Can an Ancient Greek Skeptic Be
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Plato Apology of Socrates and Crito
COLLEGE SERIES OF GREEK AUTHORS EDITED UNDER THE SUPERVISION OF JOHN WILLIAMS WHITE, LEWIS R. PACKARD, a n d THOMAS D. SEYMOUR. PLATO A p o l o g y o f S o c r a t e s AND C r i t o EDITED ON THE BASIS OF CRON’S EDITION BY LOUIS DYER A s s i s t a n t ·Ρι;Οχ'ε&^ο^ ι ν ^University. BOSTON: PUBLISHED BY GINN & COMPANY. 1902. I P ■ C o p · 3 Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1885, by J o h n W il l ia m s W h i t e a n d T h o m a s D. S e y m o u r , In the Office of the Librarian of Congress, at Washington. J . S. C u s h in g & Co., P r i n t e r s , B o s t o n . PREFACE. T his edition of the Apology of Socrates and the Crito is based upon Dr. Christian Cron’s eighth edition, Leipzig, 1882. The Notes and Introduction here given have in the main been con fined within the limits intelligently drawn by Dr. Cron, whose commentaries upon various dialogues of Plato have done and still do so much in Germany to make the study of our author more profitable as well as pleasanter. No scruple has been felt, how ever, in making changes. I trust there are few if any of these which Dr. Cron might not himself make if he were preparing his work for an English-thinking and English-speaking public. -
HISTORIA SCEPTYCYZMU Monografie Fundacji Na Rzecz Nauki Polskiej
HISTORIA SCEPTYCYZMU monografie fundacji na rzecz nauki polskiej rada wydawnicza prof. Tomasz Kizwalter, prof. Janusz Sławiński, prof. Antoni Ziemba, prof. Marek Ziółkowski, prof. Szymon Wróbel fundacja na rzecz nauki polskiej Renata Ziemińska HISTORIA SCEPTYCYZMU W POSZUKIWANIU SPÓJNOŚCI toruń 2013 Wydanie książki subwencjonowane przez Fundację na rzecz Nauki Polskiej w ramach programu Monografie FNP Redaktor tomu Anna Mądry Korekty Ewelina Gajewska Projekt okładki i obwoluty Barbara Kaczmarek Printed in Poland © Copyright by Renata Ziemińska and Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu Mikołaja Kopernika Toruń 2013 ISBN 978-83-231-2949-3 WYDAWNICTWO NAUKOWE UNIWERSYTETU MIKOŁAJA KOPERNIKA Redakcja: ul. Gagarina 5, 87-100 Toruń tel. +48 56 611 42 95, fax +48 56 611 47 05 e-mail: [email protected] Dystrybucja: ul. Reja 25, 87-100 Toruń tel./fax: +48 56 611 42 38, e-mail: [email protected] www.wydawnictwoumk.pl Wydanie pierwsze Druk i oprawa: Abedik Sp. z o.o. ul. Glinki 84, 85-861 Bydgoszcz Spis treści wstęp ......................................................................................................... 9 część i. pojęcie i rodzaje sceptycyzmu rozdział 1. genealogia terminu „sceptycyzm” ........................... 15 rozdział 2. ewolucja pojęcia sceptycyzmu .................................. 21 Starożytny sceptycyzm jako zawieszenie sądów pretendujących do prawdy .......................................................................................... 21 Średniowieczny sceptycyzm jako uznanie słabości ludzkich sądów wobec Bożej wszechmocy -
Olympiodorus the Life of Plato
Olympiodorus The Life of Plato Translated by George Burges in The Works of Plato: a new and literal version (London: Henry G. Bohn, 1865), volume VI, pp. 232-240. Some of the translator’s notes have been omitted and there are some changes to the text to facilitate easier reading. This document is in the public domain. platonic-philosophy.org Come then, let us speak of the family of the philosopher, not for the sake of prolixity, but of benefit rather and instruction to those, who betake themselves to him. For he was not “a Nobody,” but rather— To many of mankind he was a care. For Plato is said to have been a son of his father Ariston, the son of Aristocles, from whom he carried up his family to Solon, the law-giver; and hence he wrote, in imitation of his ancestor, the Laws in twelve books, and a Political Constitution in eleven. He came into the world by his mother Perictione, who was descended from Neleus, the son of Codrus. For they say that Apollo in a vision had an intercourse with his mother Perictione, and, appearing in the night to Ariston, ordered him to have no connexion with Perictione until the time of her bringing forth. And so he acted. And his parents taking him after his birth, and when he was still an infant, placed him on Mount Hymettus, intending to make a sacrifice to the deities there, namely, Pan, and the Nymphs, and Apollo, who presides over shepherds. But while he was lying there, bees came and filled his mouth with honey from the comb, in order that it might be said truly of him— From his mouth flow’d a voice than honey far more sweet. -
Can an Ancient Greek Sceptic Be Eudaimôn (Or Happy)? and What Difference Does the Answer Make to Us?
Journal of Ancient Philosophy Vol. VI 2012 Issue 1 Can an ancient Greek sceptic be eudaimôn (or happy)? And what difference does the answer make to us? Richard Bett (Johns Hopkins University) The paper explores how far the ancient Greek sceptics in fact accept, and how far they should accept, the central Greek ethical notion of eudaimonia , usually translated "happiness" - and what, if anything, the answers may tell us today. The first section shows that sceptics of both the Academic and Pyrrhonist traditions frequently employ the notion of eudaimonia , apparently without discomfort. The second section draws attention to a contrast within the relevant works of Sextus Empiricus - one of them being willing to speak of the sceptic's eudaimonia and the other entirely avoiding this - and considers some possible reasons why, at some point in his life, Sextus might have found the notion problematic. The answers suggested are, first, that the term eudaimonia , at least as normally used by non-sceptical philosophers, presupposes that it is possible to rank human lives objectively in terms of their levels of well-being, and second, that the term standardly carries with it a commitment to a certain kind of long-term structure in one's life; there is at least a serious question whether either of these is consistent with sceptical suspension of judgement. The third section examines how far a sceptic could aspire to happiness , where this is not assumed to be equivalent to eudaimonia , and touches on several modern philosophers who have focused on happiness or, more generally, on well- being. -
SOCRATES and EARLY SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHERS of LAW by R
CHAPTERChapter 2 - SOCRATES 2 35 SOCRATES AND EARLY SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHERS OF LAW by R. F. Stalley and Roderick T. Long1 2.1. The Socratic Movement Socrates is arguably the most important and elusive figure in the history of moral philosophy. The few known facts about his life are easily told. He was an Athenian citizen, born in 469 B.C. and worked as a sculptor. He served his city bravely in the Peloponnesian War, but did not seek an active role in poli- tics. Nevertheless, he was briefly forced into prominence after the battle of Arginusae when, as one of the presidents of the Assembly, he resisted the clamor to try the generals en masse, which he saw as illegal. During the rule of the Thirty Tyrants (404–403 B.C.) he refused an order to take part in arresting Leon of Salamis. After the restoration of democracy, he was put on trial in 399 for introducing strange gods and corrupting the young.2 He refused to save himself by opting for exile or by using any of the devices by which defendants usually sought to arouse the sympathy of Athenian juries. As a result, he was condemned and put to death by poisoning. It is clear that Socrates was an exceptional individual for his intelligence and for his moral character and integrity. He was interested less in questions about the nature of the universe than in what we could call moral questions, above all the question “What sort of life should we lead?” Although he wrote nothing and did not call himself a teacher, he acquired an extensive circle of admirers. -
Agrippa's Trilemma: Scepticism and Contemporary Epistemology
This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights and duplication or sale of all or part is not permitted, except that material may be duplicated by you for research, private study, criticism/review or educational purposes. Electronic or print copies are for your own personal, non- commercial use and shall not be passed to any other individual. No quotation may be published without proper acknowledgement. For any other use, or to quote extensively from the work, permission must be obtained from the copyright holder/s. Agrippa's trilemma: scepticism and contemporary epistemology Aaran Steven Burns PhD Philosophy March 2020 Keele University Word Count: 74970 1 Acknowledgements I must at least try (and fail) to express the deserved amount of gratitude by giving thanks to those who have aided me over the last four years – and perhaps even the last 7. My mother and grandmother have given constant support, particularly over the last year, allowing me to stay with them while finishing things up. My partner, Kathryn Hayward has offered more support than I likely deserved and shown more patience than I could reasonably expect, not to mention the more direct efforts she made in reading drafts of my work. In the early stages of my research I had a number of email exchanges with both Richard Fumerton and Laurence BonJour, who were both immeasurably helpful in helping me to understand these issues more clearly. BonJour in particular has left an almost embarrassingly large mark on my work. Although our email exchange was short, the amount which I gained was vast, and only multiplied from the subsequent reading of his work. -
An Asymmetrical Justification of Deduction: Ending the Sceptical.Debate
AN ASYMMETRICAL JUSTIFICATION OF DEDUCTION: ENDING THE SCEPTICAL.DEBATE by PATRICK EDWARDS BA.(Hon), The University of British Columbia, 2005 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES (Philosophy) THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA April 2007 © Patrick Edwards, 2007 Abstract The purpose of this paper is to explore the possibility of answering the sceptic's demand for a non-dogmatic beliefs. In order to do justice to the sceptic's demand, we will first take time to carefully develop the strongest sceptical position possible. This will be done by considering a selection of sceptical positions dating from ancient Greece, through the early modern period, to the twentieth-century. We will use the law of non-contradiction both to lend structure to this historical taxonomy, and to act as a measure of sceptical rigour. It will be argued that Arcesilaus's scepticism marks the closest approximation of the sceptical ideal, yet, he, too, remains dogmatic to some extent. The twentieth-century discussion will focus on Susan Haack's investigation into the justification of deduction. It will be argued that her treatment of the justifications of deduction and induction as symmetrical is misguided: there is an asymmetry between the two justifications. Next, it will be shown that this asymmetry results from the permissibility of a circular justification of deduction. We will examine the implications of such a circular justification and how they relate to the sceptical debate. Ultimately, it will be shown that the sceptic's demand for justification without dogmatic beliefs is itself dogmatic and circular. -
How Many Wittgensteins?
How many David G. Wittgensteins? Stern 1. Debates in Wittgenstein scholarship The paper maps out and responds to some of the main areas of disagreement over the nature of Wittgenstein’s philosophy: (1) Between defenders of a “two Wittgensteins” reading (which draws a sharp distinction between early and late Wittgenstein) and the opposing “one Wittgenstein” interpretation. (2) Among “two-Wittgensteins” interpreters as to when the later philoso- phy emerged, and over the central difference between early and late Witt- genstein. (3) Between those who hold that Wittgenstein opposes only past philosophy in order to do philosophy better and those who hold that Wittgenstein aimed to bring an end to philosophy and teach us to get by without a replacement. I begin by summarizing and responding to these debates over the nature of Wittgenstein’s philosophy and his philosophical methods. My reply turns on the point that each of these debates depends on some deeply un-Wittgen- steinian, and quite mistaken, assumptions. Why should we have to argue over whether there is “something in common to all that we call” (PI § 65) Wittgenstein’s philosophy (early, late, or all of it)? As there are both continu- ities and discontinuities in Wittgenstein’s thought, we would be better off acknowledging that his writings “are related to one another in many differ- ent ways” (PI § 65) and turning to the more productive task of investigating A. Pichler, S. Säätelä (eds.), Wittgenstein: The Philosopher and his Works, pp. 205–229, Frankfurt a.M.: ontos verlag 2006, © ontos verlag, David G. Stern. |205 those relations in greater detail. -
The Elusive Third Way: the Pyrrhonian Illumination In
The Elusive Third Way: The Pyrrhonian Illumination In Wittgenstein’s On Certainty Roger Eichorn University of Chicago [email protected] Draft: January 3, 2012 ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that, as with the Pyrrhonism of Sextus Empiricus, Wittgenstein’s response to skepticism in On Certainty involves the attempt to free us from philosophy itself and is therefore not a philosophical position, strictly speaking, but is best understood as a therapeutic metaphilosophy designed to bring into view the relationship between our everyday epistemic practices and those of philosophy such that we simultaneously come to recognize (a) the pragmatic-transcendental ‘self-standingness’ of the everyday, and (b) its philosophico–epistemic groundlessness. The result of this ‘illumination’ of the everyday is therapeutic in the sense that it is intended to transform our meta-doxastic attitude by purifying it of dogmatism. KEYWORDS: Wittgenstein; skepticism; Pyrrhonism; Sextus Empiricus; ancient skepticism “The Elusive Third Way” / 2 The difficulty of philosophy not the intellectual difficulty of the sciences, but the difficulty of a change of attitude... Work on philosophy is... actually more of a kind of work on oneself. On one’s own conception. On how one sees things. (And what one demands of them.) – Wittgenstein, “Philosophy” (§86 of The Big Typescript) 1. Introduction Commentators on Wittgenstein all agree that he had something to say about philosophical skepticism. Beyond that, one finds in the literature precious little—if any—common ground regarding Wittgenstein’s attitude toward, or the nature of his response to, skeptical threats to knowledge. In the collection of notes that his literary executors published under the title On Certainty (henceforth: OC), it is clear that Wittgenstein is concerned, at least as a jumping-off point, to address G.E. -
Unmitigated Skepticism: the Nature and Scope of Pyrrhonism
UC San Diego UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Unmitigated Skepticism: The Nature and Scope of Pyrrhonism Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/6fk1n2b1 Author Wong, Andrew David Publication Date 2017 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO Unmitigated Skepticism: The Nature and Scope of Pyrrhonism A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Andrew David Wong Committee in charge: Professor Monte Johnson, Chair Professor Casey Perin, Co-Chair Professor Samuel Rickless Professor Donald Rutherford Professor Edward Watts 2017 © Andrew David Wong, 2017 All rights reserved. The Dissertation of Andrew David Wong is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: Co-Chair Chair University of California, San Diego 2017 iii DEDICATION To my mother and father iv EPIGRAPH By way of preface let us say that on none of the matters to be discussed do we affirm that things certainly are just as we say they are: rather, wereport descriptively on each item according to how it appears to us at the time. Sextus Empiricus v TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page ................................... iii Dedication ..................................... iv Epigraph ...................................... v Table of Contents ................................. viii List of Abbreviations ............................... -
Betwixt a False Reason and None at All ______Pyrrhonian Lessons on Common Sense and Natural Commitments
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to COREyou by provided by Sydney eScholarship Betwixt a false reason and none at all __________________________________________ Pyrrhonian lessons on common sense and natural commitments Shane G. Waugh Doctor of Philosophy Thesis The University of Sydney 2008 Page 1 Acknowledgements 4 Abstract 5 Preface 7 Hume’s insight 7 Preliminary definitions 8 Why we ought to care about commonsensical scepticism? 12 Common Sense Naturalism and dialogue with scepticism 15 Reading Sextus: the apraxia challenge and debate over dogmata 17 Pyrrhonism and common sense: against Broughton 27 i) Sextus’ perception of his reader 28 ii) Sextus’ perception of his own project regarding common sense 34 a) Sextus’ explicit statements on common sense 34 b) Sextus’ account of inquiry 38 iii) The commonsensical response to philosophical theory 42 The Pyrrhonian project 47 Outline of the chapters 50 Chapter 1. Common Sense Naturalism 53 Outline 53 An observation and a distinction 54 Naturalism in CSN 63 i) The nature of naturalism 63 ii) Interlude: an objection concerning reflection 66 Arguments for the naturalism of CSN 68 i) Argument 1: Hume and Reid (and Sextus) on natural justification and default entitlement 70 ii) Argument 2: Wittgenstein and Strawson on transcendental arguments 82 Naturalism and commonsensical commitment in CSN: two views 86 i) Hume and Sextus: common sense as scientific nature 87 ii) Strawson: nature as the presupposition of reason 90 iii) Reid: tensions over nature and common sense 92 a) Outline of the basic points of Reid’s view 92 b) Reid’s primary ‘foundationalist’ view 94 c) Reid’s secondary ‘proto-transcendentalist’ view 97 Nature and common sense: convergence, divergence and debate 103 Summary of CSN and its problems 105 Chapter 2. -
Philotheagrecianoochil PREFACE
MOH fim* 8U* #1M V.! c ^H i. S. G. & E. L. ELBERT ^>c-» f i m IJlT^tulti bv J5LI*A SMIggJ&BgRg, *88 XV KATHARIIOUB^ COMAKT -««.. /" ; PHIL0THEA: 21 ©redan Romance. BY L. MARIA CHILD. AUTHOR OF LETTERS FROM NEW YORK, FLOWERS FOR CHILDREN, ETC. The intelligible forms of ancient poets, Tiie fair humanities of old religion, The Power, the Beauty, and tne Majesty, That had their haunts in dale or piny mountain. Or forest by slow stream, or peDUiy spring, Or chasms and wat'ry depths , all these have vanished— They live no longer in the faith of Reason! But still, the heart doth need a language—still Doth the old instinct bring back the old names. Coleridge. A Spirit hung, Beautiful region ! o'er thy towns and farms, Statues, and temples, and memorial tombs And emanations were perceived. Wordsworth. A NEW AND CORRECTED EDITION. NEW YORK: S. FRANCIS & CO., 252 BROADWAY. boston: J. H. FRANCIS, 128 WASHINGTON STREET 1845. Entered accm-diiif to Act of Congress, in the year 134^. by C. S. FRANCIS &, CO. In the Clerk's Office nf the District Court for the Southern District o<" New-York. printed by Mtjnrob & Francis, Bos t o n. MY BELOVED BROTHER, JBv. JFrancts, OF HARVARD UNIVERSITY, To whose Early Influence I owe my Love of Literature, THIS VOLUME IS RESPECTFULLY AND AFFECTIONATELY INSCRIBED. Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2012 with funding from Boston Library Consortium Member Libraries http://archive.org/details/philotheagrecianOOchil PREFACE. volume is purely romance and most read- This ; ers will consider it romance of the wildest kind.