NOTES on CONTRIBUTORS REGINALD E. ALLEN Is Professor

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

NOTES on CONTRIBUTORS REGINALD E. ALLEN Is Professor NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS REGINALD E. ALLEN is Professor of Philosophy at the Univer­ sity of Toronto. M. F. BURNYEAT is Lecturer in Philosophy, University Col­ lege, London. S. MARC COHEN is Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Rutgers University. KENNETH J. DOVER is Professor of Greek in the University of St. Andrews. A. R. LACEY is Lecturer in Philosophy, Bedford College, Uni­ versity of London. GEORGE NAKHNIKIAN is Professor and Chairman of the Depart­ ment of Philosophy, Indiana University. RICHARD ROBINSON was formerly Associate Professor of Philos­ ophy at Cornell University. He was a Tutor of Oriel Col­ lege and a University Lecturer at Oxford University from 1946 to 1969, and has been a Fellow of Oriel College from 1946 to the present. GERASIMOS SANTAS is Professor of Philosophy, University of California at Irvine. JAMES J. WALSH is Professor and Chairman of the Depart­ ment of Philosophy, Columbia University. A. D. WOOZLEY, formerly Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of St. Andrews, is now Professor of Philosophy in the Corcoran Department of Philosophy, University of Virginia. He has served as editor of the Philosophical Quarterly. GREGORY VLASTOS is Stuart Professor of Philosophy at Prince­ ton University. He had previously taught philosophy at Queen's University in Kingston, Ontario, and at Cornell University. SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY OF BOOKS AND ARTICLES IN ENGLISH ON SOCRATES' PHILOSOPHY I. BOOKS AND ARTICLES BY CONTRIBUTORS TO TBIS VOLUME Allen, R. E., The Euthyphro and Plato's Earlier Theory of Forms (London, 1970). --, "The Socratic Paradox," ]ourTUll of the History of Ideas 21 ( 1960), 256-65. Robinson, Richard, Plato's Earlier Dialectic, Second Edition (Ox­ ford, 1953). Santas, Gerasimos, "The Socratic Paradoxes," Philosophical Review 73 (1964), 147-64. Vlastos, Gregory, Plato's Protagoras, B. Jowett's translation re­ vised by M. Ostwald, edited with Introduction by G. Vlastos (New York, 1956), xxiv-lvi. --, "Socratic Knowledge and Platonic 'Pessimism'," Philosophi­ cal Review 66 ( 1957),226-38, at 226-32. --, "Was Polus Refuted?" American ]ourTUll of Philology 88 ( 1967), 454-60. --, "Socrates on Acrasia," Phoenix 23 (1969), 71-88. II. BOOKS BY OTBER AUTBORS (a) Commentaries or Translations with Notes of Philosophical In­ terest On the Apology: Riddell, J., The Apology of Plato (Oxford, 1865). On the Apology, Crito, and Euthyphro: Burnet, J., Plato's Eu­ thyphro, Apology of Socrates, and Cr#o (Oxford, 1924). On the Charmides: Tuckey, T. G., Plato's "Charmides" (Cam­ bridge, 1951). On the Euthydemus: Sprague, Rosamond K., Plato: Euthydemus (New York, 1965). On the Gorgias: Thompson, W. H., The Gorgias of Plato (Lon­ don, 1871). ---, Dodds, E. R., Plato: Gorgias (Oxford, 1959). On the Protagoras: Guthrie, W. K. C., Plato's Protagoras and Meno (London, 1956). (b) Books Adkins, A. W. H., Merit and Responsibility: A Study in Greek Values ( Oxford, 1960), Chapter 13, "Plato; Logic and Elenchus." Selected Bibliography 337 Barker, E., Greek Political Theory (London, 1918), Chapter 5, "Socrates and the Minor Socratics." Chroust, A. H., Socrates, Man and Myth (London, 1957). Cornford, F. M., Before and After Socrates (Cambridge, 1932). Crombie, I. M., An Examination of Plato's Doctrines, Vol. I: Plato on Man and Society (London, 1962),204-45. Field, G. C., Plato and his Contemporaries (London, 1930), Chap­ ters 10 and 11 on "The Socratic Literature," and 12 on "The Socratic Philosophers." Friedlander, P., Plato, Vol. II: The Dialogues, First Period, English translation by H. Meyerhoff (New York, 1964). Grote, G., Plato and the Other Companions of Socrates (London, 1888), discussion of the earlier dialogues in Vols. I and II. Gould, J., The Development of Plato's Ethics (Cambridge, 1955), Part One, "The Personal Ideal" (Socrates' moral philosophy and character). Gulley, N., The Philosophy of Socrates (London, 1968). Guthrie, W. K. C., History of Greek Philosophy, Vol. III: The Fifth-Century Enlightenment (Cambridge, 1969). Hackforth, R, The Composition of Plato's Apology (Cambridge, 1933 ). Huby, Pamela, Greek Ethics (London, 1967), Chapter 3, "Soc­ rates." Jaeger, W., Paideia, II, translation by G. Highet (Oxford, 1941). Levinson, R B., In Defense of Plato (Cambridge, Mass., 1953), on Socrates, 233-307 et passim. North, Helen, Sophrosyne (Ithaca, N.Y., 1966), 155-65, on the Socratic conception. O'Brien, M. J., The Socratic Paradoxes and the Greek Mind (Chapel Hill, 1967). Owens, J., A History of Ancient Western Philosophy (New York, 1959), 165-75, on Socrates. Popper, Karl, The Open Society and its Enemies, Fourth Edition (Princeton, 1962), on Socrates, 189-201 et passim. Shorey, P., What Plato Said (Chicago, 1933), on Socrates, 74-155 et passim. Sinclair, T. A., A History of Greek Political Thought (London, 1951), Chapter 5, "Socrates and his Opponents." Sprague, Rosamond, Plato's Use of Fallacy (London, 1962), Chap- ters 1 and 4, on the Euthydemus and the Hippias Minor. Strauss, L., Socrates and Aristophanes (New York, 1966). Taylor, A. E., Varia Socratica (Oxford, 1911). --, Plato, the Man and his Work (London, 1926), Chapters 3 to 7 on "Socratic Dialogues" and Chapter 10 on "Protagoras." --, Socrates (London, 1932). _ Versenyi, L., Socratic Humanism (New Haven, 1963). Winspear, A. D. and Silverberg, T., Wha Was Socrates? (New York,1939). 338 Selected Bibliography ( c) Articles and Essays Anderson, A., "Socratic Reasoning in the Euthyphro," Review of Metaphysics 22 (1969),461--81. Bambrough, J., "The Socratic Paradox," Philosophical Quarterly 10 (1960), 229-300. Brown, J. H., "The Logic in Euthyphro lOA-11B," Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1964), 1-14. Burnet, J., "The Socratic Doctrine of the Soul," Proc. of the British Academy 7 (1915-16). Reprinted in Essays and Addresses (London, 1929). Clapp, J. G., "Some Notes on Plato's Protagoras," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 10 (1949-50), 486-gg. Ehnmark, E., "Socrates and the Immortality of the Soul," Eranos 44 (1946), 105-22. Ferguson, A. S., "The Impiety of Socrates," Classical Quarterly 7 (1913), 157-75· Fox, M., "The Trials of Socrates," Archiv fUr Philosophie 6 (1956), 226ff. Gallop, G., "Justice and Holiness in Prot. 330-331," Phronesis 6 ( 1961 ), 86--93. --, "The Socratic Paradox in the Protagoras," Phronesis 9 (1964),117-29. Gauthier, David P., "The Unity of Wisdom and Temperance" (Critique of D. Savan, "Socrates' Logic and the Unity of Wisdom and Temperance"), Journal of the History of Philoso­ phy 6 (1968), 157-59. Geach, P., "Plato's Euthyphro: An Analysis and Commentary," Monist 50 (1966), 36g-82. Gordon, R. M., "Socratic Definitions and Moral Neutrality," Journal of Philosophy 61 (1964), 433-50. Gould, Th., "Socrates as an Existentialist," Arion 3 (1964), 112- 15· Greenberg, N. A., "Socrates' Choice in the Crito," Harvard Studies in Classic Philosophy 70 (1965), 45--82. Grube, G., "The Structural Unity of the Protagoras," Classical Quarterly 27 (1933),203-7. Gulley, N., "The Interpretation of 'No one does wrong willingly' in Plato's Dialogues," Phronesis 10 (1965), 82-96. Hackforth, R., "Socrates," Philosophy 11 (1933),259-72. --, "Hedonism in Plato's Protagoras," Classical Quarterly 22 (1928), 39 ff. Hall, J. C., "Plato: Euth. lOA1-11AlO," Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1968), 1-11. Havelock, E., "The Evidence for the Teaching of Socrates," Trans. of the American Philological Association 65 (1934), 282-95. --, "Why was Socrates tried?" Phoenix Supplement 1 (Studies in honor of Gilbert Norwood), 1952, 95-108. Selected Bibliography 339 Hoerber, R. G., "Plato's Euthyphro," "Plato's Lysis," "Plato's Lesser Hippias," "Plato's Greater Hippias," Phronesis 3 (1958 ), 95 H.; 4 (1959), ISH.; 7 (1962), 121 H.; 9 (1964), 143 H. Jackson, H., "Socrates," Encyclopaedia Britannica, Eleventh Edi­ tion, Vol. XXIX (London, 1911), 331-38. Kidd, I. G., "Socrates," Encyclopedia C1f Philosophy, Vol. IX (New York, 1967),480-86. Laguna, Th. de, "The Interpretation of the Apology," Philosophi­ cal Review 18 (1909),23-27. Mulhern, J. J., "Tropos and polytropia in Plato's Hippias Minor," Phoenix 22 (1968), 283-88. O'Brien, M. J., "The 'Fallacy' in Prot. 349D-350C," Trans. of the American Philological Association 92 ( 1961 ), 408-17. Savan, D., "Self-predication in Protagoras 33~31," Phronesis 9 (1964), 13~35· --, "Socrates' Logic and the Unity of Wisdom and Temper­ ance," in R. J. Butler, ed., Analytical Philosophy, Vol. II (Oxford, 1965), 2~26. Sparshott, F. E., "Socrates and Thrasymachus," Monist 50 (1966), 421-59. Stocks, J. L., "The Argument of Plato, Prot. 351A-356C," Classical Quarterly 7 (1913), 100H. Strycker, E. de, "The Unity of Knowledge and Love in Socrates' Conception of Virtue," International Philosophical Quarterly 6 (1966),428-44. Sullivan, J. P., "The Hedonism in Plato's Protagoras," Phronesis 6 (1961), g-28. Vogel, C. de, "Who was Socrates?" Journal C1f the History C1f Phi­ losophy 1 (1963),143-61, Woodbury, L., "Simonides on Arete," Trans. C1f the American Philological Association 84 (1953), 135-63. INDEX LOCORUM (Passages in Aristophanes, Aristotle, Plato and Xenophon) AUTHOR AND TITLE Page Aristophanes Birds 60 3-5 29 Birds 688ff. 74 Birds 90 4 ff. 73 Birds 959 ff. 73 Birds 1009 54 Birds 1281 £. 70 Birds 1554 53 Birds 1564 53 Clouds 45 62 Clouds 71 ff. 62 Clouds 95ff. 52,53, 55 Clouds 98 52 Clouds 103 51 Clouds 104 51 Clouds 119£. 51 Clouds 137 28,61 Clouds 140 ff. 52 Clouds 144ff. 52 Clouds 148 ff. 58 Clouds 156ff. 52 Clouds 171 £. 52 Clouds 175 51, 52 Clouds 175 ff. 26 Clouds 177£. 52 Clouds 179 52 Clouds 179 52 Clouds 188 ff. 52 Clouds 193£. 52 Clouds 198£. 51 Clouds 201 52 Clouds 202 £. 52 Clouds 206 ff. 52 Clouds 225 ff. 52 Clouds 227 ff. 53 Clouds 245£. 52 Clouds 247 £. 53 Clouds 250 ff. 52 Clouds 254 ff. 53 Index Locorum 341 Aristophanes (cont'd) Clouds 314 ff. 52 Clouds 316 52 Clouds 331 ff. 59,73 Clouds 334 52 Clouds 340 ff. 52 Clouds 342 ff.
Recommended publications
  • Agorapicbk-17.Pdf
    Excavations of the Athenian Agora Picture Book No. 17 Prepared by Mabel L. Lang Dedicated to Eugene Vanderpool o American School of Classical Studies at Athens ISBN 87661-617-1 Produced by the Meriden Gravure Company Meriden, Connecticut COVER: Bone figure of Socrates TITLE PAGE: Hemlock SOCRATES IN THE AGORA AMERICAN SCHOOL OF CLASSICAL STUDIES AT ATHENS PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY 1978 ‘Everything combines to make our knowledge of Socrates himself a subject of Socratic irony. The only thing we know definitely about him is that we know nothing.’ -L. Brunschvicg As FAR AS we know Socrates himselfwrote nothing, yet not only were his life and words given dramatic attention in his own time in the Clouds of Ar- istophanes, but they have also become the subject of many others’ writing in the centuries since his death. Fourth-century B.C. writers who had first-hand knowledge of him composed either dialogues in which he was the dominant figure (Plato and Aeschines) or memories of his teaching and activities (Xe- nophon). Later authors down even to the present day have written numerous biographies based on these early sources and considering this most protean of philosophers from every possible point of view except perhaps the topograph- ical one which is attempted here. Instead of putting Socrates in the context of 5th-century B.C. philosophy, politics, ethics or rhetoric, we shall look to find him in the material world and physical surroundings of his favorite stamping- grounds, the Athenian Agora. Just as ‘agora’ in its original sense meant ‘gathering place’ but came in time to mean ‘market place’, so the agora itself was originally a gathering place I.
    [Show full text]
  • The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1946 The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates David J. Bowman Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Bowman, David J., "The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates" (1946). Master's Theses. 61. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/61 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1946 David J. Bowman !HE HISTORICITY OP PLATO'S APOLOGY OF SOCRATES BY DA.VID J. BOWJWf~ S.J• .l. !BESIS SUBMITTED Ilf PARTIAL FULFILIJIE.NT OF THB: R}gQUIRE'IIENTS POR THE DEGREE OF IIA.STER OF ARTS Ill LOYOLA UlfiVERSITY JULY 1946 -VI'fA. David J. Bowman; S.J•• was born in Oak Park, Ill1no1a, on Ma7 20, 1919. Atter b!a eleaentar7 education at Ascension School# in Oak Park, he attended LoJola AcademJ ot Chicago, graduat1DS .from. there in June, 1937. On September 1, 1937# he entered the Sacred Heart Novitiate ot the SocietJ ot Jesus at Milford~ Ohio. Por the tour Jear• he spent there, he was aoademicallJ connected with Xavier Univeraitr, Cincinnati, Ohio. In August ot 1941 he tranaterred to West Baden College o.f Lorol& Universit7, Obicago, and received the degree ot Bachelor o.f Arts with a major in Greek in Deo.aber, 1941.
    [Show full text]
  • The Prosecutors of Socrates and the Political Motive Theory
    Portland State University PDXScholar Dissertations and Theses Dissertations and Theses 2-1981 The prosecutors of Socrates and the political motive theory Thomas Patrick Kelly Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/open_access_etds Part of the Intellectual History Commons, and the Political History Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Kelly, Thomas Patrick, "The prosecutors of Socrates and the political motive theory" (1981). Dissertations and Theses. Paper 2692. https://doi.org/10.15760/etd.2689 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF Thomas Patrick Kelly for the Master of Arts in History presented February 26, 1981. Title: The Prosecutors of Socrates and The Political Motive Theory. APPROVED BY MEMBERS OF THE THESIS CO~rnITTEE: ~~varnos, Cha1rman Charles A. Le Guin Roderlc D1man This thesis presents a critical analysis of the histor- ical roles assigned to the prosecutors of Socrates by modern historians. Ancient sources relating to the trial and the principles involved, and modern renditions, especially those of John Burnet and A. E. Taylor, originators of the theory that the trial of Socrates was politically motivated, are critically 2 analyzed and examined. The thesis concludes that the political motive theory is not supported by the evidence on which it relies. THE PROSECUTORS OF SOCRATES AND THE POLITICAL MOTIVE THEORY by THOMAS PATRICK KELLY A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in HISTORY Portland State University 1981 TO THE OFFICE OF GRADUATE STUDIES AND RESEARCH: The members of the Committee approve the thesis of Thomas Patrick Kelly presented February 26, 1981.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and Xenophon on the Different Reasons That Socrates Always Obeys the Law
    Plato and Xenophon on the Different Reasons that Socrates Always Obeys the Law Louis-André Dorion Plato and Xenophon agree that Socrates always obeys the law. In the Crito and the Memorabilia (4.4 and 4.6), we see that they also agree that Socrates gives reasons for his obedience to the law. Despite this common ground, Plato and Xenophon disagree about the reasons that justify obedience to the law, as can be shown by a comparative analysis of Plato and Xenophon on the important Socratic theme of obedience to the law. I intend to show, as I have done for other Socratic positions shared by Plato and Xenophon, that the Crito and the Memorabilia provide different reasons for holding the same Socratic position on obedience to the law. Although Plato’s Crito has been the subject of numer- ous studies and greater attention is now being paid to Xenophon’s Memorabilia 4.4,1 it appears that no one has yet attempted a comparative analysis of these two texts. However, I will not provide a new interpretation of the Crito. My aim is to compare the Memorabilia with the Crito in order to highlight what is unique to the argument of the Memorabilia and, consequently, to the argu- ment of the Crito as well. I will limit myself to the most noteworthy differences. The Context of the Discussion It is probably not a coincidence that Plato and Xenophon situate their respec- tive discussions of obedience to the law in an apologetic context. In the Crito, the immediate context is the prison where Socrates awaits the day of his execu- tion after his trial.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophic Life and Socratic Fatherhood in the Apology, the Crito, and the Phaedo
    Gib´on vol. IX (2011) pp. 35{50 c 2012 Ateneo de Naga University Regular Research Article ISSN 1655-7247 The Philosophic Life and Socratic Fatherhood in the Apology, the Crito, and the Phaedo Federico Jos´eT. Lagdameo Department of Philosophy Ateneo de Naga University Abstract Plato's depiction and defense of philosophy were linked to his de- piction and defense of Socrates' own life. Notably in the Early Dialogues which gave accounts of Socrates' trial and execution, Plato portrayed his mentor's life as the philosophic life which one ought to aspire for. Yet, Socrates' admission in the Apology and the Crito's reproof that the former had neglected his oikon or his household presented an image of Socrates that suggested that the paradigm of the philosophic life had been in fact remiss by being an absent father who failed to care for his own children. I indicate that this image of Socrates engendered questions and criticisms against the life devoted to philosophy, especially from those belonging to a family-centered cultural milieu such as the Philippines. I show that Socrates's fatherhood is one that prioritizes the care of the political community over that of his own family. Keywords: Plato, trial of Socrates, Early Dialogues, fatherhood, philo- sophic life From Plato we receive the notion that philosophy is not merely an activity, that it is not merely something that a man does. Philos- ophy is an ethos in which one's actions are derived ultimately from the soul's virtue. Philosophy, in other words, is a kind of life that is lived.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Did Xenophon Write a Symposium? Erotica Paideia and Logos Sokratikos*
    JOSÉ VELA TEJADA Why did Xenophon write a Symposium? Erotica paideia and logos Sokratikos* 1. Xenophon, Socrates and the logos Sokratikos Xenophon bequeathed a collection of works, with philosophical con- tent, grouped under the title of Socratica, whose composing was mainly in- spired by the leading role of Socrates, or, actually, by Xenophon’s under- standing of the Athenian master’s ideas. Therefore, the Socrates’ lifetime until his condemn, and his intellectual activity – matters that are less focused in his historical works – find a proper narrative vehicle in the Socratica, ac- cording to Xenophontean tendency to thematic specialization. The topic of this essay is the effect of Socratic spirit1, also ascertained in the pedagogic aim and in the ultimate search of the individual paradigm of the Xenophon’s historical works. Nevertheless, we should not insist – as in previous analyses – in estab- lishing the epistemological superiority that results from comparison with * This article was made under the general frame of the Research-Team Byblíon H 52 (Dirección General de Investigación, Innovación y Desarrollo, Consejería de Ciencia y Tec- nología, DGA, Spain). 1 We say spirit or influence because, although Xenophon informs us of personal rela- tionship with Socrates in Anabasis (III, 1, 5), this does not mean that he was member of the closest circle of Socrates’ disciples. In relation to that, WATERFIELD 2004, 79, considers Xe- nophon as a true Socratic for “he followed Socrates’ philosophy to the best of his ability”. H istorikαv I 2011 ISSN 2240-774X e-ISSN 2039-4985 81 José Vela Tejada Plato2. Sometimes it has been suggested that the Xenophontean profile of Socrates has a more accurate historical reliability than the Platonic one; however, we cannot prove any hypothesis neither in the historian nor in the philosopher3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of Plato's Crito and Phaedo on Xenophon's Apology of Socrates
    Kentron Revue pluridisciplinaire du monde antique 31 | 2015 Les Socratica de Xénophon The influence of Plato’s Crito and Phaedo on Xenophon’s Apology of Socrates Boris Hogenmüller Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/kentron/347 DOI: 10.4000/kentron.347 ISSN: 2264-1459 Publisher Presses universitaires de Caen Printed version Date of publication: 1 November 2015 Number of pages: 127-138 ISBN: 978-2-84133-747-7 ISSN: 0765-0590 Electronic reference Boris Hogenmüller, « The influence of Plato’s Crito and Phaedo on Xenophon’s Apology of Socrates », Kentron [Online], 31 | 2015, Online since 19 October 2016, connection on 17 November 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/kentron/347 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/kentron.347 Kentron is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 3.0 International License. The inFluence OF Plato’S CRITO and PHAEDO Hauteur 1 du rectangle d’empagement on Xenophon’S APOLOGY OF SOCRATES T_3_Article The relationship between Plato and Xenophon has been the subject of research for many years. During the late 19th and early 20th century, the result of this research, especially in terms of the ‘Sokratesbild’, was always the same, and Xenophon’s dependence on the logoi Sokratikoi written by Plato and Antisthenes has always been quite obvious 2. In the middle of the 20th century, however, new studies have given rise to another opinion 3, which made the case for dependence of Xenophon on other Socratics. Thus L.-A. Dorion’s statement (« Xénophon dépend des autres Socratiques : il ne constitue pas une source indépendante » 4), although he attempts to refute it 5, seems more appropriate today than ever before.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Political Philosophy
    History of Political Thought: Ancient Political Philosophy Semester: Spring 2021 ECTS Credits: 6 Hours/week: 90 + 90 min Language: English Instructor: Cole Simmons, PhD Meeting: Tues: 9:00 – 10:30 (Online) Thursday: (b) 9:00 – 10:30; (a) 10:40-12:10 (Online) Office third floor, Blue building Tel: (+421 2) 59234 722 Cell: +421 944 846 840 [email protected] CONTENT The thing that hath been, it is that which shall be; and that which is done is that which shall be done: and there is no new thing under the sun. – Ecclesiastes 1:9 The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato. I do not mean the systematic scheme of thought which scholars have doubtfully extracted from his writings. I allude to the wealth of general ideas scattered through them. –Alfred North Whitehead We are going to read Plato, Xenophon, and Aristotle. Plato and Xeonphon were friends and the pupils of Socrates. Aristotle was the pupil of Plato. Their writings have lasted for a reason. We will try to understand that reason, namely, we will try to understand their ineradicable insights into the Right of Nature. In Ancient Greece, man perfected himself. ASSIGNMENTS There will be 2 papers, each worth 25% of your grade. 25% is for attendance and participation. There will be an online message board component, worth 25%. Timeliness is of essence in this course. Assignments have to be uploaded via Google Classroom by the due date. Late submissions will incur grade penalty.
    [Show full text]
  • Dialectic in Xenophon's Memorabilia
    Dialectic in xenophon’s Memorabilia : Responding to 4.6 William Henry Furness Altman1 Abstract: A consideration of Memorabilia 4.6 as a whole and in context reveals that Xenophon’s Socrates taught his companions to be “more dialectical” (dialektikōtéroi) by deliberately offering them bad, simplistic, or fallacious arguments in order to provoke debate, discussion, and dialectic. This reading indicates why Xenophon introduces the chapter modestly by saying “I will try to explain even this” (the first words of 4.6.1) and why some of the arguments that follow have generated a decidedly mixed scholarly response. Although the chapter as a whole will be analyzed and discussed, particular attention is given to the use of the word “hypothesis” in the chapter (4.6.13-14) and the fact that Socrates identifies Odysseus as “a safe speaker” at 4.6.15. Keywords: Xenophon. Socrates. dialectic. akrasía. Odysseus. 1. PhD in Philosophy by UFSC. E-mail: [email protected] DOI 10.5935/2179-9180.20180017 Dialética nas Memorabilia de Xenofonte: respondendo a 4.6 Resumo: Uma consideração de Memorabilia 4.6 como um todo e em contexto revela que Sócrates de Xenofonte ensinou seus companheiros a serem “mais dialéticos” (dialektikōtéroi) deliberadamente oferecendo-lhes argumentos ruins, simplistas ou falaciosos para provocar debate, discussão e dialética. Essa leitura indica por que Xenofonte introduz o capítulo modestamente dizendo “tentarei explicar até mesmo isto” (as primeiras palavras de 4.6.1) e por que alguns dos argumentos que se seguem geraram uma resposta claramente heterogênea dos eruditos. Embora o capítulo como um todo seja analisado e discutido, uma atenção especial é dada ao uso da palavra “hipótese” no capítulo (4.6.13-14) e ao fato de que Sócrates identifica Odisseu como “um orador seguro” em 4.6.15.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Daimonion of Socrates
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Heinz-Günther Nesselrath, Reinhard Feldmeier und Rainer Hirsch-Luipold Band XVI Plutarch On the daimonion of Socrates Human liberation, divine guidance and philosophy edited by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath Introduction, Text, Translation and Interpretative Essays by Donald Russell, George Cawkwell, Werner Deuse, John Dillon, Heinz-Günther Nesselrath, Robert Parker, Christopher Pelling, Stephan Schröder Mohr Siebeck e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156444-4 ISBN 978-3-16-150138-8 (cloth) ISBN 987-3-16-150137-1 (paperback) The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio- nal bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data is availableon the Internet at http:// dnb.d-nb.de. © 2010 by Mohr Siebeck Tübingen. This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This applies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and processing in electronic systems. This book was typeset by Christoph Alexander Martsch, Serena Pirrotta and Thorsten Stolper at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen, printed by Gulde- Druck in Tübingen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times. The first four centuries of our era have, however, produced a cornucopia of works in Greek and Latin dealing with questions of philoso- phy, ethics, and religion that continue to be relevant even today.
    [Show full text]
  • Dialogue and Virtue in Xenophon's
    Dialogue, Speeches, and the Acquisition of Virtue In Xenophon’s Memorabilia Louis-André Dorion (Université de Montréal) The role that dialogue plays in the works of Xenophon is a deeply interesting issue that could be analyzed from a variety of different perspectives. From a literary point of view, it would be possible to raise the question of how dialogue fits into what is above all a narrative framework, in particular in the Cyropaedia and in the Anabasis. It would also be worthwhile to analyze from a literary point of view dialogues that have the form of a mise en abyme. Here I am mainly thinking of the dialogue between Virtue and Vice (Mem. 2.1.21-34), which is related by Socrates in a conversation with Aristippus, as well as of the dialogue between Socrates and Ischomachus (Oec. 7-21), which is also related by Socrates, but this time in a conversation with Critobulus. In addition, it would be interesting to ask whether the dialogues in Xenophon’s Socratic writings are models for the dialogues in his other works. For example, does the dialogue between Simonides and Hiero, in Xenophon’s Hiero, have the same literary form and the same philosophical aims as the Socratic dialogues in the Memorabilia? Is the irony that Simonides manifests in the first part of the Hiero of the same nature as Socrates’ irony? These are a few examples of questions, among many others, that it would be interesting to examine. I have decided, however, to examine Xenophon’s use of dialogue from another interpretative angle, one that is somewhat ambitious, for I propose to analyze the nature, the role, and the effectiveness of dialogue in the process of acquiring virtue as it is depicted in the Memorabilia.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates' Understanding of His Trial: the Political Presentation of Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by eScholarship@BC Socrates' Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Author: Kazutaka Kondo Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3926 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2011 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science SOCRATES’ UNDERSTANDING OF HIS TRIAL: THE POLITICAL PRESENTATION OF PHILOSOPHY a dissertation by KAZUTAKA KONDO submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2011 © copyright by KAZUTAKA KONDO 2011 Abstract Socrates’ Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Kazutaka Kondo Dissertation Advisor: Robert C. Bartlett This dissertation investigates how Socrates understands his trial. It is a well-known fact that Socrates is accused of impiety and corruption of the young and is subsequently executed. Unlike an ordinary defendant who is supposed to make every effort to be acquitted, Socrates, behaving provocatively, seems even to induce the death penalty. By reading Plato’s and Xenophon’s works, this dissertation clarifies his thoughts on the trial that must be the basis of his conduct and explains how he achieves his aim. To deal with Socrates’ view of the trial as a whole, this study examines three questions. First, does he believe in his own innocence? I argue that before and even at the trial, Socrates does not intend to prove his innocence effectively.
    [Show full text]