Categorization, Concept Learning, and Behavior Analysis: an Introduction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Categorization, Concept Learning, and Behavior Analysis: an Introduction JOURNAL OF THE EXPERIMENTAL ANALYSIS OF BEHAVIOR 2002, 78, 237±248 NUMBER 3(NOVEMBER) CATEGORIZATION, CONCEPT LEARNING, AND BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS: AN INTRODUCTION THOMAS R. ZENTALL,MARK GALIZIO, AND THOMAS S. CRITCHFIELD UNIVERSITY OF KENTUCKY, UNIVERSITY OF NORTH CAROLINA AT WILMINGTON, AND ILLINOIS STATE UNIVERSITY Categorization and concept learning encompass some of the most important aspects of behavior, but historically they have not been central topics in the experimental analysis of behavior. To intro- duce this special issue of the Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior (JEAB), we de®ne key terms; distinguish between the study of concepts and the study of concept learning; describe three types of concept learning characterized by the stimulus classes they yield; and brie¯y identify several other themes (e.g., quantitative modeling and ties to language) that appear in the literature. As the special issue demonstrates, a surprising amount and diversity of work is being conducted that either represents a behavior-analytic perspective or can inform or constructively challenge this perspective. Key words: categorization, concept learning, stimulus class, function transfer Categorization is not a matter to be taken taken place. Cognitive psychologists Laur- lightly. There is nothing more basic than cat- ence and Margolis (1999), in a book reviewed egorization to our thought, perception, ac- in the present issue, minced no words about tion, and speech. (Lakoff, 1987, p. 5) the association: ``Concepts are the most fun- Concepts give our world stability. They capture damental constructs in theories of the mind'' the notion that many objects or events are (p. 3). Yet scholars from many research com- alike in some important respects, and hence munities have struggled to come to grips with can be thought about and responded to in the complex repertoires that the topic en- ways already mastered. Concepts also allow us compasses. to go beyond the information given; for once The heterogeneity of this research area is we have assigned an entity to a class . we evident in the absence of a consensus de®- can infer some of its . attributes. (Smith & nition of the term concept (see Palmer, this Medin, p. 1) issue; Wasserman & Bhatt, 1992). Writers There is, perhaps, no larger or more di- tend to stress the importance of concepts verse literature within experimental psychol- rather than specifying their de®ning fea- ogy than that focused on categorization and turesÐperhaps, as Palmer speculates in his concept learning. This topic is, to the casual review of Margolis and Laurence (1999), ``re- observer, most directly associated with human garding the term as too familiar to need def- cognitive psychology, within which the largest inition'' (p. 598). Nevertheless, an introduc- volume of research and theory building has tion to this special issue demands at least an attempt to de®ne its subject matter. Order of authorship for this article was determined by Typically in cognitive psychology, categori- random drawing. We are grateful to the numerous re- zation is regarded as a process of determining viewers, who met the dual challenge of evaluating man- what things ``belong together,'' and a category uscripts according to JEAB's usual expectations while em- is a group or class of stimuli or events that so bracing the conceptual and methodological diversity inherent in the topic, and to the authors of the articles cohere. A concept is thought to be knowledge contained herein, many of whom invested extra effort in that facilitates the categorization process tailoring their work to an unfamiliar audience. (e.g., Barsalou, 1991, 1992). Consistent with Address correspondence to Tom Zentall at the De- the representational style of much cognitive partment of Psychology, University of Kentucky, Lexing- ton, Kentucky 40506 (e-mail: [email protected]); theorizing, conceptual knowledge is often Mark Galizio at the Department of Psychology, University portrayed as existing independently of any of North Carolina at Wilmington, Wilmington, North particular behavior±environment relation. Carolina 28403 (e-mail: [email protected]); or Tom This is assumed partly because, once a cate- Critch®eld at the Department of Psychology, Illinois State University, Normal, Illinois 61704 (e-mail: tscritc@ilstu. gorization repertoire is in place, an individual edu). may be able to categorize both previously en- 237 238 THOMAS R. ZENTALL et al. countered stimuli and novel events, suggest- departure by suggesting that ``when a group ing to some observers that the latter are rec- of objects gets the same response, when they ognized via comparison to general form a class the members of which are react- information represented in memory. Thus, ed to similarly, we speak of a concept'' (p. the goal of many studies in cognitive psy- 154). Thus, categorization may be said to in- chology is to map the knowledge that humans corporate a pattern of systematic differential presumably apply in already established pat- responding to classes of nonidentical, though terns of categorization. For example, struc- potentially discriminable, stimuli (see Fields, tured interviewing and other techniques may Reeve, et al., this issue; Wasserman & Bhatt, be used to determine what entities people in- 1992). A category is a class of stimuli that oc- clude in a category like birds; which of these casion common responses in a given context. entities are considered to be more or less typ- Such classes include stimuli involved in an ex- ical of the category; and whether hierarchical plicit learning history plus, potentially, novel relations apply to the category or instances stimuli to which the fruits of this history may within it (e.g., Rosch, 1978). transfer. Many writers use the terms category Behavior analysts are likely to regard as for- and stimulus class more or less interchange- eign this practice of describing terminal per- ably; we will follow that practice here. formance without examining the necessary When the stimuli within and between cat- and suf®cient conditions for its emergence. egories vary along relatively simple dimen- Reservations about the approach are war- sions (e.g., wavelength, size, brightness), cat- ranted. Although cognitive psychologists ex- egorization is readily conceived in the same pend much energy debating the structure terms as stimulus discrimination and gener- and contents of the knowledge that is as- alization. For example, ``Generalization with- sumed to underpin categorization and the in classes and discrimination between classesÐ means by which it is compared to new per- this is the essence of concepts'' (Keller & ceptual experiences (Laurence & Margolis, Schoenfeld, 1950, p. 155). The analytical 1999; see Palmer, this issue, for a brief syn- challenge becomes more daunting, of course, opsis of some relevant theories), their ac- as category membership is determined more counts can be dif®cult to distinguish empiri- complexly (e.g., Herrnstein, 1990). Consider, cally. Barsalou (1992) has noted a tendency as an instructive case, the balan category of for competing cognitive theories to make sim- ilar predictions and to account equally well the Australian aboriginal language Dyirbal, for data obtained from human subjects. Per- which ``includes women, ®re, and dangerous haps more important for present purposes, things. It also includes birds that are not dan- this focus on knowledge may discourage at- gerous, as well as exceptional animals such as tention to the role of experience in creating the platypus, bandicoot, and echidna'' (Lak- and maintaining conceptual behavior (Astley off, 1987, p. 5). Any plausible account must & Wasserman, 1996). also explain how categories add and lose members, merge and fracture, share mem- bers that may belong to different categories AN OPERATIONAL APPROACH under different circumstances, support the TO CONCEPT LEARNING spontaneous transfer of function from one From a behavior-analytic perspective, the member to another, and so forth. present topic provides an opportunity to ap- Some writers have gone so far as to label ply the operational analysis of psychological the capacity to glean abstract relations, such terms that Skinner (e.g., 1945) frequently es- as those that apparently unite many catego- poused. Rather than speculating about the ries, as the essence of what it means to be status of hypothetical knowledge structures, it human (e.g., see Deacon, 1997). Regardless is possible to examine the circumstances un- of whether conceptual repertoires are der which we speak of conceptualizationÐ uniquely human (many articles in the present that is, what individuals are doing when they issue suggest that they are not), they are are said to behave conceptually, and how they clearly among the most interesting behavioral came to behave in that way. Keller and phenomena available for study. Because of Schoenfeld (1950) speci®ed this very point of their richness, generativity, and adaptability, CATEGORIZATION AND CONCEPT LEARNING 239 they invite a thorough experimental and the- examples and nonexamples of category oretical analysis. members (Barsalou, 1991). The goal is ``to Unfortunately, categories and concepts establish high degrees of control over cate- have been addressed only sporadically within gory knowledge'' (Barsalou, 1992, p. 31), behavior analysis. This neglect may be under- with knowledge operationalized more or less stood partly as a rejection of the cognitive as above. Such paradigms, which are com- theoretical
Recommended publications
  • Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal) Libraries at University of Nebraska-Lincoln July 2005 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Hamilton College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac Part of the Library and Information Science Commons Herold, Ken R., "Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information" (2005). Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal). 27. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac/27 Library Philosophy and Practice Vol. 3, No. 2 (Spring 2001) (www.uidaho.edu/~mbolin/lppv3n2.htm) ISSN 1522-0222 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Systems Manager Burke Library Hamilton College Clinton, NY 13323 “My purpose is to tell of bodies which have been transformed into shapes of a different kind.” Ovid, Metamorphoses Part I. Library Philosophy Provocation Information seems to be ubiquitous, diaphanous, a-categorical, discrete, a- dimensional, and knowing. · Ubiquitous. Information is ever-present and pervasive in our technology and beyond in our thinking about the world, appearing to be a generic ‘thing’ arising from all of our contacts with each other and our environment, whether thought of in terms of communication or cognition. For librarians information is a universal concept, at its greatest extent total in content and comprehensive in scope, even though we may not agree that all information is library information. · Diaphanous. Due to its virtuality, the manner in which information has the capacity to make an effect, information is freedom. In many aspects it exhibits a transparent quality, a window-like clarity as between source and patron in an ideal interface or a perfect exchange without bias.
    [Show full text]
  • Misunderstanding Davidson by Martin Clifford Rule
    MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON BY MARTIN CLIFFORD RULE Submitted to the graduate degree program in Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. _________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. _________________________________ Ben Eggleston, Professor. _________________________________ Eileen Nutting, Assistant Professor. _________________________________ Clifton L. Pye, Associate Professor. _________________________________ John Symons, Professor. Date Defended: 07/12/2016 ii The Dissertation Committee for Martin Clifford Rule Certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: MISUNDERSTANDING DAVIDSON ________________________________ Chairperson Dr. John Bricke, Professor of Philosophy Emeritus. Date approved: 07/12/2016 iii ABSTRACT The main aim of this dissertation is to offer, and to defend, an interpretation of Donald Davidson’s classic paper “Mental Events” which interpretation I take to be identical to Davidson’s intended interpretation. My contention is that many readers misunderstand this paper. My method for showing this will be, first, to give a brief summary of the surface structure, and the core concepts, of “Mental Events”. I will then begin to canvas exemplars of the main lines of (alleged) objection to what “Mental Events” has been supposed to contend. I intend to argue that these objections misunderstand either Davidson’s conclusions, or his arguments, or they require material additional to the position that Davidson actually lays out and argues for in “Mental Events” in order to follow. In the latter case I shall attempt to show that these additions are not contentions which Davidson shares by referencing further materials from Davidson’s work.
    [Show full text]
  • Dual Categorization and the Role of Aristotle's Categories
    Dual Categorization and the Role of Aristotle's Categories Mark Ressler August 6, 2008 Abstract In the Categories, Aristotle addresses two different cases of dual cat- egorization, cases in which the same thing might appear in two different categories: relatives and secondary substances in the first case, qualities and relatives in the second. His treatment of these two cases is markedly different. Ackrill thinks dual categorization poses a dilemma for Aris- totle's project as a whole, but I argue that there is a dilemma only on particular understandings of Aristotle's purpose in compiling the list of categories. I investigate various interpretations of the categories to find one that explains Aristotle's reactions to dual categorization, and sug- gest an interpretation of the peculiar four-fold system of classification in Chapter 2. Can one thing appear in two separate categories? It seems to me that this question cannot be answered without determining the purpose for which the categories are established. If such dual categorization causes no problems ac- cording to the intended purpose of the categorial scheme, then there seems to be no reason for complaint. This is the approach that I take with regard to Aris- totle's categorial scheme in the Categories. In this work, Aristotle addresses two separate instances of dual categorization with regard to his list of ten cate- gories, but his reaction in these cases is surprisingly different, taking great pains to avoid dual categorization in one case, but showing a marked lack of concern in the other case. This indifference in the second case leads John Ackrill to criticize Aristotle's categorial project in general; however, it seems to me that if Aristotle's reaction to dual categorization in one case seems contrary to some conception of Aristotle's purpose in developing the categorial scheme, then per- haps that conception of the purpose of the Categories may not be a conception that Aristotle himself held.
    [Show full text]
  • The Importance of Categorization
    CHAPTER 1 The Importance of Categorization Many readers, I suspect, will take the title of this book as suggesting that women, fire , and dangerous things have something in common-say, that women are fiery and dangerous. Most feminists I've mentioned it to have loved the title for that reason, though some have hated it for the same rea­ son. But the chain of inference-from conjunction to categorization to commonality-is the norm. The inference is based on the common idea of what it means to be in the same category: things are categorized together on the basis of what they have in common. The idea that categories are defined by common properties is not only our everyday folk theory of what a category is , it is also the principaltechnicaltheory-one that has been with us for more than two thousand years . The classical view that categories are based on shared properties is not entirely wrong. We often do categorize things on that basis. But that is only a small part of the story. In recent years it has become clear that categorization is far more complex than thaI. A new theory of categoriza­ tion, called prototype theory, has emerged. It shows that human categori­ zation is based on principles that extend far beyond those envisioned in the classical theory. One of our goals is to survey the complexities of the way people really categorize. For example, the title of this book was in­ spired by the Australian aboriginal language Dyirbal, which haS a cate­ gory, balan, that actually includes women, fire , and dangerous things.
    [Show full text]
  • Dharmakirti, Davidson, and Knowing Reality
    Comparative Philosophy Volume 3, No. 1 (2012): 30-57 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org DHARMAKĪRTI, DAVIDSON, AND KNOWING REALITY LAJOS L. BRONS ABSTRACT: If we distinguish phenomenal effects from their noumenal causes, the former being our conceptual(ized) experiences, the latter their grounds or causes in reality ‘as it is’ independent of our experience, then two contradictory positions with regards to the relationship between these two can be distinguished: either phenomena are identical with their noumenal causes, or they are not. Davidson is among the most influential modern defenders of the former position, metaphysical non-dualism. Dharmakīrti’s strict distinction between ultimate and conventional reality, on the other hand, may be one of the most rigorously elaborated theories of the opposite position, metaphysical dualism. Despite this fundamental difference, their theories about the connection between phenomena and their noumenal causes are surprisingly similar in important respects. Both Dharmakīrti in his theory of ‘apoha’ and Davidson in his theory of ‘triangulation’ argued that the content of words or concepts depends on a process involving at least two communicating beings and shared noumenal stimuli. The main point of divergence is the nature of classification, but ultimately Dharmakīrti’s and Davidson’s conclusions on the noumenal-phenomenal relationship turn out to be complementary more than contradictory, and an integrative reconstruction suggests a ‘middle path’ between dualism and non-dualism. Keywords: Dharmakīrti, Donald Davidson, apoha, triangulation, reality, meta-ontology, subjectivity, metaphysical dualism 1. INTRODUCTION What can we know about reality? If two communicating beings are both aware of a certain black queen chess piece as evidenced by their reference(s) to that black queen chess piece in their communication, does that imply that there ‘really’ is (something that is) that black queen chess piece? At least there must be something causing the shared awareness.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Representation in Leibniz
    PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ by Stephen Montague Puryear B.S., Mechanical Engineering, North Carolina State University, 1994 M.A., Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2000 M.A., Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Stephen Montague Puryear It was defended on December 5, 2005 and approved by Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy Stephen Engstrom Associate Professor of Philosophy J. E. McGuire Professor of History and Philosophy of Science Dissertation Director: Nicholas Rescher University Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright °c by Stephen Montague Puryear 2006 iii PERCEPTION AND REPRESENTATION IN LEIBNIZ Stephen Montague Puryear, Ph.D. University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Though Leibniz’s views about perception and representation go to the heart of his philosophy, they have received surprisingly little attention over the years and in many ways continue to be poorly understood. I aim to redress these shortcomings. The body of the work begins with an exploration of Leibniz’s proposed analysis of representation (Chapter 2). Here I argue that on this analysis representation consists in a kind of structural correspondence— roughly an isomorphism—between representation and thing represented. Special attention is given to the application of this analysis to the challenging cases of linguistic and mental representation. The next two chapters concern what I take to be the central issue of the work: the nature of distinct perception.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Eastern Division New York December 2009
    APA Eastern Division New York December 2009 LATE MEDIEVAL NOMINALISM AND NONVERIDICAL CONCEPTS Claude Panaccio University of Quebec at Montreal Content externalism, as promoted by Hilary Putnam, Tyler Burge and many other prominent analytic philosophers in the last three or four decades, is the thesis that the content of our thoughts at a given moment is not uniquely determined by our internal states at that moment. In its causalist versions, it has often been presented as a deep revolution in philosophy of mind. Yet a number of medievalists (e.g. Peter King, Calvin Normore, Gyula Klima, and myself) have recently stressed the presence of significant externalist tendencies in fourteenth century nominalism, especially in William of Ockham and John Buridan. I have tried to round up the case for this interpretation of Ockham in a forthcoming paper entitled “ Ockham‟s externalism ”. Let me simply mention here, to give the most salient example, that Ockham insists, in Book II of his Commentary on the Sentences, that an intuitive cognition, whether intellectual or sensitive, always has a determinate singular thing as its object, although taken in itself it resembles a plurality of singular things, and that what fixes which singular object it is that a given intuitive cognition is a cognition of, is not the internal shape of this cognition, but which determinate thing caused it [Reportatio II, quest. 12-13, Op. Theol. V, 287-288]. Two intuitive cognitions, then, could be maximally similar to each other to the point of being indistinguishable by an observing angel ; yet, they would have different singular objects if they were caused by different singular things.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Meanings of Categorization: a Conceptual Analysis of Research on Person Perception
    DOI: 10.1111/spc3.12336 ARTICLE Four meanings of “categorization”: A conceptual analysis of research on person perception Andre Klapper1 | Ron Dotsch1,2 | Iris van Rooij1 | Daniel Wigboldus1 1 Radboud University Nijmegen Abstract 2 Utrecht University It is widely assumed that people tend to “categorize” other people. Correspondence “ ” Andre Klapper, Donders Institute for Brain, However, the term categorization has been used with qualitatively Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University different underlying definitions in the person perception literature. Nijmegen, Nijmegen, The Netherlands. We present a conceptual analysis in which we disentangle four Email: [email protected] existing definitions: (a) categorization as representing, (b) categori- zation as dichotomizing, (c) categorization as organizing, and (d) Funding information categorization as grouping. Subsequently, we show that seemingly Nederlandse Organisatie voor Wetenschappelijk Onderzoek, Grant/Award antagonistic viewpoints in the literature may be reconciled by Number: 464‐11‐036 disentangling these definitions. Furthermore, we argue that disentangling these definitions is vital for theoretical interpretations of (past and future) empirical findings. Overall, our work aims to contribute to the clarity of person perception theories, provide novel perspectives on existing debates, and serve as a stepping stone for more differentiated models of person perception. KEYWORDS categorization, conceptual analysis, social perception, stereotyping 1 | INTRODUCTION People spontaneously categorize other people and use the knowledge that is associated with those categories to guide their behavior. For example, upon encountering another person, we may immediately categorize the person as a “policeman,” infer that the person may have a relatively dominant personality, and adjust our behavior to be respectful to the other person. This is how the person perception process has been characterized by social categori- zation models.
    [Show full text]
  • Forum: the Philosophy of Classification
    Knowl. Org. 39(2012)No.1 29 Forum: The Philosophy of Classification Forum: The Philosophy of Classification The Concept of Concept: Concepts and Terms† Alberto Marradi University of Florence and Buenos Aires <[email protected]> Since 1986 Alberto Marradi has been professor of Methodology of the Social Sciences in the University of Florence. From 1981-86 he was professor of Methodology of the Political Sciences in the University of Bologna. He is a regular visiting professor in social sciences at the University of Buenos Aires. His research interests lie in philosophy of knowledgeand the social sciences, methodology of social re- search, and cultural anthropology. He was responsible for the Schools of Excellence programme of the Italian Sociological Association (2000-2008). Since 2004 he has chaired Paideia, an association of Italian academicians and intellectuals who denounce the present lamentable state of education and culture in Italy. Marradi, Alberto. The Concept of Concept: Concepts and Terms. Knowledge Organization, 39(1), 29-54. 221 references. ABSTRACT: The concept of concept has seldom been examined in its entirety, and the term very seldom defined. The rigidity, or lack thereof, and the homogeneity, or lack thereof, of concepts, are only two of their characteristics that have been debated. These issues are reviewed in this paper, namely: 1) does a concept represent its referent(s), or is it a free creation of the mind?; 2) can a concept be analyzed in parts or elements?; 3) must a concept be general, i.e., refer to a category or a type, or can it refer to a single object, physical or mental?; 4) are concepts as clearly delimited as terms are? Are concepts voiceless terms?; and, 5) what do terms contribute to an individual’s and a community’s conceptual richness? As regards the relationship of concepts with their referents in the stage of formation, it seems reasonable to conclude that said relationship may be close in some concepts, less close in others, and lacking altogether in some cases.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Violence in the Philosophy of Aristotle
    SHS Web of Conferences 72, 01024 (2019) https://doi.org/10.1051/shsconf /20197201024 APPSCONF-2 019 The concept of violence in the philosophy of Aristotle Sergei Borisov, Viktor Rimsky, Roman Ivashina, Igor Lyashenko Belgorod State National Research University, 308015, Belgorod, Russia Abstract. The idea that the concept of 'violence' was part and is still viewed as part of a broad philosophical category may seem strange. However, the problem is resolved by referring to the concept of 'force,' which is lost in modern philosophy. The exception was the works in which we find some “traces” of this concept, including the works of Aristotle, which need to be free from modernizing interpretations. Still, in the translations of Aristotle, the Greek word δύναμις, used in its traditional meaning of potentiality, lost its connotations of force (movement, capability, function); in turn, 'force' was no longer linked with 'violence' (βια) and 'necessity.' Violence is seen as a kind of necessity, which is associated with the suppression of 'will,' freedom, something 'frustrating desire' and contrary to 'common sense,' as well as the absence of 'good.' Violence is presented not only in an ontological sense, but also existentially, as the opposite of 'good' and one's own 'desire.' Force stays in the background of 'necessity' as 'potentiality', 'potential energy' and 'movement', and violence loses the opposition that has arisen in the ontological mode. Introduction Initially, we turned to the hermeneutics of the texts of Aristotle in the existing Russian translations, trying to give our own understanding of violence in the modern philosophical context in view of its categorical inadequacy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of the Nominalist Movement on the Scientific Thought of Bacon, Boyle? and Locke
    The Influence of the Nominalist Movement on the Scientific Thought of Bacon, Boyle? and Locke by John Richard Milton A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the University of London, Department of Humanities, Imperial College of Science and Technology September 1982 - 2 - Abstract This thesis is an investigation of the influence of the nominalist philosophy of the later Middle Ages on the natural philosophy (including metaphysics) and epistemology of Francis Bacon, Robert Boyle and John Locke. Because of the general reluctance of any of these thinkers to quote or make other references to any medieval or modern authors it is impossible to establish with any useful degree of probability which nominalist philosophers they had read. It can, however, be shown that Bacon, Boyle and Locke all accepted the kind of basic nominalist principles which William of Ockham and his successors had enunciated, and moreover that their acceptance of these principles influenced many of their other philosophical and scientific beliefs. Chapter 1 contains a general discussion of the traditional problem of universals and its philosophical implications. Chapter 2 is concerned with ancient and medieval nominalist theories and with their subsequent influence. Chapters 3 and 4 deal respectively with Bacon and Boyle; the former shows the connection between Bacon's inductive theory of method and his nominalist metaphysics; the latter discusses the influence of nominalist and voluntarist ideas on Boyle's conception of nature. Chapter 5 discusses nominalist influences in Locke's early work, up to and including the Drafts for the Essay written in 1671. Chapter 6 is concerned with the develop- ment of Locke's thought between 1671 and 1690, and with the general question of Locke's sources.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction Smiles, talks, runs, arrivals and departures, births and deaths, thunder and lightning: the va- riety of the world seems to lie not only in the assortment of its ordinary and less ordinary inhabitants—animals and physical objects, or perhaps minds, sets, atoms—but also in the sort of things that happen to or are performed by them. In the last three decades this view has been a focus of considerable debate in philosophy, with implications reaching far into the concern of other disciplines as well (above all linguistics and cognitive science). It is a view that many authors have accepted, mostly on account of the prominent role played by the concept of event in the formulation and analysis of a wide variety of philosophical is- sues. However, there has not been much agreement as to the precise nature of such entities, and a range of alternative theories (along with a corresponding variety of identity and indi- viduation criteria for events) have been put forward. This volume brings together a selection of essays that have deeply influenced this debate, paving the way to an understanding of the role played by events in our representation of the world. The material is organized in five sections: (i) the role of events in the logical analysis of natural language; (ii) the metaphysical status of events; (iii) their identity and individua- tion criteria; (iv) their role in the analysis of space, time and causality; and (v) the distinction and classification of various types of events and event-like entities (such as processes and states).
    [Show full text]