Will Fenton Thesis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Will Fenton Thesis FENTON, WILLIAM, M.A. DECEMBER 2019 PHILOSOPHY ON THE PHILOSOPHY AND PSYCHOLOGY OF REASONING AND RATIONALITY (67 pp.) Thesis Advisor: David Pereplyotchik Many theorists in philosophy and psychology have held that reasoning is a capacity geared towards getting at truth and epitomized in logical deduction. Though this remains a prevalent view, it has recently been called into question by psychological research on biases in human reasoning. Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber challenge both of these views and provide an alternative account of the nature and function of human reason. I will outline the grounds for holding that their "Interactionism" fits best with what is known about the evolution of human reasoning. Robert Brandom’s theory of rationality coincides with Interactionism in stressing the social nature of rationality, and in rejecting the notion that deduction is the key to understanding human reasoning. Although Brandom’s view has many virtues, it is not empirically informed. This raises questions about whether Brandom's theory can stand up in light of the putative success of Interactionism. I will argue that, far from being rival theories of the same subject matter, Interactionism can usefully supplement Brandom's theory of rationality, thereby correcting some of its deficiencies. ON THE PHILOSOPHY AND PSYCHOLOGY OF REASONING AND RATIONALITY A thesis submitted To Kent State University in Partial Fulfillment for the Degree of Master of Arts by William Fenton December, 2019 © Copyright All rights reserved Except for previously published materials Thesis written by William Fenton B.A., Kent State University, 2016 M.A., Kent State University, 2019 Approved by _______________________________, Advisor David Pereplyotchik _______________________________, Chair, Department of Philosophy Michael Byron _______________________________, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences James L. Blank TABLE OF CONTENTS……………………………………………………………………..…iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS…………………………………………………………………….vi INTRODUCTION………………………………………………………………………………1 CHAPTERS 1. Formalist Approaches to Human Reasoning §1 Introduction…………………………………………………………………………………7 §2 The Rejection of Psychologism……………………………………………………………..8 §3 Rudiments of Formalist Thought…………………………………………………………..10 §4 Mental Logic Theory………………………………………………………………………13 §5 Dual Process Theory……………………………………………………………………….16 §6 The Language of Thought Hypothesis……………………………………………………..21 §7 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………………23 2. Inferential Materialism and Logical Expressivism §1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………..25 §2 Sellars on Material Rules of Inference…………………………………………………….27 §3.1 Logical Expressivism……………………………………………………………………34 §3.2 Semantic Inferentialism………………………………………………………………….36 §4 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………………42 3. Inferentialism and Interactionism §1 Introduction………………………………………………………………………………...44 §2 The Interactionist Theory of Reasoning……………………………………………………44 §3.1 Connections ……………………………………………………………………………...50 §3.2 Normative Pragmatics……………………………………………………………………52 iv §4.1 Reasoning and Mentalese………………………………………………………………..55 §4.2 Reasoning and Modularity………………………………………………………………57 Conclusion ………………………………………………………………………………………60 REFERENCES…………………………………………………………………………………..64 v ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Many thanks to David, Dr. Deb, Dr. Aldea, Dr. Zavota, Dr. Fernandez, Dr. Pendleton, Dr. Barnbaum, Dr. Byron, Dr. Ryan, Dr. Ikuenobe, Dr. Kim, Alex Haas, Brant, Cara, Matt, Alex Martin, Stan, Nikita, Griffin, Jared, and Nick. vi On The Philosophy and Psychology of Reasoning and Rationality Introduction Formalism is the dominant view about rationality in philosophy, psychology, and cognitive science.1 The idea is that reasoning is a formal-computational process in the brain, geared towards the acquisition of true beliefs. Formalist approaches in psychology include mental logic theory, which seeks to explain our deductive reasoning capacities in terms of innate inference rules (Braine 1978; Braine and O’Brien 1998; Rips 1983, 1994), and dual process theory (Evans and Over 1996, Stanovich 1999, Kahneman 2011). Dual process theory holds that rational thinking—i.e., deduction and probabilistic reasoning—is a job for System 2, the slow, lazy, and sometimes rational part of the mind, while System 1 is in charge of fast, automatic, associative, intuitive processing. In philosophy and cognitive science, this idea finds its expression in the language of thought hypothesis, and the standard formulation of the computational theory of mind, according to which thoughts are represented by logically structured physical symbols in the brain (Fodor, 1975, 1987). To be clear, when I speak of the “formalist” in this paper, I intend to be referring to a wide swath of theorists—not only to those who subscribe to the language of thought hypothesis, mental logic theory, or dual process theory, 1 There has been a recent shift in the psychology of reasoning away from the “deduction paradigm,” and towards the “the new paradigm” (see Elqayam, Bonnefon, and Over, 2016). Although the probabilistic and dual process approaches that fall under the heading of the new paradigm are not logic-centered, they are still formalist, as that term is used here. !1 but more generally to any view that takes human reasoning to be formal in nature, or understands rationality narrowly in terms of adherence to formal rules of inference. In spite of the popularity of such views, I think that they are premised on questionable assumptions about the nature of reasoning and rationality. My critical aim in this essay is to motivate skepticism towards three formalist tenets in particular: (i) the hypothesis that reasoning is formal in nature, and carried out by the internal manipulation of symbols in accordance with formal rules of inference, (ii) the assumption that reasoning is primarily a solitary activity, geared solely towards the acquisition of true beliefs, and (iii) the formalist conception of rationality according to which agents are rational so long as they draw formally valid inferences, and irrational when they fail to draw such inferences. These ideas are interrelated: (i) is the central claim about reasoning present in all formalist theories, and it lends an air of plausibility to both (ii) and (iii) since it makes no mention of the environmental context that reasoning evolved to function in. Rather, (i) simply describes reasoning as an internal, formal psychological process, and since cognitive processes are private —in the trivial sense that there aren’t other agents inside of our heads while we reason—the solitary picture of reasoning and its putative function mentioned in (ii) seems intuitively correct. The standard of rationality invoked by (iii) is then jointly supported by both (i) and (ii). If reasoning is an internal formal-computational process, then it's not clear what purpose it might serve other than to produce true beliefs through formally valid inferential processes, and the failure to do so would appear to show that one’s reasoning skills are inadequate. The reader should bear in mind that it is the formalist paradigm that I am attempting to motivate skepticism towards in this essay. It is—of course—rational to have true beliefs, and beliefs are no doubt the outputs of inferential processes. The alternative view of reasoning and !2 rationality pieced together in ch. 3 is compatible with both of these claims. It differs, however, with respect to the characterization of the inferential processes involved in reasoning, and it is skeptical with regard to the conception of irrationality assumed by those working under the formalist paradigm. While it is certainly rational to produce formally valid arguments with true conclusions, it’s not obvious that we should always characterize the failure to do so as irrational behavior. For one thing, we should expect reasoning to fail, as it typically does (see ch. 1, §5), in contexts for which it is ill-suited in an evolutionary sense. This is one of the major lessons of the interactionist theory of reasoning (ch. 3, §2). Furthermore, materially valid arguments of the sort discussed in ch. 2 are not formally valid, but we would not characterize, e.g., the subjunctive inference from ‘X is a pen’ to ‘X would not disintegrate into thin air if I were to use it to write my signature’ as irrational on account of its not being a formally valid inference. And as Sellars points out (ch. 2, §2), we cannot say that our reason for endorsing such inferences is that they are enthymemes—that their true, “hidden” structures are formally valid. Considerations of this sort ought to motivate skepticism towards the idea—thesis (iii) above—that drawing formally valid inferences is the sole measure of human rationality. If what are clearly correct instances of reasoning do not qualify as rational by formalist standards, then it is not ordinary human reason that is inadequate but, rather, the formalist conception of it. My constructive aim will be to piece together two strands of theorizing that I believe jointly comprise a satisfying alternative approach. The primary contribution will be to integrate Robert Brandom’s semantic “inferentialism” with a promising new proposal in cognitive science —viz., “interactionism,” as developed by Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber in their 2017 book, The !3 Enigma of Reason. Although these theories differ in terms of methodology, inferentialism being a purely theoretical project, and interactionism an empirical hypothesis, I will argue that they are in agreement on fundamental
Recommended publications
  • Formalism Or “The Regime of Truth”: a Reading of Adrienne Rich’S
    International Journal of Linguistics and Literature (IJLL) ISSN 2319-3956 Vol. 2, Issue 4, Sep 2013, 19-28 © IASET FORMALISM OR “THE REGIME OF TRUTH”: A READING OF ADRIENNE RICH’S A CHANGE OF WORLD NAHID MOHAMMADI Department of English Language and Literature, Alzahra University, Tehran, Iran ABSTRACT Formalism in Adrienne Rich‟s first book, A Change of World, has attracted different critics and scholars so far. In their interpretations, it seems that they have taken it for granted that Adrienne Rich was a formalist. But none of them has ever presented the cause for the emergence of formalism in Adrienne Rich‟s early poetry. In this paper, I draw upon Michel Foucault‟s theory of “repressive power” and demonstrate that formalism was actually “the regime of truth” which determined „true/false‟ poetry for the young poet and excluded some poetic discourses and permitted only some particular ones to come into being in her first book. KEYWORDS: Adrienne Rich, A Change of World, Formalism, Michel Foucault, Discourse Analysis, Repressive Power, Exclusion, Truth, The Regime of Truth INTRODUCTION Almost all critics of Adrienne Rich‟s poetry agree that her early poems in A Change of World (1951) have been the poet‟s practice of distancing devices of modernist formalism which was dominant among the poets in the United States in the 1950s. Trudi Dawne Witonsky, who has examined Adrienne Rich‟s works in terms of Paulo Freire‟s theory of praxis1, admits that, in her early poetry, Rich wrote under the doctrine of New Critical formalism. She goes further and states that Rich‟s transition from formalism in her early poetry to feminism in her later volumes happens because of the „inadequacy of formalist‟ theory (Witonsky)2.
    [Show full text]
  • From Frames to Inference
    From Frames to Inference Nancy Chang, Srini Narayanan, and Miriam R.L. Petruck International Computer Science Institute 1947 Center St., Suite 600, Berkeley, CA 94704 nchang,miriamp,snarayan ¡ @icsi.berkeley.edu Abstract money ($1000) to another (Jerry) in exchange for some goods (a car) – but differ in the perspective This paper describes a computational they impose on the scene. formalism that captures structural rela- The shared inferential structure of verbs like buy tionships among participants in a dy- and sell is captured in FrameNet by the COMMERCE namic scenario. This representation is frame, which is associated with a set of situational used to describe the internal structure of roles, or frame elements (FEs), corresponding to FrameNet frames in terms of parameters event participants and props. These FEs are used for active event simulations. We apply our as annotation tags for sentences like those in (1), formalism to the commerce domain and yielding, for example: show how it provides a flexible means of handling linguistic perspective and other Buyer Goods challenges of semantic representation. (2) a. [Chuck] bought [a car] [from Jerry]Seller [for $1000]Payment. 1 Introduction b. [Jerry]Seller sold [a car]Goods [to Chuck]Buyer [for $1000]Payment. The development of lexical semantic resources is widely recognized as a prerequisite to progress in FE tags act as a shorthand that allows diverse verbs scalable natural language understanding. One of the to tap into a common subset of encyclopedic knowl- most semantically sophisticated efforts in this direc- edge. Moreover, regularities in the set of FEs real- tion is FrameNet (Baker et al., 1998; Fillmore et al., ized with specific lexical items can be taken as cor- 2001), an online lexical resource1 designed accord- related with their favored perspective.
    [Show full text]
  • Formalism and Realism in Ruins (Mapping the Logics of Collapse)
    University of Colorado Law School Colorado Law Scholarly Commons Articles Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship 2009 Formalism and Realism in Ruins (Mapping the Logics of Collapse) Pierre Schlag University of Colorado Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Politics Commons Citation Information Pierre Schlag, Formalism and Realism in Ruins (Mapping the Logics of Collapse), 95 Iowa L. Rev. 195 (2009) (reprinted with permission), available at . Copyright Statement Copyright protected. Use of materials from this collection beyond the exceptions provided for in the Fair Use and Educational Use clauses of the U.S. Copyright Law may violate federal law. Permission to publish or reproduce is required. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship at Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. +(,121/,1( Citation: 95 Iowa L. Rev. 195 2009-2010 Provided by: William A. Wise Law Library Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline Thu Mar 2 17:47:48 2017 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: Copyright Information Formalism and Realism in Ruins (Mapping the Logics of Collapse) PierreSchlag* ABSTRACT: After laying out a conventional account of the formalism vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Mechanism, Mentalism, and Metamathematics Synthese Library
    MECHANISM, MENTALISM, AND METAMATHEMATICS SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Florida State University Editors: ROBER T S. COHEN, Boston University DONALD DAVIDSON, University o/Chicago GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University 0/ Leyden WESLEY C. SALMON, University 0/ Arizona VOLUME 137 JUDSON CHAMBERS WEBB Boston University. Dept. 0/ Philosophy. Boston. Mass .• U.S.A. MECHANISM, MENT ALISM, AND MET AMA THEMA TICS An Essay on Finitism i Springer-Science+Business Media, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Webb, Judson Chambers, 1936- CII:J Mechanism, mentalism, and metamathematics. (Synthese library; v. 137) Bibliography: p. Includes indexes. 1. Metamathematics. I. Title. QA9.8.w4 510: 1 79-27819 ISBN 978-90-481-8357-9 ISBN 978-94-015-7653-6 (eBook) DOl 10.1007/978-94-015-7653-6 All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1980 by Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland in 1980. Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1980 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any informational storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE vii INTRODUCTION ix CHAPTER I / MECHANISM: SOME HISTORICAL NOTES I. Machines and Demons 2. Machines and Men 17 3. Machines, Arithmetic, and Logic 22 CHAPTER II / MIND, NUMBER, AND THE INFINITE 33 I. The Obligations of Infinity 33 2. Mind and Philosophy of Number 40 3. Dedekind's Theory of Arithmetic 46 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Aesthetic Formalism, Reactions and Solutions
    Hekmat va Falsafe (Wisdom and Philosophy) vol.6, no.4, 2011, pp. 101-112 Aesthetic Formalism, Reactions and Solutions Khosrow Bagheri Noaparast Mohammad Zoheir Bagheri Noaparast Abstract It seems necessary to introduce the basic concepts used in this article i.e. formalism, anti-formalism and moderate formalism. Formalists believe that the aesthetic appreciation of an artwork generally involves an attentive awareness of its sensory or perceptual qualities and does not require knowledge about its non-perceptual properties. Anti-formalists on the other hand hold that none of the aesthetic properties in a work of art are formal. A number of philosophers have recently advocated a more moderate formalism. According to this view, although not all aesthetic qualities are formal, many are, and some artworks possess only formal aesthetic qualities. The quarrel among these three rival views concerns what sort of knowledge, if any, is required for appropriate aesthetic appreciation of an artwork. In what follows, we will give a brief exposition of these three viewpoints. Subsequently, we will give our preferred position with regard to these views. Keywords: Aesthetic formalism, anti-formalism, aesthetics, Nick Zangwill. 101 1. Formalism, anti-formalism and moderate formalism Before getting involved with the details of the three viewpoints, it seems necessary to introduce the notions of aesthetic and non-aesthetic properties and formal and non- formal properties. Observable properties are properties that can make a difference in our perceptual experience of the artwork. In contrast, non-observable properties refer to instances such as the artist‟s intention, the artist‟s love life, the artist‟s mental health, the artwork‟s history.
    [Show full text]
  • A Formalism for Argument Over Rules of Inference
    Tenacious Tortoises: A Formalism for Argument over Rules of Inference Peter McBurney and Simon Parsons Department of Computer Science University of Liverpool Liverpool L69 7ZF U.K. g fP.J.McBurney,S.D.Parsons @csc.liv.ac.uk May 31, 2000 Abstract Eighty years later, philosopher Susan Haack [9] took up the question of how one justifies the use of MP as a As multi-agent systems proliferate and employ different deductive rule of inference. If one does so by means of and more sophisticated formal logics, it is increasingly examples of its valid application, then this is in essence likely that agents will be reasoning with different rules a form of induction, which (as she remarks) seems too of inference. Hence, an agent seeking to convince an- weak a means of justification for a rule of deduction. If, other of some proposition may first have to convincethe on the other hand, one uses a deductive means of justi- latter to use a rule of inference which it has not thus far fication, such as demonstrating the preservation of truth adopted. We define a formalism to represent degrees across the inference step in a truth-table, one risks us- of acceptability or validity of rules of inference, to en- ing the very rule being justified. So how can one person able autonomous agents to undertake dialogue concern- convince another of the validity of a rule of deductive ing inference rules. Even when they disagree over the inference? acceptability of a rule, two agents may still use the pro- That rules of inference may be the subject of fierce posed formalism to reason collaboratively.
    [Show full text]
  • The Place of Formalism in Legal Theory, 70 N.C
    NORTH CAROLINA LAW REVIEW Volume 70 | Number 5 Article 4 6-1-1992 The lP ace of Formalism in Legal Theory Michael Corrado Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.unc.edu/nclr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Michael Corrado, The Place of Formalism in Legal Theory, 70 N.C. L. Rev. 1545 (1992). Available at: http://scholarship.law.unc.edu/nclr/vol70/iss5/4 This Comments is brought to you for free and open access by Carolina Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in North Carolina Law Review by an authorized administrator of Carolina Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ESSAY THE PLACE OF FORMALISM IN LEGAL THEORY MICHAEL CORRADO* I understand formalism to be the claim that law is an autonomous area of knowledge. To say that it is autonomous is to say that it is self- contained, that it is not dependent on other areas of knowledge like mo- rality or politics or sociology. In particular it is to say that law is not reducible to those other areas, in a sense of reducibility I will try to make clear. There is a version of formalism that is true. This version of formal- ism does not claim that law is unrelated to other areas of knowledge. It admits that legal argument makes use of moral, political, and sociologi- cal information. But it insists that, although much that is extra-legal is taken into account in deciding a question of law, it remains extra-legal; it does not become part of the law.' I.
    [Show full text]
  • What Does It Mean to Say That Logic Is Formal?
    WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT LOGIC IS FORMAL? by John Gordon MacFarlane A.B., Philosophy, Harvard College, 1991 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 1994 M.A., Classics, University of Pittsburgh, 1997 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2000 i Robert Brandom, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy (Director) Nuel Belnap, Alan Ross Anderson Distinguished Professor of Philosophy (Second Reader) Joseph Camp, Professor of Philosophy Danielle Macbeth, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Haverford College (Outside Reader) Kenneth Manders, Associate Professor of Philosophy Gerald Massey, Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy ii WHAT DOES IT MEAN TO SAY THAT LOGIC IS FORMAL? John Gordon MacFarlane, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2000 Much philosophy of logic is shaped, explicitly or implicitly, by the thought that logic is distinctively formal and abstracts from material content. The distinction between formal and material does not appear to coincide with the more familiar contrasts between a pri- ori and empirical, necessary and contingent, analytic and synthetic—indeed, it is often invoked to explain these. Nor, it turns out, can it be explained by appeal to schematic inference patterns, syntactic rules, or grammar. What does it mean, then, to say that logic is distinctively formal? Three things: logic is said to be formal (or “topic-neutral”) (1) in the sense that it provides constitutive norms for thought as such, (2) in the sense that it is indifferent to the particular identities of objects, and (3) in the sense that it abstracts entirely from the semantic content of thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic in Philosophy of Mathematics
    Logic in Philosophy of Mathematics Hannes Leitgeb 1 What is Philosophy of Mathematics? Philosophers have been fascinated by mathematics right from the beginning of philosophy, and it is easy to see why: The subject matter of mathematics| numbers, geometrical figures, calculation procedures, functions, sets, and so on|seems to be abstract, that is, not in space or time and not anything to which we could get access by any causal means. Still mathematicians seem to be able to justify theorems about numbers, geometrical figures, calcula- tion procedures, functions, and sets in the strictest possible sense, by giving mathematical proofs for these theorems. How is this possible? Can we actu- ally justify mathematics in this way? What exactly is a proof? What do we even mean when we say things like `The less-than relation for natural num- bers (non-negative integers) is transitive' or `there exists a function on the real numbers which is continuous but nowhere differentiable'? Under what conditions are such statements true or false? Are all statements that are formulated in some mathematical language true or false, and is every true mathematical statement necessarily true? Are there mathematical truths which mathematicians could not prove even if they had unlimited time and economical resources? What do mathematical entities have in common with everyday objects such as chairs or the moon, and how do they differ from them? Or do they exist at all? Do we need to commit ourselves to the existence of mathematical entities when we do mathematics? Which role does mathematics play in our modern scientific theories, and does the em- pirical support of scientific theories translate into empirical support of the mathematical parts of these theories? Questions like these are among the many fascinating questions that get asked by philosophers of mathematics, and as it turned out, much of the progress on these questions in the last century is due to the development of modern mathematical and philosophical logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Fourteen Arguments in Favor of a Formalist Philosophy of Real
    Baltic J. Modern Computing, Vol. 3 (2015), No. 1, pp. 1–15 Fourteen Arguments in Favour of a Formalist Philosophy of Real Mathematics Karlis PODNIEKS University of Latvia, Rain¸a bulvaris¯ 19, Riga, LV-1586, Latvia [email protected] Abstract. The formalist philosophy of mathematics (in its purest, most extreme version) is widely regarded as a “discredited position”. This pure and extreme version of formalism is called by some authors “game formalism”, because it is alleged to represent mathematics as a meaning- less game with strings of symbols. Nevertheless, I would like to draw attention to some arguments in favour of game formalism as an appropriate philosophy of real mathematics. For the most part, these arguments have not yet been used or were neglected in past discussions. Keywords: foundations of mathematics, philosophy of real mathematics, formalism, platonism, consistency, inconsistency 1 Introduction The formalist philosophy of mathematics (in its purest, most extreme version) is widely regarded as a “discredited and hopeless position”. This pure and extreme version of for- malism is called by some authors “game formalism”, because it is alleged to represent mathematics as a meaningless game with strings of symbols (for references, see the account by A. Weir (2011)). Nevertheless, I would like to draw attention to some arguments in favour of game formalism as an appropriate philosophy of real mathematics. For the most part, these arguments have not yet been used or were neglected in past discussions. 2 Carl Johannes Thomae as Founder of Game Formalism The idea of the game formalist foundations of mathematics can be traced to 1898 when Carl Johannes Thomae stated in his book: “The formal conception of numbers..
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics of Grammar Formalisms Seen As Computer Languages
    The semantics of grammar formalisms seen as computer languages The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Fernando C. N. Pereira and Stuart M. Shieber. The semantics of grammar formalisms seen as computer languages. In Proceedings of the Tenth International Conference on Computational Linguistics, pages 123-129, Stanford University, Stanford, California, July 2-6 1984. Published Version http://dx.doi.org/10.3115/980491.980518 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:2309658 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA The Semantics of Grammar Formalisms Seen as Computer Languages Fernando C. N. Pereira and Stuart M. Shieber Artificial Intelligence Center SRI International and Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University Abstract a declarative semantics z extended in the natural way from the declarative semantics of context-free grammars. The design, implementation, and use of grammar for- The last point deserves amplification. Context-free ma]isms for natural language have constituted a major grammars possess an obvious declarative semantics in branch of coml)utational linguistics throughout its devel- which nonterminals represent sets of strings and rules rep- opment. By viewing grammar formalisms as just a spe- resent n-ary relations over strings. This is brought out by cial ease of computer languages, we can take advantage of the reinterpretation familiar from formal language theory the machinery of denotational semantics to provide a pre- of context-free grammars as polynomials over concatena- cise specification of their meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times? David E.W
    University of North Florida UNF Digital Commons Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy Fall 2010 Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times? David E.W. Fenner University of North Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.unf.edu/aphi_facpub Part of the Esthetics Commons Recommended Citation Fenner, David E.W., "Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times?" (2010). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 2. http://digitalcommons.unf.edu/aphi_facpub/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at UNF Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UNF Digital Commons. For more information, please contact Digital Projects. © Fall 2010 All Rights Reserved Why Has Aesthetic Formalism Fallen on Hard Times? David E. W. Fenner University of North Florida 1. Introduction Nick Zangwill has done more than any person recently to resuscitate aesthetic formalism.1 I say ―resuscitate‖ because formalism has not been in favor for several decades. Zangwill writes that ―Aesthetic Formalism has fallen on hard times. At best it receives unsympathetic discussion and swift rejection. At worse it is the object of abuse and derision.‖2 The reasons many today believe aesthetic formalism is not viable have been the subject of discussion since the pendulum swing away from New Criticism, via the work of William Wimsatt, Cleanth Brooks, Clement Greenberg, André Levinson, and Heinrich Wolfflin. Most of these reasons have been discussed thoroughly, and those that I will review here that have been discussed I will spend little time reconsidering.
    [Show full text]