Some Theorists Argue That Moral Bioenhancement Ought to Be Compulsory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Some Theorists Argue That Moral Bioenhancement Ought to Be Compulsory Penultimate draft—final version to be published in Bioethics Compulsory Moral Bioenhancement Should Be Covert ABSTRACT: Some theorists argue that moral bioenhancement ought to be compulsory. I take this argument one step further, arguing that if moral bioenhancement ought to be compulsory, then its administration ought to be covert rather than overt. This is to say that it is morally preferable for compulsory moral bioenhancement to be administered without the recipients knowing that they are receiving the enhancement. My argument for this is that if moral bioenhancement ought to be compulsory, then its administration is a matter of public health, and for this reason should be governed by public health ethics. I argue that the covert administration of a compulsory moral bioenhancement program better conforms to public health ethics than does an overt compulsory program. In particular, a covert compulsory program promotes values such as liberty, utility, equality, and autonomy better than an overt program does. Thus, a covert compulsory moral bioenhancement program is morally preferable to an overt moral bioenhancement program. Keywords: moral enhancement; public health ethics; autonomy; public policy; harm Advancements in technology and globalization create many opportunities. Among them are not only greater opportunities to enhance our capacities for cognition, but also to use those enhanced capacities to cause “ultimate harm,” which is an event or series of events that brings about either the annihilation of humanity or a condition of living that is so poor that life is not worthwhile.1 Global in scope, ultimate harm is characterized by high rates of death, and, for those that survive, immense suffering. Examples of potential catalysts of ultimate harm are familiar and include global warming, terrorists, and short- sighted scientists unleashing a plague. Some argue that as cognitive enhancement increases in scope and availability, the potential for ultimate harm is greater, especially when conjoined with some of the possible catalysts of ultimate harm.2 But an event or series of events doesn’t have to be caused by an agent or agents to be ultimate harm. A large meteor or supernova could also bring about ultimate harm. 1 Persson, I., & Savulescu, J. (2008). The perils of cognitive enhancement and the urgent imperative to enhance the moral character of humanity. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 25(3), 162–177 2 Op. cit. note 1. 1 Penultimate draft—final version to be published in Bioethics Persson and Savulescu claim that in order to prevent the greater possibility of ultimate harm, it is necessary for humans to be morally enhanced.3 More specifically, it is necessary to morally bioenhance the population in order to prevent ultimate harm. Moral bioenhancement is the potential practice of influencing a person’s moral behavior by way of biological intervention upon their moral attitudes, motivations, or dispositions. The technology that may permit moral bioenhancement is on the scale between non-existent and nascent, but common examples of potential interventions include infusing water supplies with pharmaceuticals that enhance empathy or altruism or otherwise intervening on a person’s emotions or motivations, in an attempt to influence the person’s moral behavior. The proposal of engaging in moral bioenhancement has since generated a lot of controversy, resulting in a substantial literature debating the ethics of moral bioenhancement. Among the ethical issues with moral bioenhancement are its impact on autonomy, whether moral bioenhancement will result in a more or less egalitarian society, whether it will erode personal identity, and whether it will benefit others or just the people who are morally enhanced.4 There has also been debate around the empirical issues of whether a means of moral bioenhancement is or ever will be feasible and whether it really is necessary.5 Others have argued that if moral bioenhancement is 3 Persson & Savulescu op cit.; Persson, I., & Savulescu, J. (2012). Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement. Oxford University Press. Persson, I., & Savulescu, J. (2013). Should moral bioenhancement be compulsory? Reply to Vojin Rakic. Journal of Medical Ethics. 4 Douglas, T. (2008). Moral enhancement. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 25(3), 228– 245; Sparrow, R. (2014). Egalitarianism and moral bioenhancement. The American Journal of Bioethics : AJOB, 14(4), 20–8; 5 Crockett, M. J. (2014). Moral bioenhancement: a neuroscientific perspective. Journal of Medical Ethics, 40(6), 370–1; Harris, J. (2011). Moral enhancement and freedom. Bioethics, 25(2), 102–111; Sorensen, K. (2014). Moral enhancement and self-subversion objections. Neuroethics, 7(3), 275–286.; Wiseman, H. (2014a). SSRIs as Moral Enhancement Interventions: A Practical Dead End. AJOB Neuroscience, 5(3), 21–30.; Wiseman, H. (2016). The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement. MIT Press. 2 Penultimate draft—final version to be published in Bioethics necessary to prevent ultimate harm, then moral bioenhancement should be compulsory.6 I adopt this argument, but go a step further. Not only should moral bioenhancement be compulsory, it should also be covert, conducted without the knowledge of those who are being enhanced. I have previously argued on the grounds that it is the only way for a program to be effective for it to be covert (Author, redacted). Here I argue on ethical grounds that a moral bioenhancement program ought to be covert, if it ought to be compulsory. My argument rests on two assumptions. The first is that moral bioenhancement is necessary to prevent ultimate harm. Whether moral bioenhancement is so necessary is an empirical matter. Here, I assume it is necessary. The second assumption is that whatever moral bioenhancement is used will be safe and effective. Moral bioenhancement will be safe and effective when it can reliably intervene on a person’s moral capacities and do so without causing serious adverse events. Whether this assumption is true is also an empirical matter. Admittedly, these are demanding assumptions, and for some readers this demand may push what follows into the merely theoretical. Perhaps I give too much credit to scientists and too little to the moral motivations of large groups of people, but I don’t find the assumptions to be merely theoretical. Moreover, most of the recent discussion of the ethics of moral bioenhancement has proceeded from the assumption that moral bioenhancement can be safe and effective. It is a common assumption, and without it we can all stop discussing the ethics of moral bioenhancement until the science is settled. However, even if the argument that follows is merely theoretical, then it at least represents the limiting case from which it is possible to reason about other potential interventions upon moral behavior. The argument that follows is intended to support the claim that if moral bioenhancement ought to be compulsory, it ought to be covert. I do not offer a vigorous defense of the antecedent of this conditional, that moral bioenhancement ought to be compulsory. Others have defended this elsewhere, but I do review the argument for this 6 Persson & Savulescu (2008) op. cit. note 1 3 Penultimate draft—final version to be published in Bioethics position in the first section. Second, I argue that contrary to the focus of the literature on moral bioenhancement, moral bioenhancement is a matter of public health and is therefore subject to ethical norms that guide decisions on public health interventions rather than the ethical norms that guide individual medical decisions. I then introduce the frameworks for public health ethics. The final step is to argue that according to these frameworks, moral bioenhancement ought to be covert, if it is to be compulsory. Compared to an overt program, a covert program is better. This conclusion is likely to be unacceptable to some. I aim to establish the implication of covert moral bioenhancement from compulsory moral bioenhancement. If the consequent of this implication is unacceptable, it is a short step to the notion that moral bioenhancement should be voluntary. And if it shouldn’t be voluntary, the only alternative is to forego moral bioenhancement completely. I conclude with a discussion of these inferences. 1. Compulsory Moral Bioenhancement Given that the costs of not preventing ultimate harm are indefinitely high7, there is no intervention the costs of which would outweigh utility of the prevention of ultimate harm. Thus, if an intervention is necessary to prevent ultimate harm, and the intervention will actually prevent ultimate harm, then that intervention ought to be carried out, because the cost of not doing so is indefinitely high. Moral bioenhancement is necessary, because as cognitive enhancement makes causing ultimate harm more accessible to nefarious moral agents, ultimate harm is much more likely, unless everyone is enhanced.8 Where it used to require an extraordinarily coordinated effort to cause ultimate harm, now, or in the near future, it only takes one person. Thus, moral bioenhancement ought to be compulsory for everyone. 7 The costs of ultimate harm are so high because (a) not existing at all or existing in a state in which it would be better to not exist is the worst event, state, or intervention and (b) if ultimate harm were to occur it is impossible to know the goodness that such an occurrence would prevent (Persson & Savulescu op. cit. note 1). 8 I discuss in section five the likelihood and potential inevitability of ultimate harm. 4 Penultimate draft—final version to be published in Bioethics To get the conclusion that moral bioenhancement ought to be compulsory, three propositions must be true: that the costs of not preventing ultimate harm are indefinitely high; that moral bioenhancement is causally necessary to prevent ultimate harm; and that moral bioenhancement is safe and effective. That the costs of not preventing ultimate harm are indefinitely high is disputable. If ultimate harm has occurred, then most of us are either dead or in a state of living that is so bad that death would be an improvement.
Recommended publications
  • Human Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines
    Human Enhancement and Technologies Our Merger with Machines Human • Woodrow Barfield and Blodgett-Ford Sayoko Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines Edited by Woodrow Barfield and Sayoko Blodgett-Ford Printed Edition of the Special Issue Published in Philosophies www.mdpi.com/journal/philosophies Human Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines Human Enhancement Technologies and Our Merger with Machines Editors Woodrow Barfield Sayoko Blodgett-Ford MDPI • Basel • Beijing • Wuhan • Barcelona • Belgrade • Manchester • Tokyo • Cluj • Tianjin Editors Woodrow Barfield Sayoko Blodgett-Ford Visiting Professor, University of Turin Boston College Law School Affiliate, Whitaker Institute, NUI, Galway USA Editorial Office MDPI St. Alban-Anlage 66 4052 Basel, Switzerland This is a reprint of articles from the Special Issue published online in the open access journal Philosophies (ISSN 2409-9287) (available at: https://www.mdpi.com/journal/philosophies/special issues/human enhancement technologies). For citation purposes, cite each article independently as indicated on the article page online and as indicated below: LastName, A.A.; LastName, B.B.; LastName, C.C. Article Title. Journal Name Year, Volume Number, Page Range. ISBN 978-3-0365-0904-4 (Hbk) ISBN 978-3-0365-0905-1 (PDF) Cover image courtesy of N. M. Ford. © 2021 by the authors. Articles in this book are Open Access and distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license, which allows users to download, copy and build upon published articles, as long as the author and publisher are properly credited, which ensures maximum dissemination and a wider impact of our publications. The book as a whole is distributed by MDPI under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons license CC BY-NC-ND.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Bioenhancement: an Ethical and Philosophical Investigation
    Moral Bioenhancement: An Ethical and Philosophical Investigation by Andrea C Palk Dissertation presented for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences at Stellenbosch University Supervisor: Prof Anton A van Niekerk March 2018 The financial assistance of the National Research Foundation (NRF) towards this research is hereby acknowledged. Opinions expressed, and conclusions arrived at, are those of the author and are not necessarily to be attributed to the NRF Stellenbosch University https://scholar.sun.ac.za DECLARATION By submitting this thesis electronically, I declare that the entirety of the work contained therein is my own original work, that I am the sole author thereof (save to the extent explicitly otherwise stated), that reproduction and publication thereof by Stellenbosch University will not infringe any third party rights and that I have not previously in its entirety, or in part, submitted it for obtaining any qualification. Signed – Andrea Palk (March 2018) Copyright © 2018 Stellenbosch University All rights reserved Stellenbosch University https://scholar.sun.ac.za Abstract It has been argued, in the bioethics literature, that traditional forms of moral instruction and development are no longer adequate in equipping humanity to address the urgent nature of the ethical problems facing contemporary societies. Rather than continuing to rely upon these supposedly ineffective methods, we should explore the possibility of biologically enhancing our morality. This would entail both decreasing the likelihood that we would wish to cause harm to others as well as increasing our motivation to do good. The proponents of moral bioenhancement argue that the best way of achieving this would be to isolate which affective dispositions, that are associated with moral traits, are susceptible to biological modification and to biologically enhance these dispositions.
    [Show full text]
  • Autonomy and the Ethics of Biological Behaviour Modification Julian Savulescu, Thomas Douglas, Ingmar Persson
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Autonomy and the Ethics of Biological Behaviour Modification Julian Savulescu, Thomas Douglas, Ingmar Persson [This is a pre-publication version. The final version is available in A Akabayashi (ed) The Future of Bioethics: International Dialogues, Oxford University Press.] Much disease and disability is the result of lifestyle behaviours. For example, the contribution of imprudence in the form of smoking, poor diet, sedentary lifestyle, and drug and alcohol abuse to ill-health is now well established. More importantly, some of the greatest challenges facing humanity as a whole – climate change, terrorism, global poverty, depletion of resources, abuse of children, overpopulation – are the result of human behaviour. In this chapter, we will explore the possibility of using advances in the cognitive sciences to develop strategies to intentionally manipulate human motivation and behaviour. While our arguments apply also to improving prudential motivation and behaviour in relation to health, we will focus on the more controversial instance: the deliberate targeted use of biomedicine to improve moral motivation and behaviour. We do this because the challenge of improving human morality is arguably the most important issue facing humankind (Persson and Savulescu, forthcoming). We will ask whether using the knowledge from the biological and cognitive sciences to influence motivation and behaviour erodes autonomy and, if so, whether this makes it wrong.1 1. COGNITIVE SCIENCE AND BEHAVIOUR MODIFICATION One of the emerging subdisciplines of the cognitive sciences is the cognitive science of motivation and behaviour. Advanced techniques in neuroscience, such as functional magnetic resonance imaging, together with sophisticated pharmacological, psychological and economic experiments have begun to shed light on the subtle neural and psychological bases of motivation and behaviour.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming in Bioethics. Please Cite Final Version 1 Moral Enhancement and Those Left Behind Abstract
    Forthcoming in Bioethics. Please Cite Final Version Moral Enhancement and Those Left Behind Abstract: Opponents to genetic or biomedical human enhancement often claim that the availability of these technologies would have negative consequences for those who either choose not to utilize these resources or lack access to them. However, Thomas Douglas has argued that this objection has no force against the use of technologies that aim to bring about morally desirable character traits, as the unenhanced would benefit from being surrounded by such people. I will argue that things are not as straightforward as Douglas makes out. The widespread use of moral enhancement would raise the standards for praise and blame worthiness, making it much harder for the unenhanced to perform praiseworthy actions or avoid performing blameworthy actions. This shows that supporters of moral enhancement cannot avoid this challenge in the way that Douglas suggests. Introduction Suppose humanity had the potential to use biomedical enhancement techniques to produce human beings with morally improved character traits. What would the moral implications of the availability of this technology be? This question is not one of mere theoretical importance. There are a number of existing drugs that may be capable of doing this job. The neurotransmitter Oxytocin, for example, has been found by Kosfield et al. to increase levels of trust and 1 Forthcoming in Bioethics. Please Cite Final Version cooperation between people.1 Similarly, Terbeck et al. have found that there is evidence to suggest that Propranolol may reduce implicit negative racial bias.2 It is no surprise then, that this question has been the subject of much debate in the recent philosophical literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Hille Haker, Ph.D. Richard Mccormick, S.J., Chair in Moral Theology
    Hille Haker, Ph.D. Loyola University Richard McCormick, S.J., Chair in Moral Theology 1032 W Sheridan Road Loyola University Chicago Chicago, Illinois 60660 Email: [email protected] Phone: ++1 773 508 2368 Fax: ++1 773 508 2386 ................................................................................................................................................................................... 1 UNIVERSITY POSITIONS, EDUCATION, AND EXPERIENCE .................................................................... 3 I. UNIVERSITY POSITIONS ........................................................................................................................................... 3 II. EDUCATION .......................................................................................................................................................... 3 III. ADDITIONAL EXPERIENCE .................................................................................................................................... 4 IV. VISITS ABROAD ................................................................................................................................................. 4 V. TEACHING ........................................................................................................................................................ 4 PROFESSIONAL SERVICES ....................................................................................................................................... 6 I. DISSERTATION COMMITTEES ...................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence As a Means to Moral Enhancement
    STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 48 (61) 2016 DOI: 10.1515/slgr-2016-0061 Michał Klincewicz Jagiellonian University ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE AS A MEANS TO MORAL ENHANCEMENT Abstract. This paper critically assesses the possibility of moral enhance- ment with ambient intelligence technologies and artificial intelligence presented in Savulescu and Maslen (2015). The main problem with their proposal is that it is not robust enough to play a normative role in users’ behavior. A more promising approach, and the one presented in the paper, relies on an artifi- cial moral reasoning engine, which is designed to present its users with moral arguments grounded in first-order normative theories, such as Kantianism or utilitarianism, that reason-responsive people can be persuaded by. This pro- posal can play a normative role and it is also a more promising avenue towards moral enhancement. It is more promising because such a system can be designed to take advantage of the sometimes undue trust that people put in automated technologies. We could therefore expect a well-designed moral reasoner system to be able to persuade people that may not be persuaded by similar arguments from other people. So, all things considered, there is hope in artificial intelli- gence for moral enhancement, but not in artificial intelligence that relies solely on ambient intelligence technologies. Keywords: moral enhancement, artificial intelligence, rhetoric, ambient intelli- gence. 1. The moral lag problem and moral enhancement In a notorious opening section to the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle tells us that only those already brought up well and in possession of the moral virtues can engage in the study of ethics (Nicomachean Ethics 1095b4–6).
    [Show full text]
  • Counterproductive Criminal Rehabilitation: Dealing with the Double-Edged Sword of Moral Bioenhancement Via Cognitive Enhancemen
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Aberdeen University Research Archive Counterproductive criminal rehabilitation: Dealing with the double-edged sword of moral bioenhancement via cognitive enhancement Elizabeth Shaw (This paper is a pre-publication draft of: Shaw, E. Counterproductive Criminal Rehabilitation: Dealing with the Double-Edged Sword of Moral Bioenhancement via Cognitive Enhancement. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry. DOI: 10.1016/j.ijlp.2018.07.006) 1. Introduction Given the high criminal recidivism rate, there is a pressing need to find new approaches to offender rehabilitation (Ministry of Justice, 2013). Recently, there has been increasing academic discussion of using biomedical interventions in rehabilitation programmes (see, e.g. Birks and Douglas, 2018). The discussion of biomedical criminal rehabilitation intersects with the literature on “moral bioenhancement” – the idea that biomedical interventions could be used in order to morally improve individuals' motivations, decision-making and conduct (and to decrease the likelihood of seriously immoral actions, including criminal behaviour). There is a growing consensus among advocates of moral bioenhancement that the most defensible type of moral enhancement would involve enhancing cognitive capacities and enhancing control over one's thought-processes, emotions and behaviour. This article will discuss a potential problem with attempting to use cognitive enhancement to rehabilitate offenders - a problem that, so far, has not been the subject of detailed analysis. Cognitive enhancement is a double-edged sword. The very same cognitive capacities that are required for moral reasoning, and which would be targeted by the envisaged enhancement technologies, are also the capacities that could be used for criminal behaviour.
    [Show full text]
  • Direct Vs. Indirect Moral Enhancement G
    Schaefer • Direct vS. inDirect Moral enhanceMent G. Owen Schaefer Direct vs. Indirect Moral Enhancement ABSTRACT. Moral enhancement is an ostensibly laudable project. Who wouldn’t want people to become more moral? Still, the project’s approach is crucial. We can distinguish between two approaches for moral enhancement: direct and indirect. Direct moral enhancements aim at bringing about particular ideas, motives or behaviors. Indirect moral enhancements, by contrast, aim at making people more reliably produce the morally correct ideas, motives or behaviors without commit- ting to the content of those ideas, motives and/or actions. I will argue, on Millian grounds, that the value of disagreement puts serious pressure on proposals for relatively widespread direct moral enhancement. A more acceptable path would be to focus instead on indirect moral enhancements while staying neutral, for the most part, on a wide range of substantive moral claims. I will outline what such indirect moral enhancement might look like, and why we should expect it to lead to general moral improvement. INTRODUCTION etermining the nature of morality and promoting philosophical ideals of moral behavior have historically been of great concern Damongst philosophers and society as a whole. These concerns have involved not only trying to determine what is good and right but also trying to determine how to ensure that people will in fact be good and do the right thing. While the former has received a great amount of philosophical attention, the latter has—until recently—been somewhat overlooked. The attention that has been given to the question of how to inculcate values has focused on traditional methods such as education, (dis)incentives, and social pressure.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence As a Means to Moral Enhancement
    STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 48 (61) 2016 DOI: 10.1515/slgr-2016-0061 Michał Klincewicz Jagiellonian University ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE AS A MEANS TO MORAL ENHANCEMENT Abstract. This paper critically assesses the possibility of moral enhance- ment with ambient intelligence technologies and artificial intelligence presented in Savulescu and Maslen (2015). The main problem with their proposal is that it is not robust enough to play a normative role in users’ behavior. A more promising approach, and the one presented in the paper, relies on an artifi- cial moral reasoning engine, which is designed to present its users with moral arguments grounded in first-order normative theories, such as Kantianism or utilitarianism, that reason-responsive people can be persuaded by. This pro- posal can play a normative role and it is also a more promising avenue towards moral enhancement. It is more promising because such a system can be designed to take advantage of the sometimes undue trust that people put in automated technologies. We could therefore expect a well-designed moral reasoner system to be able to persuade people that may not be persuaded by similar arguments from other people. So, all things considered, there is hope in artificial intelli- gence for moral enhancement, but not in artificial intelligence that relies solely on ambient intelligence technologies. Keywords: moral enhancement, artificial intelligence, rhetoric, ambient intelli- gence. 1. The moral lag problem and moral enhancement In a notorious opening section to the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle tells us that only those already brought up well and in possession of the moral virtues can engage in the study of ethics (Nicomachean Ethics 1095b4–6).
    [Show full text]
  • CYBORG MIND What Brain–Computer And
    CYBORG MIND What Brain‒Computer and Mind‒Cyberspace Interfaces Mean for Cyberneuroethics CYBORG MIND Edited by Calum MacKellar Offers a valuable contribution to a conversation that promises to only grow in relevance and importance in the years ahead. Matthew James, St Mary’s University, London ith the development of new direct interfaces between the human brain and comput- Wer systems, the time has come for an in-depth ethical examination of the way these neuronal interfaces may support an interaction between the mind and cyberspace. In so doing, this book does not hesitate to blend disciplines including neurobiology, philosophy, anthropology and politics. It also invites society, as a whole, to seek a path in the use of these interfaces enabling humanity to prosper while avoiding the relevant risks. As such, the volume is the fi rst extensive study in cyberneuroethics, a subject matter which is certain to have a signifi cant impact in the twenty-fi rst century and beyond. Calum MacKellar is Director of Research of the Scottish Council on Human Bioethics, Ed- MACKELLAR inburgh, and Visiting Lecturer of Bioethics at St. Mary’s University, London. His past books EDITED BY What include (as co-editor) The Ethics of the New Eugenics (Berghahn Books, 2014). Brain‒Computer and Mind‒Cyberspace Interfaces Mean for Cyberneuroethics MEDICAL ANTHROPOLOGY EDITED BY CALUM MACKELLAR berghahn N E W Y O R K • O X F O R D Cover image by www.berghahnbooks.com Alexey Kuzin © 123RF.COM Cyborg Mind This open access edition has been made available under a CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 license thanks to the support of Knowledge Unlatched.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Enhancement
    Tying oneself to the mast: one necessary cost to morally enhancing oneself biomedically Most of us try, in various ways and to varying degrees of success, to be better people. Over time we have developed a range of tools and techniques of varying efficacy to aid us in these efforts – we might seek the advice of others, make resolutions, read instructive works of fiction and non-fiction, and so on. In recent years, however, bioethicists have become increasingly interested in the idea that one day we might be able to ‘morally enhance’ ourselves through biomedical means. The actual development and manufacture of such ‘biomedical moral enhancements’ (hereafter BMEs) still looks some way off.1 However, even the prospect of such technologies has given rise to a vigorous debate in the philosophical literature on their ethical permissibility and desirability. A review from 2014, for example, found 85 articles published on the subject since 2008.2 Proponents include Tom Douglas, David DeGrazia, Mark Walker, Ingmar Persson and Julian Savulescu. For Douglas, BMEs are moral permissible primarily because there is no good reason for thinking their use is morally objectionable.3 Persson and Savulescu go 1 M. J. Crockett. Moral bioenhancement: a neuroscientific perspective. J Med Ethics. 2014; 40: 370-1; L. Arnhart. Can virtue be genetically engineered? Polit Life Sci. 2010; 29: 79–81. 2 J. Specker, F. Focquaert, K. Raus, S. Sterckx, M. Schermer. The ethical desirability of moral bioenhancement: A review of reasons. 2014. BMC Medical Ethics, 15, 67. 3 T. Douglas. Moral enhancement. J Appl Philos. 2008; 25: 228–245; T.
    [Show full text]
  • On Cognitive and Moral Enhancement: a Reply to Savulescu and Persson
    Carter, J. A. and Gordon, E. C. (2015) On cognitive and moral enhancement: a reply to Savulescu and Persson. Bioethics, 29(3), pp. 153-161. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. This is the peer reviewed version of the following article Carter, J. A. and Gordon, E. C. (2015) On cognitive and moral enhancement: a reply to Savulescu and Persson. Bioethics, 29(3), pp. 153-161, which has been published in final form at http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12076. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/174178/ Deposited on: 27 November 2018 Enlighten – Research publications by members of the University of Glasgow http://eprints.gla.ac.uk Forthcoming in Bioethics On Cognitive and Moral Enhancement: A Reply to Savulescu and Persson J. Adam Carter & Emma C. Gordon Edinburgh University Abstract: In a series of recent works, Julian Savulescu and Ingmar Persson insist that, given the ease by which irreversible destruction is achievable by a morally wicked minority, (i) strictly cognitive bio-enhancement is currently too risky, while (ii) moral bio- enhancement is plausibly morally mandatory (and urgently so). This paper aims to show that the proposal Savulescu & Persson advance relies on several problematic assumptions about the separability of cognitive and moral enhancement as distinct aims. Specifically, we propose that the underpinnings of Savulescu’s & Persson’s normative argument unravel once it is suitably clear how aiming to cognitively enhance an individual will in part require that one aim to bring about certain moral goods we show to be essential to cognitive flourishing; conversely, aiming to bring about moral enhancement in an individual must involve aiming to improve certain cognitive capacities we show to be essential to moral flourishing.
    [Show full text]