his effects. I respond that Melamed would be correct only if we view things from the perspective of the first kind of knowledge, which is a perspective that is by definition false. I conclude, then, that finite things in Spinoza, qua finite, are not illusions, but fictions, and that when viewed truly or truthfully they are so many infinite in kind or absolutely infinite ways one infinite and eternal substance, God or nature, is discernibly identical to itself. Keywords: Spinoza, Hegel, Acosmism, Discernibility, Infinite, Knowledge, Truth I.
    [Show full text]
  • ART4 Dial107articulomiguelbadia Reveh8dec2020
    HEGEL’S APPROACH TO THE KNOWLEDGE OF GOD IN THE LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Miguel A. Badía Cabrera Universidad de Puerto Rico [email protected] Resumen: Con las Lecciones sobre la filosofía de la religión Hegel muy probablemente se convierte no sólo en un predecesor, sino en el fundador de la filosofía de la religión contemporánea. Esto es así porque en esta obra esboza un acercamiento original al conocimiento de Dios. Cuando Hegel dilucida el concepto de religión como la “consciencia” (Bewusstsein), y en especial la “ocupación” (Beschäftigung) del ser humano con Dios, diferencia la perspectiva objetiva de la teología natural del punto de vista doblemente subjetivo de la filosofía de la religión. Mientras que en la primera disciplina Dios es aprehendido como un objeto “abstracto” del pensamiento —Dios como meramente es en sí mismo—, en la segunda conocer a Dios es primariamente percatarse de él como un sujeto “concreto” que aparece a los sujetos que nosotros somos, ya que “El Espíritu de Dios es esencialmente en su comunidad”. El énfasis de Hegel en “esta esfera íntima” (dies Innerste) ejemplariza un enfoque análogo al de pensadores medulares del siglo veinte quienes, a partir de tradiciones filosóficas diferentes, aseveran que el conocimiento de Dios hay que sacarlo de adentro. Palabras clave: Hegel, filosofía de la religión, Dios, religión, Espíritu, Innerste, Unamuno Abstract: With the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion Hegel arguably becomes not just a forerunner, but the founder of contemporary philosophy of religion. This is because in this work he delineates an original approach to the knowledge of God.
    [Show full text]
  • Māyā and Becoming: Deleuze and Vedānta on Attributes, Acosmism
    COMPARATIVE AND CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY https://doi.org/10.1080/17570638.2018.1488354 Māyā and Becoming: Deleuze and Vedānta on Attributes, Acosmism, and Parallelism in Spinoza Michael Hemmingsen Division of Humanities, College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences, University of Guam, Guam, USA ABSTRACT KEYWORDS This paper compares two readings of Baruch Spinoza – those of Deleuze; Vedānta; Spinoza; Gilles Deleuze and Rama Kanta Tripathi – with a particular focus māyā; becoming on three features of Spinoza’s philosophy: the relationship between substance and attribute; the problem of acosmism and unity; and the problem of the parallelism of attributes. Deleuze and Tripathi’s understanding of these three issues in Spinoza’s thought illustrates for us their own concerns with becoming over substance (in the non-Spinozistic sense) and māyā, respectively. This investigation provides not just two interesting and contradictory interpretations of Spinoza, but also gives us insight into Deleuze’s metaphysics and Tripathi’s Vedāntic philosophy. Interpreting historical thinkers often brings with it the concerns and preconceptions of those engaged in the reading. As such, in considering the views of later interpreters of a philosopher or philosophy, we can sometimes learn just as much about the views of those doing the interpreting as we can about the “correct” way of reading the original phi- losopher. A good example of this appears in contemporary readings of Baruch Spinoza. In this paper, I look at Spinoza through the eyes of Gilles Deleuze and Rama Kanta Tripathi. Their interpretations of Spinoza help to illuminate some of the concerns and presupposi- tions in their own thought and help us further understand their own philosophical pos- itions.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel on Indian Philosophy: Spinozism, Romanticism, Eurocentrism Gino Signoracci University of New Mexico
    University of New Mexico UNM Digital Repository Philosophy ETDs Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 5-4-2017 Hegel on Indian Philosophy: Spinozism, Romanticism, Eurocentrism Gino Signoracci University of New Mexico Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/phil_etds Part of the Comparative Philosophy Commons, Continental Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Signoracci, Gino. "Hegel on Indian Philosophy: Spinozism, Romanticism, Eurocentrism." (2017). https://digitalrepository.unm.edu/ phil_etds/24 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Electronic Theses and Dissertations at UNM Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy ETDs by an authorized administrator of UNM Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Gino Signoracci Candidate Philosophy Department This dissertation is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication: Approved by the Dissertation Committee: Adrian Johnston, Chairperson John Taber Brent Kalar Iain Thomson Shannon Mussett i HEGEL ON INDIAN PHILOSOPHY: SPINOZISM, ROMANTICISM, EUROCENTRISM by GINO SIGNORACCI B.A., Philosophy, English, University of Notre Dame, 2004 M.A., Philosophy, Brock University, 2009 DISSERTATION Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Philosophy The University of New Mexico Albuquerque, New Mexico July, 2017 ii DEDICATION For Ally, for turning up, keeping up, putting up, picking (me) up, and never letting up: with love, good humor, and wonder iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS There are seven people whose abiding support, encouragement, sensitivity, patience, and understanding are the reason I completed this dissertation at all: Adrian, Ally, Jane, Jon, Judy, Kaity, and Krupa.
    [Show full text]
  • Yitzhak Y. Melamed Curriculum Vitae (10.23.2016) 7808 Crossland Road, Baltimore, MD 21208 Phone: (410) 484-0276 Email: [email protected]
    Yitzhak Y. Melamed Curriculum Vitae (10.23.2016) 7808 Crossland Road, Baltimore, MD 21208 Phone: (410) 484-0276 Email: [email protected] EDUCATION 1996-2005 Yale University - Ph.D., Philosophy (2005). Dissertation The Metaphysics of Substance and the Metaphysics of Thought in Spinoza. Advisor: Professor Michael Della Rocca. 1992-1996 Tel Aviv University - M.A. in History and Philosophy of Science, Summa cum laude. Master's thesis: The Liar Paradox, Sentence Construction, and the atemporality of Logic. 1991-1995 Tel Aviv University - B.A.-M.A. Program, The Elkana-Lautman Interdisciplinary Program for Outstanding Students. Main fields of study: Philosophy, Neuropsychology, and Mathematics. 1990-1991 Tel Aviv University - B.A. Studies, Psychology and Philosophy. AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Early Modern Philosophy; German Idealism. AREAS OF COMPETENCE Metaphysics (primarily, tropes, mereology, and time); 19th Century Philosophy; Medieval Philosophy; History & Philosophy of Science; Political philosophy. TEACHING EXPERIENCE July 2016 Johns Hopkins University. Charlotte Bloomberg Professor of Philosophy and the Humanities. 2013 - 2016 Johns Hopkins University. Professor. Department of Philosophy. Courses taught: “The Identity of Indiscernibles”; “Spinoza’s Metaphysics”; “History of Modern Philosophy”; “Spinoza’s Theological Political Treatise”; “Spinoza and German Idealism” (co-taught with Eckart Förster); “Topics in Metaphysics: Mereology”; “Spinoza and the Pantheism Controversy” (co- taught with Eckart Förster); “Descartes”; “Kant and the Early
    [Show full text]
  • 03 Dillon.Indd
    International Journal for the Study of New Religions 9.1 (2018) 57–81 ISSN 2041-9511 (print) ISSN 2041-952X (online) https://doi.org/10.1558/ijsnr.37614 he Impact of Scholarship on Contemporary “Gnosticism(s)”: A Case Study on the Apostolic Johannite Church and Jeremy Puma Matthew J. Dillon DePauw University [email protected] his article examines the impact of academic discourses on Neo-Gnosticism. he identities and ritual practices of Neo-Gnostics are constructed with refer- ence to Gnostic Studies. Analysis of two case studies (the Apostolic Johannite Church and Jeremy Puma) shows how academic discourse legitimizes, chal- lenges, or reforms Gnostic identity in the twenty-irst century. Transformations and inventions of ancient Gnostic religion in the twenty- first century take place in a crowded field of discourse.1 here are dozens, per- haps hundreds of organized Gnostic churches in North America.2 Prominent artists, writers, and intellectuals claim to be Gnostics and produce works that 1. I use the term discourse in line with Jan Assmann to refer to “a concatenation of texts which are based on each other and treat or negotiate a common subject matter” (Ass- mann YEAR, 15–16). Lincoln (1989) exhibits how such discourses (in myth, ritual, and classification) on the past serve to negotiate religious identities. Post-structuralist approaches to discourse analysis, stressing the symbolic capital entrenched in particular discourses and the power dynamics inherent in the definition of terms, is a diferent project (Foucault 1972; Gee 1999); in action regarding the study of esotericism see for example, Robertson (2010); von Stuckrad (2010).
    [Show full text]
  • Soudan2020.Pdf (1.383Mb)
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. SPELLS OF OUR INHABITING: TRANSITIONING FROM THE SPECTRE OF GNOSTIC ESTRANGEMENT TO A PHILOSOPHY OF ENTANGLED OVERFLOWING Clara SOUDAN PhD in Philosophy The University of Edinburgh 2019 This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza's Philosophy & Nihilism
    Spinoza’s Philosophy & Nihilism God, Truth, and Freedom in an Uncaring Universe M.G. (Gaby) de Jong MA Thesis Philosophy – University Utrecht Student Number: 3697975 Program: Academic Master Philosophy Thesis Advisor: dr. Albert Gootjes Second Reader dr. Johan de Jong Date of Submission: 24/05/2017 Total Word Count: 21034 (main text: 18333) Contact: [email protected] 1 “Spinoza has been claimed as the ancestor, founder, or originator of many things, both good and evil, among them the ruin of all religions, biblical criticism, liberalism, Jewish secularism, Zionism, the enlightenment, secularization, neurobiology, evolutionary theory, toleration, libertarianism, and modernity as such. Taken together these claims are too good to be true, and yet one can usually see why people have interpreted Spinoza’s heritage along these lines.” Piet Steenbakkers, Spinoza Research: To Be Continued (2016). Pg. 19. While writing my thesis I could not help but recall these words spoken by professor Steenbakkers in his farewell address, almost anticipating a project such as my own. The first Spinoza lecture I received was in 2009 (or 2010) and given by professor Steenbakkers when I was yet to become a student of philosophy. It seems only fitting that his words are at the beginning of the end of my philosophical path that as a circle begins and ends with Spinoza. 2 Table of Contents Introduction ................................................................................................. 4 I. Interpreting Scripture and Defending Freedom ....................................
    [Show full text]
  • God, Self, and Identity: a Comparative Examination of Eastern And
    1 GOD, SELF, AND IDENTITY: A COMPARATIVE EXAMINATION OF EASTERN AND WESTERN PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION A Honors Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Psychology and Philosophy Sam Houston State University In Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for the Degree of Bachelor of Arts By Matthew McGrenera May 2020 2 GOD, SELF, AND IDENTITY: A COMPARATIVE EXAMINATION OF EASTERN AND WESTERN PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION By Matthew McGrenera APPROVED: Dr. Harris Bechtol, Ph.D. Director Dr. Kimberly Bell, Ph.D. Dean, Elliott T. Bowers Honors College 3 DEDICATION To Patrick and Kathleen McGrenera, for the opportunity. I love you Mom and Dad. 4 ABSTRACT Matthew McGrenera, God, Self, and Identity: A Comparative Examination of Eastern and Western Philosophy of Religion . Bachelor of Arts (Philosophy), May, 2020, Sam Houston State University, Huntsville, Texas. This project is intended to prove that Eastern philosophy can be used along with Western philosophy to further what seems to be the limitation of human comprehension. The paper will focus on Hinduism in comparison with three Western philosophers: GWF Hegel, Baruch Spinoza, and John Locke. This paper will be a unique take on the philosophy of religion through a comparative philosophy approach. The paper will explore three main topics: God, Self and Identity. It will do so through a case study on each topic. The case studies are to be seen as evidence that this form of comparative philosophy can be beneficial in progressing philosophy. The case studies are not intended to be separate from one another. While they can exist alone as evidence of the conclusion, they are intended to be read in sequence as there is a clear connection that exists between them.
    [Show full text]