Gadamer, Heidegger, and the Social Dimensions of Language: Reflections on the Critical Otentialp of Hermeneutical Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Gadamer, Heidegger, and the Social Dimensions of Language: Reflections on the Critical Otentialp of Hermeneutical Philosophy Chicago-Kent Law Review Volume 76 Issue 2 Symposium on Philosophical Article 7 Hermeneutics and Critical Legal Theory December 2000 Gadamer, Heidegger, and the Social Dimensions of Language: Reflections on the Critical otentialP of Hermeneutical Philosophy Ingrid Scheibler Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.kentlaw.iit.edu/cklawreview Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Ingrid Scheibler, Gadamer, Heidegger, and the Social Dimensions of Language: Reflections on the Critical Potential of Hermeneutical Philosophy, 76 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 853 (2000). Available at: https://scholarship.kentlaw.iit.edu/cklawreview/vol76/iss2/7 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chicago-Kent Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. GADAMER, HEIDEGGER, AND THE SOCIAL DIMENSIONS OF LANGUAGE: REFLECTIONS ON THE CRITICAL POTENTIAL OF HERMENEUTICAL PHILOSOPHY INGRID SCHEIBLER* INTRODUCTION In the English-speaking world, the work of Hans-Georg Gadamer has been influential in philosophy and the social sciences since his debate with German social theorist Jurgen Habermas in the late 1960s and early 1970s. More recently, Gadamer's insights into the hermeneutical dimension of human existence have been considered and developed in a range of areas, from literary criticism to debates in legal theory. This is not surprising, given that his hermeneutical philosophy anticipates many concerns central to recent developments of deconstruction and postmodern criticism, which have impacted the humanities and legal studies generally, as well as the development, following "legal realism," of what has become known as the Critical Legal Studies movement ("CLS").1 We also see Gadamer's work taken up in debates explored by political theory and legal studies concerning both the nature and role of rhetoric in legal argumentation, 2 and the nature of justice. Perhaps most notable among hermeneutical approaches to issues of justice is Georgia Warnke's Justice and Interpretation.3 Warnke * Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Boston College. 1. For an account of recent developments, see William W. Fisher III, The Development of Modem American Legal Theory and the Judicial Interpretation of the Bill of Rights, in A CULTURE OF RIGHTS 266, 267-89 (Michael J. Lacey & Knud Haakonssen eds., 1991); ROBERTO MANGABEIRA UNGER, THE CRITICAL LEGAL STUDIES MOVEMENT (1st ed. 1986). For a more general discussion, oriented to the critique of liberalism in different strains of the CLS movement, see CORNEL WEST, KEEPING FAITH: PHILOSOPHY AND RACE IN AMERICA 195- 250 (1993). For a discussion of Habermas's engagement with the CLS movement, see DAVID M. RASMUSSEN, READING HABERMAS 56-93 (1990). 2. For an excellent account linking the rhetorical dimension of knowledge with legal argumentation and the possibility of reasoning about justice, which draws on Gadamer's and Chaim Perelman's work, see Francis J. Mootz III, Rhetorical Knowledge in Legal Practice and Theory, 6 S. CAL. INTERDISC. L.J., 491,492-610 (1998). 3. See GEORGIA WARNKE, JUSTICE AND INTERPRETATION (1992) [hereinafter WARNKE, JUSTICE]. For discussions linking hermeneutics and justice, see also Fred Dallmayr, Hermeneutics and Justice, David Couzens Hoy, Legal Hermeneutics: Recent Debates, and CHICAGO-KENT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 76:853 addresses one of the central problems for modern political theory, of responding effectively to charges of subjectivism, or conventionalism, in recognizing that principles of justice are always rooted in specific cultural contexts and traditions. Given this situation, the challenge is to develop a concept of justice and an account of the nature of political discourse and the means for rationally justifying competing and divergent interpretations, which supplies a critical and normative dimension. 4 The question of interpretation is central to disputes over principles of justice reflecting, Warnke says, "differences either over which institutional arrangements comply with a given society's public political culture or over what the public political culture itself means."5 She is interested in developing interpretive guidelines, which she locates in the hermeneutic insight into the unity of meaning of parts and whole. She sees a criterion for interpretation in, among other views she considers, Gadamer's account of the "anticipation of completeness. '6 Further, she finds illuminating Gadamer's con- nection of a criterion of coherence, with another criterion, the "educative" function of a given interpretation. For Gadamer, Warnke writes, [T]he point of any serious attempt to understand the meaning of a text or text analogue must be to achieve a better understanding of the issues and questions with which we are concerned.... [W]e must suppose that the texts or text analogues we are studying can be not only internally coherent but also illuminating, that they can educate us over some subject matter, answer a question we have or clarify some issue.7 Gadamer's work, then, provides insight for a hermeneutic political theory which conceives our conceptions of justice as "constrained interpretations of our democratic traditions, institutions, and practice" and which recognizes that no interpretation of these has Georgia Warnke, Walzer, Rawls, and Gadamer: Hermeneutics and Political Theory, in FESTIVALS OF INTERPRETATION: ESSAYS ON HANs-GEORG GADAMER'S WORK (Kathleen Wright ed., 1990). 4. Warnke likens this problem of a hermeneutic political theory with the diversity of interpretations encountered in the humanities. She locates the more pressing need for agreement in the political domain, where she says, "we must be able to agree on shared social meanings so that we can agree on the principles, actions and practices that are appropriate to them." WARNKE, JUSTICE, supra note 3, at 62. 5. Id. at 131. 6. Id. at 129. 7. Id. Warnke supplements Gadamer's approach with a version of Habermas's proceduralist critical theory to address the existence of social forces that distort practical dialogue and hinder the educative function of conversation. I address the issue of the criterion of "education" below. 2000] GADAMER, HEIDEGGER,SOCIAL DIMENSIONS OF LANGUAGE 855 exclusivity. Rather, there is a fundamental recognition that "we 8 might learn from others." Warnke's appropriation of Gadamer, then, seeks to provide normative guidelines for what happens in the everyday context of public debate about contested moral and political issues-for example, abortion or affirmative action.9 Further, this everyday context of public debate is conceived as one where ongoing interpretation and deliberation among a healthy divergence and disagreement of views, and not a homogenizing consensus, is the source of political legitimation. 10 Though Gadamer's view may need to be supplemented with criteria for assessing the educative function of different interpretations, his hermeneutical philosophy provides a normative dimension for interpretative situations in public, political discourse. This is one of the central and most fruitful aspects of his work. I single out Warnke's efforts because my interest in Gadamer shares with Warnke a commitment to drawing out the critical potential of this aspect of Gadamer's hermeneutical philosophy. I examine his views of language and tradition, connected with his concept of dialogue or conversation, to show that they offer important critical insights. Gadamer offers a model for thinking the position of human beings in the world, at once rooted in a finite and historical situation-the condition of belonging to the contexts of tradition and language-yet not conceiving this context as inherently limiting. Rather, given the centrality of and injunction for dialogue with what is other, other traditions and points of view, Gadamer's concept of the engagement of hermeneutical understanding conceives it as ongoing and critically motivated dialogue between particular and divergent points of view. That Gadamer's hermeneutical philosophy has this critical and political potential comes into relief most sharply by examining the specifically social dimensions of language in his work. In examining these, I will look at an issue central to Gadamer's work: his view of linguistically mediated tradition. The critical and 8. Id. at 131. 9. Warnke also extends her appropriation of Gadamer and Habermas to further develop an account of the role of interpretation in public political debate in GEORGIA WARNKE, LEGITIMATE DIFFERENCES: INTERPRETATION IN THE ABORTION CONTROVERSY AND OTHER PUBLIC DEBATES (1999). 10. Warnke takes up this issue specifically in relation to Alasdair MacIntyre's work. See WARNKE, JUSTICE, supra note 3, at 116-17. CHICAGO-KENT LAW REVIEW [Vol. 76:853 political potential of the social dimensions of language come into relief most strongly here. Despite the fact that Gadamer's work can be so productively used to illuminate efforts to provide normative guidelines vital to fostering an open democratic society, his work, however, continues to elicit charges of conservatism and traditionalism." Such readings suggest that, in Gadamer's view, tradition and justice are antithetical. Some of these charges stem from Gadamer's debate in the 1960s and early 1970s with Jirgen Habermas, focusing on the conservative character of Gadamer's work in the face of the interests
Recommended publications
  • Critical Inquiry As Virtuous Truth-Telling: Implications of Phronesis and Parrhesia ______
    ______________________________________________________________________________ Critical Inquiry as Virtuous Truth-Telling: Implications of Phronesis and Parrhesia ______________________________________________________________________________ Austin Pickup, Aurora University Abstract This article examines critical inquiry and truth-telling from the perspective of two comple- mentary theoretical frameworks. First, Aristotelian phronesis, or practical wisdom, offers a framework for truth that is oriented toward ethical deliberation while recognizing the contingency of practical application. Second, Foucauldian parrhesia calls for an engaged sense of truth-telling that requires risk from the inquirer while grounding truth in the com- plexity of human discourse. Taken together, phronesis and parrhesia orient inquirers to- ward intentional truth-telling practices that resist simplistic renderings of criticality and overly technical understandings of research. This article argues that truly critical inquiry must spring from the perspectives of phronesis and parrhesia, providing research projects that aim at virtuous truth-telling over technical veracity with the hope of contributing to ethical discourse and social praxis. Keywords: phronesis, praxis, parrhesia, critical inquiry, truth-telling Introduction The theme of this special issue considers the nature of critical inquiry, specifically methodological work that remains committed to explicit goals of social justice and the good. One of the central concerns of this issue is that critical studies have lost much of their meaning due to a proliferation of the term critical in educational scholarship. As noted in the introduction to this issue, much contemporary work in education research that claims to be critical may be so in name only, offering but methodological techniques to engage in critical work; techniques that are incapable of inter- vening in both the epistemological and ontological formations of normative practices in education.
    [Show full text]
  • Sheila M. Ross
    ISSN 1393-614X Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 8 (2004): 132-168 ____________________________________________________ Gadamer’s Late Thinking on Verweilen Sheila M. Ross Abstract This essay presents Gadamer’s interest in temporality as his strategy for advancing the importance of hermeneutics as philosophy of experience, a strategy that I show becomes significantly more salient with the appearance of his 1992 essay, Wort und Bild. I show how temporal categories function to demarcate the ontological imbalance that is of such central concern in Gadamer’s philosophical project. The paper also considers some common misunderstandings of Gadamer that result from a failure to take full account of his experiential orientation, and thus prevent recognition of its radical potential. A full account must include a grasp of the exemplariness of art in his philosophy, and in this connection, the essay considers, not Gadamer’s ideal of lyric poetry, but the quite distinct exemplariness of narrative art. Though its temporal structure would seem particularly pertinent, it is not this feature, it turns out, that makes it particularly worthy of hermeneutical reflection. I. Close to the Living World: Late Crystallizations This essay considers Gadamer’s attribution of a special temporality to the experience of “tarrying” (Verweilen), a term that for Gadamer denotes the exemplary hermeneutical eventfulness of application. Gadamer has frequently mentioned that the quality of time during tarrying is its definitive feature, and therefore this particular thread about time in Gadamer would appear to be rather fundamental. However, it is difficult to find any substantial discussion of the overall significance of Gadamer’s particular thinking about time.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science Patrick A
    Fordham University Masthead Logo DigitalResearch@Fordham Hermeneutic and Phenomenological Philosophies Research Resources of Science 1991 Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science Patrick A. Heelan Georgetown University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_research Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Heelan, Patrick A., "Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science" (1991). Research Resources. 11. https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_research/11 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Hermeneutic and Phenomenological Philosophies of Science at DigitalResearch@Fordham. It has been accepted for inclusion in Research Resources by an authorized administrator of DigitalResearch@Fordham. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science Heelan, Patrick, “Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science,” in Silverman, Hugh (ed.), Gadamer and Hermeneutics: Science, Culture, and Literature, (New York: Routledge, 1991). pp. 213-228 HERMENEUTICAL PHENOMENOLOGY AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE PATRICK A. HEELAN PART I: Continental and Analytic Philosophy of Science Compared The two most characteristic interests of continental philosophy1 are (1) its preoccupation with the problem of the “constitution” of knowledge, and (2) the effect of the historical and cultural world context of science on the “social constitution” of scientific knowledge. Such constitution is “hermeneutical,” when it essentially involves language, natural and artifactual symbols, and historical communities of interpreters. Continental philosophy from the start sees science as an institution in a cultural, historical, and hermeneutical setting. The domain of its discourse is values, subjectivity, Life Worlds, history, and society, as these affect the constitution of scientific knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Spring 2007 Professor Balbus
    Spring 2007 Professor Balbus Political Science 504. Theoretical Approaches to Policy and Governance This course encourages a careful reading of three of the most important, widely discussed and debated works of philosophy of the last quarter of the 20th century that raise questions about the epistemologies that govern the study of politics: Richard Rortys Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Hans-Georg Gadamer's Truth and Method, and Jurgen Habermass The Theory of Communicative Action: Volume I. Thus the course also serves as an introduction to central issues in analytic philosophy, hermeneutics, and critical theory. Richard Bernstein's overview, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism, is also required, as is a take-home final examination, weekly 1-2 page memos (beginning with week 4) and one oral presentation in class. The four required texts referred to above are all available for purchase at the Circle Center bookstore. Weeks 1-3 I. Introduction and overview Required: Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism Weeks 4-7 II. Analytic Philosophy Required: Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature Recommended: 1. Works Referred to in the Text P.F. Strawson, Individuals ___________, The Bounds of Sense George Pitcher, A Theory of Perception D.M. Armstrong, Perception and the Physical World D.M. Armstrong, A Materialist Theory of Mind John Dewey, The Quest for Certainty John Dewey, Experience and Nature John Locke, Essay Concerning Understanding Wilfrid Sellars, Science, Perception, and Reality Rene Descartes, Discourse on Method Rene Descartes, Meditations Willis Doney, Descartes: Critical Essays Michael Hooker, Descartes: Critical and Interpretative Essays Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind Jerome Shaffer, Philosophy of Mind O.P.
    [Show full text]
  • Gadamer's Ambivalence Toward the Enlightenment Project
    University of Tabriz Journal of Philosophical Investigations Volume 6, No. 11 Autumn & Winter 2012 Gadamer’s Ambivalence toward the Enlightenment Project − Robert J. Dostal −− Rufus M. Jones Professor of Philosophy, Bryn Mawr College Abstract This essay explores Gadamer’s ambivalent relationship with modernity. Gadamer is a prominent critic of the Enlightenment project. His criticisms are both theoretical and practical. Theoretically, representationalism is at the center of modern epistemology for Gadamer. Practically, Gadamer sees the demotion of prudence ( phronesis ) as fundamental to the “bad” Enlightenment. Gadamer’s attempt to revive an appreciation of rhetoric is a way to the join the theoretical and practical dimensions of speech and life. The central representative philosopher of the Enlightenment for Gadamer is Kant. The antithetical thinker is Aristotle. Gadamer would have his Kant and his Aristotle too. The tension between these is at the heart of Gadamer’s philosophical hermeneutics. Keywords: Gadamer, Enlightenment, Modernity, Philosophical Herme- neutics, Understanding, Language . − ﺗﺎرﻳﺦ وﺻﻮل: 20/7/ 1391 ، ﺗﺄﻳﻴﺪ ﻧﻬﺎﻳﻲ: 9/28/ 1391 University of Tabriz Journal of Philosophical Investigations 54 I. Introduction: Gadamer and Modernity’s Break with the Past Characteristic of much of the philosophical discourse of the 19 th and 20 th century is the rhetoric of a radical break with previous thought. This “break” is often expressed as a break with metaphysics or a break with modernity or a break with the Enlightenment. Prominent voices include, in the 19th century, Comte, Marx and Nietzsche, and in the 20 th century Husserl, Heidegger, Wittgenstein, Horkheimer and Adorno. More recent is the phenomena of postmodernism, which very label announces the break with modern thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Enacting Hermeneutic Philosophy As Research in Practice Disciplines
    Journal of Applied Hermeneutics January 2, 2016 ©The Author(s) 2016 Encountering the Great Problems in the Street: Enacting Hermeneutic Philosophy as Research in Practice Disciplines Graham McCaffrey1, RN, PhD & Nancy J. Moules1, RN, PhD Abstract In this paper, we speak to tenets of Gadamerian hermeneutic philosophy that “guide” our herme- neutic inquiry in research that seeks to understand the complexity of human experiences. In our conduct of hermeneutic research, we grapple with “great problems” and encounter the human difficulty of topics such as childhood cancer, grief, mental illness, education and schools, arts and humanities, and other topics that show up in practice professions of nursing, teaching, social work, or psychology. Keywords hermeneutic research, hermeneutic philosophy, Hans-Georg Gadamer, nursing, qualitative research, applied hermeneutics Of all actions, those performed for a purpose have been least understood, no doubt be- cause they have always been counted the most understandable and are to our conscious- ness the most commonplace. The great problems are to be encountered in the street. (Nie- tzsche, 1881/1982, p. 78) In 2015, Dr. John Caputo introduced us to a society hosted out of Villanova University called the North American Society for Philosophical Hermeneutics (NASPH), a society interested in 1 University of Calgary, Faculty of Nursing Corresponding Author: Graham McCaffrey, RN PhD Email: [email protected] 2 McCaffrey & Moules Journal of Applied Hermeneutics 2016 Article 1 philosophical hermeneutics in particular that of Hans-Georg Gadamer. The focus of the 2015 10th annual meeting was “The Future(s) of Hermeneutics” and we decided to submit a paper offering our perspectives and approaches that involve applied hermeneutics.
    [Show full text]
  • Print This Article
    Aesthetic Experience, Mimesis and Testimony Roger W. H. Savage University of California Los Angeles Abstract In this article, I relate the demand that Paul Ricœur suggests mimesis places on the way we think about truth to the idea that the work of art is a model for thinking about testimony. By attributing a work’s epoché of reality to the work of imagination, I resolve the impasse that arises from attributing music, literature, and art’s distance from the real to their social emancipation. Examining the conjunction, in aesthetic experience, of the communicability and the exemplarity of a work reveals how Ricœur’s definition of mimesis as refiguration relates to the “rule” that the work summons. This “rule” constitutes the solution to a problem or question for which the work is the answer. In conclusion, as a model for thinking about testimony, the claims that works make have a counterpart in the injunctions that issue from exemplary moral and political acts. Keywords: Aesthetic experience, Mimesis, Judgment, Testimony Résumé Dans cet article, j’établis un lien entre l’exigence que, selon Paul Ricœur,la mimèsis place dans notre façon de penser la vérité, et l’idée que l’œuvre d’art est un modèle pour penser le témoignage. Appliquant l’époché de la réalité à l’oeuvre d’imagination, j’évite l’impasse qui se dresse lorsqu’on attribue la musique, la littérature et la distance artistique du réel à leur émancipation sociale. L’étude de la conjonction du caractère communicable et exemplaire d’une œuvre – dans l’expérience esthétique - met en lumière la relation que la définition par Ricœur de la mimésis comme refiguration établit avec la “règle” que l’œuvre convoque.
    [Show full text]
  • Foucault and Gadamer: Like Apples and Oranges Passing in the Night
    FOUCAULT AND GADAMER: LIKE APPLES AND ORANGES PASSING IN THE NIGHT GARY WICKHAM* INTRODUCTION In introducing their book, Michel Foucault:Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, (first published in 1982, one of the earliest attempts in English at a book-length exposition of the direction and nuances of Foucault's work-one which has stood the test of time), Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow tell us that philosophical hermeneutics "gives up the phenomenologists' attempt to understand man as a meaning-giving subject, but attempts to preserve meaning by locating it in the social practices and literary texts which man produces."1 They go on to identify two types of hermeneutics which emerged from Heidegger's Being and Time. The first involves "the way Dasein interprets itself in this everyday activity. This 'primordial understanding' in our everyday practices and discourse, which is overlooked by the practitioners but which they would recognize if it were pointed out to them, is the subject of much recent hermeneutic investigation. '2 This school of Heideggerian hermeneutics 3 "claims to find that the deep truth hidden by the everyday practices is the unsettling groundlessness of a way of being which is, so to speak, interpretation all the way down."' They suggest that this school can be characterized as "the hermeneutics of suspicion."5 The second type of hermeneutics is that developed by Hans- Georg Gadamer. It "gives deep hermeneutics a more positive * Senior Lecturer, Sociology Programme, Murdoch University. I thank Alan Hunt and Jeff Malpas for their helpful comments and suggestions, and I thank Jay Mootz for his encouragement.
    [Show full text]
  • Gadamerian Hermeneutics and Irony: Between Strauss and Derrida Robert J
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Philosophy Faculty Research and Scholarship Philosophy 2008 Gadamerian Hermeneutics and Irony: Between Strauss and Derrida Robert J. Dostal Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/philosophy_pubs Part of the Philosophy Commons Custom Citation Dostal, Robert J., "Gadamerian Hermeneutics and Irony: Between Strauss and Derrida," Research in Phenomenology 38:2, (2008): 247-269. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/philosophy_pubs/6 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Robert J. Dostal Bryn Mawr College GADAMERIAN HERMENEUTICS AND IRONY: BETWEEN STRAUSS AND DERRIDA 1. Introduction There is a well-known and well-founded, if somewhat oversimple, distinction between the hermeneutics of trust (or good will) and the hermeneutics of suspicion. Commentators on Gadamer, I among them, have counted Gadamer’s hermeneutics as a “hermeneutics of trust” and contrasted it with the hermeneutics of suscipion. 1 As is well-known, this latter phrase, “hermeneutics of suspicion,” was coined by Paul Ricoeur in his book on Freud. 2 The 19 th century masters of such a hermeneutics are Freud and Marx. It goes without saying that they have had much influence on contemporary hermeneutics. Gadamer himself devoted an essay to the hermeneutics of suspicion, which, for whatever reason, Gadamer did not publish in German. 3 In this essay Gadamer names Nietzsche as the “inaugurator” of radical suspicion, whose “most striking instances” are to be found in the critique of ideology and psychoanalysis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comparative Analysis on the Notion of Death in Heidegger and Gadamer
    Death’s Doorstep: A comparative analysis on the notion of death in Heidegger and Gadamer Bachelor thesis written by Anniek den Toom, 5682010 Utrecht University, Faculty of Humanities Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Philosophy Submitted on 19-06-2020 First Supervisor Dr. Tom Giesbers Second Supervisor Dr. Mathijs Peters Abstract Contrary to his former teacher Heidegger, Gadamer has not formulated an extensive and unified notion of death. His articulation of the subject must be reconstructed from short essays he has written throughout his lifetime. This has caused Gadamer’s view on death to contain some ambiguity. I will attempt to provide insight into Gadamer’s account on death by comparing his writings to Heidegger’s notion of death as presented in Being and Time. Gadamer’s philosophy has been highly influenced by Heidegger. Therefore, it is to be expected that there is some degree of compatibility between the two notions of death. I will argue that because of its fragmented character, Gadamer’s notion of death is very much susceptible to interpretation. Donatella Di Cesare offers one such interpretation by reconstructing Gadamer’s view via his texts on death as well as his other fundamental philosophical positions. I will provide an account of Gadamer’s notion of death solely on the basis of his specific texts on the subject and argue why Heidegger’s and Gadamer’s views on death might me more compatible than is suggested by Di Cesare. Using an isolated version of Gadamer’s conception of death will reveal the degree of susceptibility to interpretation of this notion and therefore also the obstacles in acquiring clear insight into Gadamer’s view on death.
    [Show full text]
  • Gadamer, Davidson, and the Ground of Understanding
    The Ground of Understanding Jeff Malpas In his contribution to Gadamer’s volume in the Library of Living Philosophers, Donald Davidson makes an explicit attempt, taking Plato’s Philebus as his focus, to connect his own thinking with that of Hans-Georg Gadamer in a way that, while it does not ignore possible points of difference, is also suggestive of important continuities in their approaches.1 In the same volume David Hoy argues that ‘the hermeneutic theory of interpretation can enter into a dialogue with the Davidsonian account’ and attempts to ‘draw on some of Davidson’s arguments to defend Gadamer’s hermeneutic theory against its critics.’2 Elsewhere Simon Evnine has suggested that Davidson belongs more in the company of two of Gadamer’s own philosophical heroes – Plato and Hegel – ‘than in the company of the Vienna Circle and Quine, with their austere, anti-metaphysical scientism’3 – while in my own work I have advanced a reading of Davidson that brings him into proximity, not only with Gadamer, but also with Gadamer’s teacher, Martin Heidegger.4 Yet although there has been much within recent English-speaking philosophy that looks towards a rapprochement between the so-called ‘analytic’ tradition as represented in Davidson’s work and the ‘phenomenological-hermeneutic’ tradition of which Gadamer was one of the leading figures, still there are reasons for hesitation in announcing such a rapprochement. From a European perspective, for instance, Davidson might be thought to be committed to a naturalism, an extensionalism, even perhaps, a scientism, quite antithetical to the more ‘humanistic’ style of philosophising to which Gadamer belongs.
    [Show full text]
  • The Science of Philology and the Discipline of Hermeneutics: Gadamer’S Understanding
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Philosophy Faculty Research and Scholarship Philosophy 2010 The cS ience of Philology and the Discipline of Hermeneutics: Gadamer's Understanding Robert J. Dostal Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/philosophy_pubs Part of the Philosophy Commons Custom Citation Dostal, Robert J., "The cS ience of Philology and the Discipline of Hermeneutics: Gadamer's Understanding," Internationales Jahrbuch für Hermeneutik 9 (2010): 53-62. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/philosophy_pubs/5 For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE SCIENCE OF PHILOLOGY AND THE DISCIPLINE OF HERMENEUTICS: GADAMER’S UNDERSTANDING Robert J. Dostal Rufus M. Jones Professor of Philosophy Bryn Mawr College Bryn Mawr, Pennsylvania (Philadelphia) It is notable that nowhere in his major work on hermeneutics, Wahrheit und Methode , does Gadamer consider the question of knowledge ( Erkenntnis ) or the conditions and/or limits of knowing ( Erkennen ). Gadamer is not concerned with knowledge but with understanding ( Verstehen ). He only discusses knowledge in the context of his critique of neo-Kantian Erkenntnistheorie , epistemology. Gadamer draws a direct line from neo- Kantian Erkenntnistheorie of the late 19 th and early 20 th century to the epistemology of positivism in the early and middle 20 th century, the positivism of Carnap and Hempel, among others. In the context of the historical and social sciences Gadamer aligns his hermeneutics with the Verstehenssoziologie of Weber that has its roots in Dilthey and which contrasts with the Erklärenswissenschaften of the Neo-Kantians and positivists.
    [Show full text]