The Elusive Third Way: the Pyrrhonian Illumination In

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Elusive Third Way: the Pyrrhonian Illumination In The Elusive Third Way: The Pyrrhonian Illumination In Wittgenstein’s On Certainty Roger Eichorn University of Chicago [email protected] Draft: January 3, 2012 ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that, as with the Pyrrhonism of Sextus Empiricus, Wittgenstein’s response to skepticism in On Certainty involves the attempt to free us from philosophy itself and is therefore not a philosophical position, strictly speaking, but is best understood as a therapeutic metaphilosophy designed to bring into view the relationship between our everyday epistemic practices and those of philosophy such that we simultaneously come to recognize (a) the pragmatic-transcendental ‘self-standingness’ of the everyday, and (b) its philosophico–epistemic groundlessness. The result of this ‘illumination’ of the everyday is therapeutic in the sense that it is intended to transform our meta-doxastic attitude by purifying it of dogmatism. KEYWORDS: Wittgenstein; skepticism; Pyrrhonism; Sextus Empiricus; ancient skepticism “The Elusive Third Way” / 2 The difficulty of philosophy not the intellectual difficulty of the sciences, but the difficulty of a change of attitude... Work on philosophy is... actually more of a kind of work on oneself. On one’s own conception. On how one sees things. (And what one demands of them.) – Wittgenstein, “Philosophy” (§86 of The Big Typescript) 1. Introduction Commentators on Wittgenstein all agree that he had something to say about philosophical skepticism. Beyond that, one finds in the literature precious little—if any—common ground regarding Wittgenstein’s attitude toward, or the nature of his response to, skeptical threats to knowledge. In the collection of notes that his literary executors published under the title On Certainty (henceforth: OC), it is clear that Wittgenstein is concerned, at least as a jumping-off point, to address G.E. Moore’s responses to skepticism and idealism in “A Defence of Common Sense”1 and the later “Proof of an External World.”2 Most commentators regard Wittgenstein as hostile to Moore, yet some take him to be largely sympathetic to Moore’s anti-skeptical strategy.3 Even if we grant that Wittgenstein rejects, in some strong sense, Moore’s response to skepticism and idealism, the literature abounds with differing accounts of just what charge Wittgenstein wants to lay at Moore’s feet.4 It isn’t even agreed that Wittgenstein ultimately wants (or that he has the conceptual resources) to confute the philosophical skeptic’s claims.5 In 1 Moore 1925. 2 Moore 1939. 3 Cf., Morawetz 2007, 186: “Wittgenstein is fundamentally in sympathy, as I read him, with Moore’s critique of scepticism.” Anthony Rudd claims, echoing Kripke (Kripke 1982, 63), that “Wittgenstein is often still regarded as a robust ‘common sense realist,’ an implacable opponent of idealism and scepticism—essentially just a subtler version of G. E. Moore” (Rudd 2003, 73). 4 Cf., de Pierris 1996, 188; Conant 1998, 230; Wright 2004, 41; Moyal-Sharrock 2005, 165; Proessel 2005, 345; Stroll 2007, 36; Morawetz 2007, 185; Coliva 2010, 59–60; Pritchard (forthcoming), 3. 5 Cf., Wright 2004, 27; Pritchard 2007, 208; Rudd 2003, 89; Stone 2000, 96–9. “The Elusive Third Way” / 3 other words, although everyone agrees that Wittgenstein had something to say about skepticism, it isn’t clear even whether he opposed skepticism or propounded a form of it himself. According to a common interpretive line, the later Wittgenstein responds to skepticism by (a) rejecting some assumption or set of assumptions shared by both the skeptic and the (traditional) anti-skeptic, and subsequently (b) advocating a third option, one that forges (or at least attempts to forge) a new path through the problem. One encounters ‘third way’ interpretations with such frequency because it’s clearly—or so it seems to me—the right sort of account.6 I don’t think, however, that the details of the account have been satisfactorily worked out. In what follows, I argue that the nature of Wittgenstein’s ‘third way’ comes into sharper focus when seen in relation to the Pyrrhonism of Sextus Empiricus; likewise, important aspects of Pyrrhonism become clearer, at least to contemporary philosophical eyes, when seen in relation to Wittgenstein’s work. In the opening sections of Outlines of Pyrrhonism (henceforth: PH), Sextus presents a taxonomy of philosophers according to which they fall, with respect to any given investigation, into one of three categories: dogmatists, who claim to have discovered the truth; skeptics, who claim that the truth cannot be discovered; and Pyrrhonians, who suspend judgment.7 Generalizing, we can say that a dogmatist will typically claim to know many (perhaps all) truths, skeptics will typically claim that many (perhaps all) truths are inapprehensible, and Pyrrhonians 6 Cf., Philosophical Investigations (henceforth: PI) §352. 7 For ease of exposition, I have modified Sextus’s taxonomy in two important ways. First, the opening sections of PH refer not to dogmatists, skeptics, and Pyrrhonians, but to dogmatists, Academics, and skeptics. By ‘Academics,’ Sextus is referring to the skeptics of Plato’s Academy, the original school of ancient skepticism. The Academics, Sextus says (fairly or not), “have asserted that things cannot be apprehended” (PH §1.3; cf., PH §§1.220–35). The Academics, then, are (at least as Sextus presents them) akin to what modern philosophers think of when they think of ‘skeptics.’ For that reason, I have decided to refer to such ‘negative dogmatists’ as ‘skeptics,’ and to distinguish them from Pyrrhonians, who are not only not skeptics so understood but are opposed to such forms of skepticism. Second, Sextus does not initially distinguish Pyrrhonians from dogmatists and skeptics by saying that the former suspend judgment, but rather by saying that they “are still investigating” (PH §1.4). But (a) Pyrrhonians continue the investigation, if they do, because they suspend judgment, i.e., because for them the question remains open, and therefore (b) their suspension of judgment on the conclusions of philosophical arguments is what sets Pyrrhonians apart from dogmatists and skeptics in Sextus’s taxonomy. “The Elusive Third Way” / 4 will suspend judgment on a broad (perhaps maximally broad) range of philosophical claims and arguments. Both the dogmatist and the skeptic are in the business of promoting acceptance of the conclusions of philosophical arguments. They are mirror images of each other: the skeptic is simply a negative dogmatist. Pyrrhonians, on the other hand, are in the business of promoting suspension of judgment (epochē) regarding the conclusions of philosophical arguments (cf., PH §§3.280–1). The skeptic’s attitude toward skeptical arguments is one of acceptance. The dogmatist, on the other hand, will generally want to refute the skeptic’s arguments by marshalling other philosophical arguments. Unlike both dogmatist and skeptic, however, the Pyrrhonian will, when faced with a skeptical argument, neither accept its conclusion nor claim that the argument can be or has been refuted. In this way, Sextus signals at the outset of PH that Pyrrhonism represents a third way with skepticism (and with philosophy more generally). We’ve already seen that some commentators read the later Wittgenstein as belonging, with Moore, among (traditional) dogmatists. We’ve also seen that others think—or worry that— he belongs instead among (traditional) skeptics.8 As for ‘third way’ interpretations, they come in three basic forms: those that see Wittgenstein as advocating a revised dogmatism; those that see Wittgenstein as advocating a revised skepticism; and those that see Wittgenstein as wanting to reject the framework in which it makes sense to talk in terms of either dogmatism or skepticism (however revised). We’ll look at examples of each in §2. For now, I want to point out that those who advance the third type of ‘third way’ reading have struggled to articulate a principled means of responding to skepticism while also breaking free from the traditional philosophico- conceptual framework in which skepticism has its natural home.9 Call this the principled- 8 Kripke’s interpretation of Wittgenstein’s ‘skeptical paradox’ in Kripke 1982, coupled with widespread dissatisfication with Kripke’s proposed ‘skeptical solution,’ has been especially influential in generating concerns that Wittgenstein falls prey to skepticism. 9 An example should make the outlines of the problem clear. In Mind and World, John McDowell claims to have “The Elusive Third Way” / 5 rejection problem.10 It is my contention that, by viewing Wittgenstein’s ‘third way’ in light of what I take to be Pyrrhonism’s third way, a new and compelling interpretive avenue opens up, one that solves the principled-rejection problem. According to the reading advocated here, Wittgenstein’s response to skepticism is predicated on freeing us from philosophy’s epistemic constraints and so is not strictly speaking a philosophical position at all, but is rather a therapeutic metaphilosophy designed to bring into view—to ‘illuminate’—the relationship between our everyday epistemic practices and those of philosophy such that (a) we come to recognize common life as constituting a self-standing pragmatic-transcendental framework in which we live and move and have our being, while simultaneously (b) coming to recognize the rational groundlessness of that framework, i.e., the fact that it seems to lack the sort of objective or absolute justification (i) that we are naturally inclined to think it must possess, even if we’ve never attempted to secure it, and (ii) that alone is capable of underwriting a dogmatic discovered, with his conception of ‘experience’ as an ‘openness’ to a richly conceptual ‘world,’ a way for us to “achieve an intellectual right to shrug our shoulders at skeptical questions” (McDowell 1994, 143). It is far from clear, however, that he succeeds at dislodging skepticism. As he admits, “[i]t is true that we could not establish that we are open to facts in any given case.
Recommended publications
  • Skepticism and Pluralism Ways of Living a Life Of
    SKEPTICISM AND PLURALISM WAYS OF LIVING A LIFE OF AWARENESS AS RECOMMENDED BY THE ZHUANGZI #±r A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI'I IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY AUGUST 2004 By John Trowbridge Dissertation Committee: Roger T. Ames, Chairperson Tamara Albertini Chung-ying Cheng James E. Tiles David R. McCraw © Copyright 2004 by John Trowbridge iii Dedicated to my wife, Jill iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing this research, I would like to express my appreciation first and foremost to my wife, Jill, and our three children, James, Holly, and Henry for their support during this process. I would also like to express my gratitude to my entire dissertation committee for their insight and understanding ofthe topics at hand. Studying under Roger Ames has been a transformative experience. In particular, his commitment to taking the Chinese tradition on its own terms and avoiding the tendency among Western interpreters to overwrite traditional Chinese thought with the preoccupations ofWestern philosophy has enabled me to broaden my conception ofphilosophy itself. Roger's seminars on Confucianism and Daoism, and especially a seminar on writing a philosophical translation ofthe Zhongyong r:pJm (Achieving Equilibrium in the Everyday), have greatly influenced my own initial attempts to translate and interpret the seminal philosophical texts ofancient China. Tamara Albertini's expertise in ancient Greek philosophy was indispensable to this project, and a seminar I audited with her, comparing early Greek and ancient Chinese philosophy, was part ofthe inspiration for my choice ofresearch topic. I particularly valued the opportunity to study Daoism and the Yijing ~*~ with Chung-ying Cheng g\Gr:p~ and benefited greatly from his theory ofonto-cosmology as a means of understanding classical Chinese philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: the Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin
    Cornell Law Review Volume 75 Article 2 Issue 4 May 1990 Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory Robert Justin Lipkin Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Robert Justin Lipkin, Beyond Skepticism Foundationalism and the New Fuzziness: The Role of Wide Reflective Equilibrium in Legal Theory , 75 Cornell L. Rev. 810 (1990) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol75/iss4/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEYOND SKEPTICISM, FOUNDATIONALISM AND THE NEW FUZZINESS: THE ROLE OF WIDE REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM IN LEGAL THEORY Robert Justin Liphint TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION .............................................. 812 I. FOUNDATIONALISM AND SKEPTICISM ..................... 816 A. The Problem of Skepticism ........................ 816 B. Skepticism and Nihilism ........................... 819 1. Theoretical and PracticalSkepticism ................ 820 2. Subjectivism and Relativism ....................... 821 3. Epistemic and Conceptual Skepticism ................ 821 4. Radical Skepticism ............................... 822 C. Modified Skepticism ............................... 824 II. NEW FOUNDATIONALISM
    [Show full text]
  • Testimony Using the Term “Reasonable Scientific Certainty”
    NATIONAL COMMISSION ON FORENSIC SCIENCE Testimony Using the Term “Reasonable Scientific Certainty” Subcommittee Reporting and Testimony Type of Work Product Views Document Statement of the Issue It is the view of the National Commission on Forensic Science (NCFS) that legal professionals should not require that forensic discipline testimony be admitted conditioned upon the expert witness testifying that a conclusion is held to a “reasonable scientific certainty,” a “reasonable degree of scientific certainty,” or a “reasonable degree of [discipline] certainty.” The legal community should recognize that medical professionals and other scientists do not routinely use “to a reasonable scientific certainty” when expressing conclusions outside of the courts. Such terms have no scientific meaning and may mislead factfinders [jurors or judges] when deciding whether guilt has been proved beyond a reasonable doubt. Forensic science service providers should not endorse or promote the use of this terminology. The Commission recognizes the right of each jurisdiction to determine admissibility standards but expresses this view as part of its mandate to “develop proposed guidance concerning the intersection of forensic science and the courtroom.” Forensics experts are often required to testify that the opinions or facts stated are offered “to a reasonable scientific certainty” or to a “reasonable degree of [discipline] certainty.” Outside of the courts, this phrasing is not routinely used in scientific disciplines, a point acknowledged in the Daubert decision (“it would be unreasonable to conclude that the subject of scientific testimony must be ‘known’ to a certainty; arguably, there are no certainties in science.”). Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharms., 509 U.S. 579, 590 (1993).
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Critique of Ancient Skepticism
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy Summer 8-1-2012 Hegel's Critique of Ancient Skepticism John Wood Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Wood, John, "Hegel's Critique of Ancient Skepticism." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2012. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/113 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HEGEL’S CRITIQUE OF ANCIENT SKEPTICISM by JAY WOOD Under the Direction of Dr. Sebastian Rand ABSTRACT Recent work on the philosophy of G.W.F. Hegel has emphasized his interest in skeptical concerns. These contemporary scholars argue that, despite common opinions to the contrary, Hegel actually had a very keen interest in skepticism, one that informed and motivated much of his overall project. While I welcome this recent literature, I argue here that contemporary scholars have overemphasized the importance of skepticism for Hegel. By looking closely at Hegel’s arguments against skepticism in the Phenomenology of Spirit, I argue that Hegel’s anti-skeptical arguments are in fact major failures. Hegel’s failure is at odds with the emphasis that contemporary literature places on Hegel’s interests in skepticism. For a philosopher who was supposedly centrally concerned with skeptical issues, Hegel sure does not act like it. I conclude that the tension here is the result of contemporary scholars’ overemphasis of the role that skepticism plays in Hegel’s project.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of the Criterion
    Chapter 5 The Problem of the Criterion i "The problem of the criterion" seems to me to be one of the most important and one of the most difficult of all the problems of phi- losophy. I am tempted to say that one has not begun to philosophize until one has faced this problem and has recognized how unappealing, in the end, each of the possible solutions is. I have chosen this problem as my topic for the Aquinas Lecture because what first set me to thinking about it (and I remain obsessed by it) were two treatises of twentieth century scholastic philosophy. I refer first to P. Coffey's two-volume work, Epistemology or the Theory of Knowledge, pub- lished in 1917.1 This led me in turn to the treatises of Coffey's great teacher, Cardinal D. J. Merrier: Criteriologie generale ou theorie gen- erate de la certitude.2 Mercier and, following him, Coffey set the problem correctly, I think, and have seen what is necessary for its solution. But I shall not discuss their views in detail. I shall formulate the problem; then note what, according to Mercier, is necessary if we are to solve the prob- lem; then sketch my own solution; and, finally, note the limitations of my approach to the problem. What is the problem, then? It is the ancient problem of "the dial- lelus"—the problem of "the wheel" or "the vicious circle." It was 61 62 • PROBLEM OF THE CRITERION put very neatly by Montaigne in his Essays. So let us being by para- paraphrasing his formulation of the puzzle.
    [Show full text]
  • Al-Ghazali and Descartes from Doubt to Certainty: a Phenomenological Approach
    AL-GHAZALI AND DESCARTES FROM DOUBT TO CERTAINTY: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL APPROACH Mohammad Alwahaib Abstract: This paper clarifies the philosophical connection between Al-Ghazali and Descartes, with the goal to articulate similarities and differences in their famous journeys from doubt to certainty. As such, its primary focus is on the chain of their reasoning, starting from their conceptions of truth and doubt arguments, until their arrival at truth. Both philosophers agreed on the ambiguous character of ordinary everyday knowledge and decided to set forth in undermining its foundations. As such, most scholars tend to agree that the doubt arguments used by Descartes and Al-Ghazali are similar, but identify their departures from doubt as radically different: while Descartes found his way out of doubt through the cogito and so reason, Al-Ghazali ended his philosophical journey as a Sufi in a sheer state of passivity, waiting for the truth to be revealed to him by God. This paper proves this is not the case. Under close textual scrutiny and through the use of basic Husserlian-phenomenological concepts, I show that Al-Ghazali's position was misunderstood, thus disclosing his true philosophic nature. I. Introduction This paper clarifies the philosophical relation between Al-Ghazali, a Muslim philosopher (1058--1111), and the French philosopher Rene Descartes (1596--1650), with the objective of articulating the similarities and differences in their famous journeys from doubt to certainty. Historical evidence on whether Descartes did in fact read or had knowledge of Al-Ghazali’s work will not be discussed in this paper. Instead, this paper focuses primarily on the chain of their reasoning, starting from their conceptions of truth and the arguments used by each to destroy or deconstruct the pillars of our knowledge and thus reach truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Scepticism: the Cartesian Approach Luciano Floridi
    Mathematical Scepticism: the Cartesian Approach1 Luciano Floridi Wolfson College, Oxford, OX2 6UD, UK [email protected] - www.wolfson.ox.ac.uk/~floridi Introduction Paris, 15 February 1665: Molière’s Don Juan is first performed in the Palais-Royal Hall. Third Act, First Scene: the most daring of Don Juan’s intellectual adventures takes place. In a dialogue with his servant Sganarelle, Don Juan makes explicit his atheist philosophy: SGANARELLE. I want to get to the bottom of what you really think. Is it possible that you don’t believe in Heaven at all? D. JUAN. Let that question alone. SGANARELLE. That means you don’t. And Hell? D. JUAN. Enough. SGANARELLE. Ditto. What about the devil then? D. JUAN. Oh, of course. SGANARELLE. As little. Do you believe in an after life? D. JUAN. Ha! ha! ha! SGANARELLE. Here is a man I shall have a job to convert. […] SGANARELLE. But everybody must believe in something. What do you believe in? D. JUAN. What do I believe? SGANARELLE. Yes. D. JUAN. I believe that two and two make four, Sganarelle, and four and four make eight. SGANARELLE. That’s a fine thing to believe! What fine article of faith! Your religion is then nothing but arithmetic. Some people do have queer ideas in their heads, and those that have been educated are often the silliest. I never studied, thank God, and no one can boast he taught me anything. But, to my poor way of thinking, my eyes are better than books. I know very well that this world we see around us is not a mushroom grown up in a single night.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Moderate Invariantism
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research Philosophy, Department of July 2008 A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM Leo W. Iacono University of Nebraska at Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosophydiss Part of the Philosophy Commons Iacono, Leo W., "A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM" (2008). Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research. 1. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/philosophydiss/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Dissertations, Theses, & Student Research by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM by Leo Iacono A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of The Graduate College at the University of Nebraska In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Major: Philosophy Under the Supervision of Professor Albert Casullo Lincoln, Nebraska August, 2008 A DEFENSE OF MODERATE INVARIANTISM Leo Iacono, Ph.D. University of Nebraska, 2008 Adviser: Albert Casullo This dissertation is a defense of moderate invariantism, the traditional epistemological position combining the following three theses: invariantism, according to which the word ‘know’ expresses the same content in every context of use; intellectualism, according to which whether one knows a certain proposition does not depend on one’s practical interests; and anti- skepticism, according to which we really do know much of what we ordinarily take ourselves to know. Moderate invariantism needs defending because of seemingly powerful arguments for contextualism, the view that, like ‘I’ and ‘now’, ‘know’ expresses different contents in different contexts.
    [Show full text]
  • Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy
    Moonshadows This page intentionally left blank Moonshadows Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy T HE C OWHERDS 2011 Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further Oxford University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education. Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offi ces in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Copyright © 2011 by Oxford University Press, Inc. Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 www.oup.com Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Cowherds (Authors) Moonshadows : conventional truth in Buddhist philosophy / the Cowherds. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-19-975142-6; ISBN 978-0-19-975143-3 (pbk.) 1. Truth—Religious aspects—Buddhism. 2. Buddhist philosophy. I. Title. BQ4255.C69 2011 121.088′2943—dc22 2009050158 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper Preface This is an unusual volume. It is neither an anthology nor a monograph. We prefer to think of it as a polygraph— a collectively written volume refl ecting the varying views of a large collection of authors.
    [Show full text]
  • On Certainty (Uber Gewissheit) Ed
    Ludwig Wittgenstein On Certainty (Uber Gewissheit) ed. G.E.M.Anscombe and G.H.von Wright Translated by Denis Paul and G.E.M.Anscombe Basil Blackwell, Oxford 1969-1975 Preface What we publish here belongs to the last year and a half of Wittgenstein's life. In the middle of 1949 he visited the United States at the invitation of Norman Malcolm, staying at Malcolm's house in Ithaca. Malcolm acted as a goad to his interest in Moore's 'defence of common sense', that is to say his claim to know a number of propositions for sure, such as "Here is one hand, and here is another", and "The earth existed for a long time before my birth", and "I have never been far from the earth's surface". The first of these comes in Moore's 'Proof of the External World'. The two others are in his 'Defence of Common Sense'; Wittgenstein had long been interested in these and had said to Moore that this was his best article. Moore had agreed. This book contains the whole of what Wittgenstein wrote on this topic from that time until his death. It is all first-draft material, which he did not live to excerpt and polish. The material falls into four parts; we have shown the divisions at #65, #192, #299. What we believe to be the first part was written on twenty loose sheets of lined foolscap, undated. These Wittgenstein left in his room in G.E.M.Anscombe's house in Oxford, where he lived (apart from a visit to Norway in the autumn) from April 1950 to February 1951.
    [Show full text]
  • Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy. Volume 31, Winter 2006
    LIVING IN DOUBT: CARNEADES’ PITHANON RECONSIDERED SUZANNE OBDRZALEK I though the interpretation of ancient texts is inevitably di¶cult, Carneades presents what one might call a worst-case scenario. In the first place, he wrote nothing. To complicate matters, Carneades’ views were so obscure that his faithful disciple Clitomachus con- fessed that he could never figure out what Carneades actually be- lieved (Cic. Acad. 2. 139). Showing remarkable fortitude in the face of such an obstacle, Clitomachus, attempting to play Plato to Carneades’ Socrates, reportedly recorded Carneades’ teachings in 400 books (D.L. 4. 67). Not one remains. None the less, Clito- machus’ attempt to make a philosophy of Carneades’ anti-theoreti- cal stance was not a complete failure; Carneades had a tremendous influence on the later Academy as well as the Stoa, and his views (or lack thereof) have been handed down to us by both Sextus Em- piricus and Cicero. These sources are, however, problematic. As a Pyrrhonist, Sextus was critical of the Academy and may have ex- aggerated what he took to be Carneades’ dogmatism. Cicero, on the other hand, a student of Philo, was undoubtedly influenced in his interpretation of Carneades by his teacher’s dogmatic scepti- cism. Carneades is perhaps best known for proposing the pithan»e phantasia (probable impression) as a criterion for life. However, the status of his theory of the pithanon (probable) is completely unclear.1 Was it merely a dialectical move against the Stoic charge of apraxia (inaction)? Was it a theory that Carneades himself en- ã Suzanne Obdrzalek 2006 I would like to thank Alan Code, Tony Long, Julius Moravcsik, and David Sedley for their comments on this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Against the Logicians Edited by Richard Bett Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 0521531950 - Sextus Empiricus: Against the Logicians Edited by Richard Bett Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY SEXTUS EMPIRICUS Against the Logicians © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521531950 - Sextus Empiricus: Against the Logicians Edited by Richard Bett Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY Series editors KARL AMERIKS Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame DESMOND M. CLARKE Professor of Philosophy at University College Cork The main objective of Cambridge Textsin the History of Philosophy is to expand the range, variety and quality of texts in the history of philosophy which are available in English. The series includes texts by familiar names (such as Descartes and Kant) and also by less well-known authors. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each volume contains a critical introduction together with a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and textual apparatus. The volumes are designed for student use at undergraduate and postgraduate level and will be of interest not only to students of philosophy, but also to a wider audience of readers in the history of science, the history of theology and the history of ideas. For a list of titles published in the series, please see end of book. © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521531950
    [Show full text]