<<

Beyond Realism Seeking the Divine Other

A Study in Applied

Simon Smith

SERIES IN

Copyright © 2017 Vernon Press, an imprint of Vernon Art and Science Inc, on behalf of the author.

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Vernon Art and Science Inc. www.vernonpress.com

In the Americas: In the rest of the world: Vernon Press Vernon Press 1000 N West Street, C/Sancti Espiritu 17, Suite 1200, Wilmington, Malaga, 29006 Delaware 19801 Spain United States

Series in Philosophy

Library of Congress Control Number: 2017943308

ISBN: 978-1-62273-225-8

Product and company names mentioned in this work are the trademarks of their respective owners. While every care has been taken in preparing this work, neither the authors nor Vernon Art and Science Inc. may be held responsible for any loss or damage caused or alleged to be caused directly or indirectly by the information contained in it.

For my parents, Mary and Eric Smith and Charlie Reilly (1938-2014) To live in hearts we leave behind Is not to die.

Table of contents

Preface i

Abbreviations Used in this Work v

Acknowledgements vii

Introduction 1

Summary of the Argument 16

Chapter One The Incoherence of Realism 23

Innocent Realism: Review and Overview 25

Language and Realism 31

Empiricism and Realism 38

Grace Jantzen and ‘Relativist Transcendence’ 43

The Passive Observer 50

Theistical Realism and Theodicy 56

Chapter Two Process : A Post-Modern Metaphysic 71

The Language of Process 73

The Ontology of Creativity and the Analogy of Consciousness 79

Equiprimordiality and Necessity 93

Behaviourism, Existentialism, and Process Metaphysics 107 Process and Pragmatism 115

Chapter Three Prior Actuality and the Divine Playwright 121

High Transcendence and Prior Actuality 124

The Playwright Allegory 133

Theology and the Personal Analogy 144

The Trinity as Social Reality 156

The Story So Far 165

Chapter Four Gazing into the Glass of God 169

The Embodiment of Agency 174

In the Birthplace of Being 188

Anthropology and Anthropomorphism 199

A Psychology of Belief 204

Overcoming Abstractions 213

Reinvesting Consciousness, Reconstructing Theology 223

Bibliography 237

Notes 247

Index 323

Preface

The meaning of “talk about God” remains the first and most fundamental issue facing philosophers and theologians in the modern age. This study concerns the analogies needed to make sense of that talk: images, ripe with poetic intensity, borrowed from the language and practice of faith; from the splicing together of lives, human and divine. It concerns, moreover, the reinvestment of those images in the structures of human personality, their role in the development of a renewed metaphysic of the human spirit, aspirationally divine or ‘upwardly’ oriented.

Such concerns have, in recent years, gained still greater urgency as a popular and aggressive ‘evangelical atheism’ has come to dominate religious discourse, threatening to obscure the human truth of religious language. The challenge is a familiar one; its polemic deeply indebted to British Empiricism and, perhaps, especially the Logical Positivism of the last century. It seems that those who put their faith in post-modern theories of language to silence the likes of Ayer and Russell spoke too soon.

In response, theism has retreated from empiricist attack into a new- found realism. Championed by the likes of Peter Byrne, William Alston, and of course, Richard Swinburne, neo-realist metaphysics has, ostensibly, steeped itself in classical philosophy. Amid the search for reason and necessity, the God of grace and providence, of ordinary belief, has been forced to yield to ‘Perfect Being’ thinking, Absolute Being ontology, and other forms of untenable metaphysics, with few alternatives on the margins of relevance. The God of the philosophers may have the virtue of necessity, but this Being’s temperament remains essentially anti- social. With God successfully held in logical quarantine, we may well wonder whether “God-talk” means anything at all.

To close the breach and realign finite with Infinite, philosophical faith with practical piety, has become the most pressing problem in contemporary philosophical theology. Undoubtedly, Whitehead and his neo-classical followers have been quick to learn the lessons of British Empiricism. If anything, however, they learned them too well, placing the religious emphasis almost exclusively on natural, physical forces. So

ii Preface

seamless an alignment of God with Creation can be of little comfort to the ordinary believer.

Caught between inflationary transcendence and reductive empiricism, the ‘gap’ between theological speculation and religious belief has widened until neither side seems very concerned with the other. Cleaving to ‘first principles’ and other metaphysical abstractions, both classical and neo- classical theologians have disenfranchised the faithful, putting faith on a trajectory for atheism.

To steer a course between such extremes, I want to return to an earlier tradition; to a metaphysic of persons exemplified in the practice of faith. Doing so draws upon the logic of personal identity: what it means to be, or rather, to become , a person.

This is the practical application of a cutting-edge theology, the progeny of one of the twentieth century’s last great metaphysical minds. Almost fifty years after his death, Austin Farrer remains in the vanguard of modern theology, his vital grasp of faith and philosophy unequalled and unrivalled. Farrer first defended theology against the excesses of positivist and then process reduction but he used them to drive his own retreat from the scholastic tradition. This was analysed at great length by Charles Conti in Metaphysical Personalism .

Locating the means and motive for revision in the experience and expressions of lived faith, Farrer supplied the vital corrective; there is nothing more one can say about an overweening impersonalism which describes God as Ens per se , so cuts its own throat by depersonalising the cosmological connection.

It is my supposition, on Farrer’s behalf, that person-concepts meet the pragmatic demands of both metaphysical theism and realistic belief. So doing, they open up a more fertile route between orthodox and ‘process’ mythologies. Following that route, I begin with the incoherence of philosophical realism and its ruinous application to theism. From there, we journey backwards into neo-classical and neo-Thomist thinkers who themselves attempted to overcome realist abstractions. Our destination lies in a Feuerbachian anthropology of theology or ‘anthropotheism’. Like Farrer, Ludwig Feuerbach used the language of the believer to relocate theology and philosophy within a framework which makes fertile use of anthropomorphic personifications to ‘think’ God.

Ultimately, revisiting the personalist presuppositions of metaphysics in this way throws light on questions of personal identity, which is to

Preface iii

describe the nature of an ‘overview’ existence directly related to or experienced in ourselves. This is to ‘draw’ reality on a grand-scale and, most importantly, locate our place within that image. Doing theology dynamically, or psychologically informed – as both Farrer and Feuerbach insisted we must – means recognising the constitutive role projections play in self-construction. Without conscious, active, or intentional participation in our projects, we cannot become persons at all. This returns us to the practice of faith wherein Feuerbach’s anthropology is reconstructed as applied theology, thus completing the personalist metaphysics perpetuated by Farrer as initially developed by the Biblical faith in a Godly person. And what greater challenge can religious philosophy respond to today?

ii

Abbreviations Used in this Work

Works by Farrer:

GV The Glass of Vision . Westminster: Dacre Press, 1948.

FI Finite and Infinite . Westminster: Dacre Press, 1959.

FW The Freedom of the Will . New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1960.

SB Saving Belief . : Hodder & Stoughton, 1964.

SG A Science of God? London: Geoffrey Bles Ltd, 1966.

LAIU Love Almighty and Ills Unlimited . London & Glasgow: The Fontana Library, 1966.

FS Faith and Speculation . London: Adam & Charles Black, 1967.

Works by others:

MP Conti, Charles. Metaphysical Personalism . : Clarendon, 1995.

EC Feuerbach, Ludwig. The Essence of Christianity , translated by George Eliot. New York: Harper & Row, 1957.

PPF Feuerbach, Ludwig. Principles of the Philosophy of the Future , translated by M. H. Vogel. Cambridge: Hackett. 1986.

DP Henderson, Edward. ‘The Divine Playwright’ in The Personalist Forum 12, no. 1 (1996), 35-80.

vi Abbreviations Used in this Work

SFA Henderson, Edward. ‘The Supremely Free Agent’ in Human and Divine Agency: Anglican, Catholic, and Lutheran Perspectives , edited by F. Michael McLain and W. Mark Richardson, 97-120. Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1999.

PR Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality , Corrected Edition, edited by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. New York: Free Press, 1978.

Acknowledgements

A word or two of profound thanks is due, perhaps even overdue, to all those who, in their own inimitable ways, helped me to bring this project to fruition at long, long last. First among them, is, of course, Charles Conti. Without the access he provided to a wealth of material, much of which remains unpublished, this book would have been much shorter. Without his guidance, his personal investment in my work and myself, it would not have been written at all. No less deserving of thanks, are the editors at Vernon Press, Argiris Legatos and Carolina Sanchez for their assistance, advice, and patience; all very deeply appreciated. Closer to home, a considerable debt of gratitude is owed to those friends and colleagues who have, both philosophically and personally, sustained my will and nourished my spirits: Tom Buford and James Beauregard, for exemplifying friendship and the meaning of human being; the British Personalist Forum, in particular Richard Allen, Alan Ford, Anna Castriota, Karl Simms, and Benjamin Bâcle, for providing the community without which the human soul can only wither; and the Research Hippies in the University of Surrey Library for doing what they could to preserve my sanity and suppress those unsavoury personal habits one is liable to cultivate during extended periods of isolation. I am also indebted, and deeply so, to my dear departed friend, Mr Pickle, whose editorial advice was as timely as it was perspicacious. More than any other, thanks are due to Orla Smith, for whom everything I have and do is but a poor return for everything she has done for me.

They have all shown, many times over, the living truth of that philosophy of persons I have tried to express in this book. I am grateful to them for their support and encouragement in its preparation. Reader, do not judge them harshly.

Introduction

Introductions are never quite what they seem. Appearances notwithstanding, they rarely begin at the beginning. 1 Contrariwise, and disdaining the King of Hearts naïve linearity, they begin at the end, go on to the beginning, then stop. (Alice would, no doubt, have guessed as much anyway.) This is because introductions are the last links in a chain of thought. (Although the length of this particular chain may not be immediately obvious, it will, I hope, soon become so.) Coming at the end – and before the beginning, in proper Wonderland fashion – introductions look backwards and forwards at the same time. They are a summation and a prediction: project and projection in one.

That makes this much more than my first and last chance to catch your attention before we disappear down a rabbit-hole of philosophical reflection. It is an opportunity to plant a few signposts, to offer my view of what is to follow.

In fact, the displaced nature of introductions is, at once, a most important signpost and illustration of some of the key themes of this book. For, on one level, this is a study in the development of consciousness, of personal identity. It concerns our projects – religious, theological, and philosophical – and the ways in which our participation in them shapes who we are and what we become. Philosophers call this the dialectics of consciousness, the logic of what it means to be or, more importantly, to become a person. Introductions make that logic explicit by closing the circle of enquiry and, yes, opening it simultaneously. They bring the enquirer face-to-face with himself, a former self; another incarnation. (Best to start with incarnational images: end as we mean to go on, in resurrection-mode.) The beginning and end of a kind of hermeneutic, introductions mark the place where first impressions coincide with final reflections, yours and mine, ushering us both into the self-critical and so transformative dialectic that is to come. As Ludwig Feuerbach might have said, such reflections tell us to our face what we are and how we came to be. 2 They tell of aspirations, of constructive complementarities, of debts owed and the measure to which they have been repaid. They reveal, in other words, the creative involvement of one consciousness, one person,

2 Introduction

in the becoming of another. This, in Martin Buber’s poignant phrase, is the ‘cradle of real life’. 3

There is a pragmatic psychology in this natal place; one which is essential to both philosophy and theology in their healthier, inclusivist modes. Essential, too, to both the form and content of this book. Philosophically speaking, this is because that psychology is the antidote to the debilitating dualisms from which much western thought has derived itself. Antiquated oppositions – mind and body, transcendence and immanence, and doubtless most damaging of all, them and us – are realigned within a framework in which we are intimately reconnected to one another.

This insight was the particular contribution of Austin Marsden Farrer, Oxford philosopher and theologian, Anglican priest, and primary subject matter of the present work. As any theology student knows, the roots of it strike deeper into both scripture and speculation. On the one hand, parallels may be found in Aquinas as well as the writings of St. Francis and Bonaventure. 4 On the other, there is a clear, if unexpected, connection with Ludwig Feuerbach’s anthropology of theology, his ‘anthropotheism’. It is, however, the flowering of this idea in Farrer and those who followed him with which this study is concerned. (Feuerbach is the exception and for good reason, as we shall see.)

For readers unfamiliar with Farrer’s extraordinary corpus, a brief introduction may be in order. 5

Austin Marsden Farrer was one of the last great metaphysical thinkers of the twentieth century. In the words of the late Basil Mitchell – philosopher, friend, and colleague – Farrer was ‘one of the most remarkable men of his generation’. 6 ‘[O]riginality, independence, imagination and intellectual force to a degree amounting to genius’ were (Mitchell assures us) the hallmarks of Farrer’s thought and character. Genius, then; ‘and the word was sometimes used of him’. John Hick agreed. The reader who tarries in such elevated company, he avowed, is bound ‘to lose any taste for the lower levels of theological writing’: those drier depths of modernist and post-modernist thought alike, which have come lately to dominate. 7 To Charles Conti, our foremost Farrerian scholar, this was ‘a mind as philosophically gifted as it was theologically rare’. 8

Farrer is, without doubt, the most important Anglican theologian since John Henry Newman, another Anglo-Catholic but of a somewhat different

Introduction 3

persuasion. Newman, as everyone knows, entered fully into Catholic theology and there he would remain. Farrer, on the other hand, concluded his neo-Catholic or “high” Anglican interlude by returning to his pragmatic roots, and there he would remain. In so doing, he kept faith to the fullest with the communitarian interests celebrated by his former tutor at Balliol, . 9 Those interests, he would further cultivate in his own philosophical theology, endowing them with greater metaphysical extensions.

Those extensions reveal a remarkable and captivating insight into the perennial, and indeed, primordial , questions of philosophy and theology. Farrer showed himself to be uniquely alive to the demands of both disciplines, ‘keeping heart and head in dynamic balance’; 10 alive, too, to the fullest implications of doing so: a clue to their vital role in the becoming of persons. Guided by a profound grasp of human nature, he brought ‘passion to bear on philosophy…aligning integrity with religion.’ His challenge to the standard articles of Christian tradition was never less than penetrating. It was also timely. Against the grain of contemporary Positivism, Farrer refused to surrender the most difficult aspects of the faith out of which he philosophised. Rich in philosophical wisdom and psychological insight, faith (he firmly believed) is central to the deepest understanding of a humanity love-oriented unto a God of love. He himself may not have used the language of ‘feeling tone’, Gefuhl , or passion, but it was there for those with eyes to see and ears to hear.

Acutely sensitive to this, the meaning of human being, Farrer resisted the temptations of cultural relativism and the worst excesses of the post- modern turn; he ‘did his theology metaphysically, approaching his task in the manner of philosophia perennis ’. 11 Anthropologically astute, his attention to the most vital topics of philosophical concern gives his work an enduring importance to modern thinkers who philosophise out of the human condition; the more so to those who enquire after matters of lasting significance and transcendental import.

To those thinkers, he offers the essential connection of thought and action embodied by the life of faith. Sermons resonate beautifully with philosophical writings, reminding us that praxis supplies the conditions by which theoria must be judged. Philosophers tend to reverse this, making inappropriate logical demands on more basic social interactions. But Farrer held fast to the fundamental conditions of active belief and, crucially, to the epistemic requirements of the simple believer. 12 Make no mistake, he said, ‘[i]f we are not tough enough to assert that the act of

4 Introduction

religious obedience is our privileged access to the knowledge of God, we shall be beaten out of the field’.13 Hick aptly termed this ‘rationality illuminatingly at work within the life of faith’. 14 It means Farrer understood that any faith worth living must be capable of being thought and any philosophy worth thinking must be capable of being lived. This gives his work an unusual metaphysical edge, overcoming traditional philosophical polarities: rationalism-cum-realism versus empiricism, idealism, and pragmatism.

That is why, on finding that ‘the ancient rift between the God of the philosophers and the God of religion remained as wide as ever,’ the process theologian John Cobb was ready to add, ‘if anyone came close to closing it, it was Austin Farrer.’ 15 Like Cobb, I am inclined to think Farrer succeeded, not least because he ‘kept faith with reason, in both senses.’

So go the pragmatic interpenetrations of praxis and theoria . More profitable than anything else on the philosophical market, this offers a way of doing philosophy and theology that is far more original and more fertile than the thinking that currently dominates the field. Both subtly anthropological and traditionally analogical, it contrasts sharply with the neo-realist revival of modern theology. Theology as construal is, of course, the vital factor, just as it was for Hegel and the entire Continental tradition; though it remains starkly, and sadly, absent from analytic philosophy and realist ontology.

Such is the vision I want to reflect here.

Heart and head; thought and action; praxis and theoria ; faith and reason: it should be obvious by now that Farrer’s stock-in-trade was not the things or substances commonly beloved of metaphysical minds. Nor was it the “first principles” that bind them. He dealt, instead, in dynamic interplay. Indeed, one might say that he washed his philosophy in the waters of life at Bethesda, baptising his constructs with living imagery: A Rebirth of Images , in the title-words of one of his works. Applied to that most ancient and honourable question of philosophical debate, “the nature of mind”, this puts Farrer at the cutting-edge of philosophy and theology.

His conception of mind as physically embodied, socially extended was radical at the time of its formulation; quite as revolutionary as Ryle’s The Concept of Mind .16 And yet if that conception has not hitherto received the attention or recognition it deserves, this is not, perhaps, entirely surprising. A prevailing climate of British empiricism, which produced

Introduction 5

Logical Positivism in the formative years of the last century and computational theories of mind in its senescence, was unlikely to foster spiritual sensibilities or offer a sympathetic ear to the overtures of consciousness. Nevertheless, ideas which Farrer first began to forge in the central chapters of his magnum opus , Finite and Infinite – before his put them firmly at the centre of philosophical theology – have, in recent years, begun to swim in the mainstream. They appear to have found a place in the latest discussions of “embodied cognition,” a development of the cognitive sciences which may turn out to be crucial. Hints abound, moreover, that neuroscientists may also be about to catch up with Farrer.

Does it seem odd that a scientific and essentially reductive approach to mind should adopt a position close to Farrer’s social and spiritually sensitised one? Perhaps it should not. This is not to suggest that there has been anything like a wholesale appropriation of his ‘metaphysical personalism’ (as Conti dubbed it). 17 Nevertheless, it seems somehow fitting that such ideas would re-emerge in another dynamic interplay of disciplines, this time philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience. How well these developments account for the subtle logic of intentionality and its place in the social and physical realisation of mind remains to be seen. However, leaving theology out may, as the poet suggests, ultimately mean they reckon ill. 18

What, in particular, they will ‘reckon without’, one suspects, is what philosophers always reckon without: the very interplay that configures, indeed makes possible, their own enquiries. (For a profession that seeks to penetrate the deepest truths of existence, philosophy has, of late, produced remarkably few practitioners of the Delphic art, gnothi seauton .)

The old Russellian school of philosophy was forced to throw a rickety analogical bridge between the self and other minds.19 Not everyone was willing to cross over. For some, the opportunity to deny that there is anything on the other side has been far too tempting: an all too human reflection of the scepticism which theists know all too well. The difficulty was and always has been obvious. The evidence offered for the reality of another (or an Other) is judged by external criteria. Supposedly, I know that you are a person, a consciousness, like me precisely because you appear to be like me. You behave like me : you walk and talk, read books, watch television, sing and dance, wine and dine, and generally do all the things that consciousnesses do. (Although not, one assumes, all at the same time.) But this is all wrong: both the reasoning and the evidence

6 Introduction

reasoned from. For, as everyone knows (or almost everyone, as we shall discover) there is a world of difference between appearance and reality. So goes the antediluvian argument between realism and idealism.

The sceptics may have a point as far as they go, but their demand for ontological security and the reassurances of what they purport to be “proper philosophic method” is no less flawed. Their analogical bridge- breaking can issue only in a self-stultifying denial of the other because, by simply refusing the analogy any purchase, they too failed to ask the right question. The right question is “How did we come by the analogy in the first place?”

How do I know what consciousness looks or behaves like? From my own case, rebounds the echo of ego-certainty. Perhaps; but in such truisms, lurk the dangers of pernicious circularity. How did I come to be a consciousness capable of recognising its reflection in others? Where, in fact, did “my own case” come from? Where else, P. F. Strawson observed, if not those others? A “case” is not a single integer. Arguments “from” are really arguments “back to”; they return us, by another full turn of the circle, to the simple ontological facts of human existence. So we plumb de facto logic to see how we become a talking mind in the first place.

Indeed, logical philosophers will doubtless aver that we have known as much since Strawson and Wittgenstein located the primary conditions for any thought at all, not in the individual, but in those who taught us how to think. The form of argument, the very language in which the sceptic frames his or her doubts, cannot, in all conscience, be claimed as a new invention. In making use of it, one is entirely, if unconsciously (worse, perhaps even thoughtlessly), reliant on ‘the other’ whose existence one may claim to doubt. Just here, pernicious circularity unfurls as self- contradiction. 20

There is a lesson in honesty here which, if I may say so, is urgently needed in philosophy, not to mention the physical sciences. I cannot help but wonder who made you the remarkable thinker you undoubtedly have become. If asked, would you, in the manner of the old joke, choose to take the blame yourself? Be warned, however, self-made minds indict their origins no less than those who recognise their debts and seek to honour them.

Farrer clearly recognised the constitutive role others play in our development. The idea appears in all his major works, most notably Finite and Infinite and The Freedom of the Will . The former was first published in

Introduction 7

1943, a good furlong ahead of both Strawson and Wittgenstein. Unfortunately, that book saw the theological application of this idea overwhelmed by the ontological demands of a more traditional . The result was a classical deployment of action-concepts: God as Actus Purus casting before it the shadow of Real Being. Working out that concept of mind, or rather of persons, in The Freedom of the Will , Farrer would use a full-blooded interactionism to purge the residue of classical absolutism from his theology. By privileging anthropology over usiology , he realigned metaphysics with the demands of religious belief. This led to the “pragmatic theology” of Faith and Speculation .

In this, his last major work, theological application returned explicitly to its anthropological and psychological roots (somewhat as I am attempting to do here). Unearthing those roots, it becomes clear that, as vital as their corrective contribution was, logical philosophers had still somehow missed the point. After all, Farrer observed, ‘[i]t is not as though we believed in our neighbour’s personality because logical philosophers are able to exhibit the self-contradiction involved in denying it’. 21 Such intellectual conceit surely adds the insult of unnecessary demonstration to the injury of inexcusable doubt: bad faith atop faulty inference. “The other” is no philosophical puzzle for rational minds to solve but a matter of real practical urgency. ‘From first infancy our elders loved us, played us, served us and talked us into knowing them’. Had they failed us, we simply would not be.

No need, then, for arguments or analogies to the other (inside). Those who had and held us have already and inexorably bound themselves into our every experience of consciousness. We are who we are by their grace and gift; wherein, St. Paul reminds us, works the grace of God. 22 Others give us the tools with which to make or ‘mend’ ourselves (as Eugene O’Neill suggests) using that same grace as ‘glue’. 23 They give us the language, the symbols, in which we think our thoughts and through which we live our lives. The hand of any great teacher may, indeed must , be perfectly hidden (just like, Farrer said, the hand of God), the ‘causal joint’ between teacher and student, utterly indiscernible.24 So much so that it is easy to forget; or worse, we ignore it, whitewashing others from our biographical reminiscences. 25 We do so to our own shame, however; for all we do we owe to them, in recognition of them. Such connections are not merely logical. ‘Otherness’ is a feature of philosophical schematics and social semantics. First and foremost, the relation is lived in so known by its social demonstrations.

8 Introduction

Philosophically and theologically pregnant, Farrer’s social semantics provide most of us with all the evidence we ever need to discern the reality of others. As conditions of knowledge, they are quite sufficient: in philosophical parlance, adequate but not necessary so not absolutely and unambiguously certain. Demand more, however, and the risks are clear; for we are the selves we are by living our belief in others. 26 Deny the transactions embodied by that belief and we are not persons at all, only ‘mindless imbeciles…innocent of all communication.’

This alone might be enough to put Farrer in the vanguard of a new philosophy. Forty-five years after his death, his “counter-episteme” still offers a vital corrective to those who pursue their enquiries without due regard to their role in the psycho-dynamics of personal identity. Rather than press into service an untenable epistemology and an unfathomable ontology, 27 as rationalists are wont to do, he distilled an empirical mandate from this basic description of persons seeking connections and explanations. That mandate overcomes traditional realist ontologising (as we shall see in Chapter One) by reconnecting us in dynamic interplay, one with another (and perhaps ultimately an Other).

Conceiving consciousness as actively extended or “agency- personified” is of fundamental importance to any intelligible theology. It is a vital clue to the meaning of “talk about God” and the cosmological relation, reminding us that both of these are human truths. At its simplest, it works like this. Real “being” is primitively experienced in action; the self – any self – is publicly enacted. No ontological deficiency, as traditional thinkers fear; sociality is the quiddity of consciousness: substance, essence, existence, all in one. Mentality is first transacted between persons. An essential expression of “soulful” social conjunctions, ‘[m]ind does everywhere flow into mind.’ 28 In practice this means that, just as ordinary believers find their own thoughts spelled out in scripture, so Farrer himself would philosophise out of the Living Word.

That, in quite a sizeable nutshell, provides the means for conceiving a real confluence between natural and spiritual. A more creative way of reintegrating finite and infinite, it splices together the very threads by which our ‘plaints’ once reached an Other’s ear, but lately snapped (as Thomas Hardy avers) by our own hands. 29 In so doing, it lays the foundation for a new personalist metaphysic.

The reality of an Other given in the shaping of a mind, a life, is as much a truth of pragmatic theology as of philosophical psychology. For the same dynamic interplay which constitutes personal becoming is at once our

Introduction 9

best analogy for and most sublime expression of the realities of faith. Best and most sublime because the application-point of the analogy lies in the enactment of the spirit there expressed. So we may both cognise the hidden hand of God and recognise the signature of ‘His’ handiwork. 30 This, Farrer well knew, makes our return to the Other a matter of direct personal experience, embedding therein a cosmological connectedness which blossoms in the providential care of a nurturing other. It puts the will of God back in the hands of those who seek to put themselves in its way. The hidden-ness of the divine/human complementarity thereby blooms in the very acts that inspirit us. In so doing, those acts meet bodily the epistemological and psychological conditions of faith. Herein lies the solution to what has become known as the “problem of double-agency”. Profitably rewriting Levinas, then, we might say that faith is first philosophy. 31

But now consciousness of such connections and the debts they imply tempts me to go further, to run the risk of saying too much. Let us be bold and make the matter plain. Let us say, unequivocally, those connections supply the analogy for ‘the God about whom we have something to do.’ 32

And there is always so much to do, not least because this analogy is not merely an analogy. It is not an arbitrary image or convenient cipher, side- by-side with the reality it symbolises. In fact, it is something we cannot do without because it is the form of our interpersonal relations, and so the form of consciousness itself. 33 It is, moreover, the form that divine/human complementarity takes: a direct encounter – the only one we are ever likely to have – with a Will working itself out in the development of consciousness. It is the very stuff of Creation.

It is also the stuff of faith, is it not? In the life of Christ, our theory of persons finds concrete expression. The Son is given to represent the Father in a fiercely demonstrative analogue for grace and providence. 34 Here, too, the analogue is no more a cipher than ‘He’ is a theoretical construct or psychic projection. In this manifestation of kenotic dynamism, we find the blood and bones of divine outreach, the enactment of love and sacrifice. Is that not, after all, what Christian faith demands of us: to redouble the analogy, recapitulate the symbolism, and imitate the Son as much as in our power lies? Not so much a symbol, then; but more, as C. S. Lewis might have said, a sacrament. 35

To say it plainer still, we strive to put what we are pleased to call “our theory of persons” (human and divine) into practice and live the analogy of interpersonality. Even, or especially, here and now. We rely on it, you

10 Introduction

and I, to unlock the content of this book, to articulate the development of consciousness, of friendship, of love; a transformation upon which the yearned-for response utterly depends. Properly understood, as Conti has put it to me, we set the matrix of social-cum-metaphysical connections trembling with spiritual anticipation, the Other syncopating with the fixing-points of a web that vibrates in every strand. Circumincessio .

In sober philosophical tones, this is the dialectic of a religious consciousness; that is, consciousness passing itself through hallowed images of infinite otherness, a sacramental self re-enacting the place of a holy Other in the name of that Other. By such anthropo-psychological insights would Farrer change the face of modern metaphysics, bearing ‘in the hand of love’ (the saints remind us) the mirror of its own highest ideals. 36

Conti himself provides a prime example of those insights in action, putting theory into practice and vice versa. This is, perhaps, not surprising since he too has followed this path, in vigorous pursuit of personal transformations and social syncopations.

Having encountered Finite and Infinite while still at Princeton, Conti found his thoughts written in Farrer’s hand, so devoted a lifetime’s study to a mind that reflected his own. The reverberations of that encounter continued even into the hereafter. The teacher participated in this, his last doctoral student’s development, far beyond the teacher’s mortal span. In response, the student amplified the gifts of his teacher, blurring the line of creative complementarity still further. The end result was an exhaustive – and surely definitive – exegesis in the shape of Metaphysical Personalism .37

Focusing on the evolution of Farrer’s thinking between Finite and Infinite and Faith and Speculation , Metaphysical Personalism sought (successfully, I believe) to rebut the common misconception of this as a shift from orthodox apologetics to Wittgensteinian fideism. In fact, Farrer took a far more subtle intellectual journey, so was able to offer a more robust and consistent philosophical engagement with questions of theology. That journey represents a progressive attempt to reconcile transcendental presuppositions with the realities of religious practice. Therein lie the social and spiritual connections which drove his own development.

Sociality implies moral agency and moral agency supplies theology with a concrete analogy for transcendence. The transactions of

PAGES MISSING

FROM THIS FREE SAMPLE

Bibliography

Abelson, Raziel. ‘Because I Want To’ in Mind , vol.74, no. 296 (1965), 540- 553.

Agee, James and Huston, John. The African Queen . Film. Directed by John Huston. Los Angeles: United Artist Films, 1951.

Alston, W. P. A Realist Conception of Truth . Ithaca, London: Cornell University Press, 1996.

Anscombe, G. E. M. Intention . Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1976.

Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologiæ: A Concise Translation , edited by Timothy McDermott. London: Methuen, 1991.

Austin, J. L. Philosophical Papers , edited by J. O. Urmson & G. J. Warnock. Oxford: Clarendon, 1961.

Ayer, A. J. Language Truth and Logic . Harmondworth: Penguin Books, 1946.

Asimov, Isaac. ‘Runaround’ in I, Robot . London: Gollancz, 1990.

Barth, Karl. ‘An Introductory Essay’ in The Essence of Christianity , translated by George Eliot, x-xxxii. New York: Harper & Row, 1957.

Beattie, Tina. New Catholic Feminism: Theology and Theory . Oxford: Routledge, 2006.

—. Interview with Jenni Murray. Woman’s Hour . BBC Radio 4, 31 st January 2006.

Buber, Martin. Between Man and Man . London: Collins, 1961.

—. The Way of Response: Martin Buber; Selections from his Writings , edited by N. N. Glatzer. New York: Schocken Books, 1966.

238 Bibliography

—. Meetings , edited by Maurice Friedman. Chicago, La Salle: Open Court, 1973.

—. I and Thou , translated by trans. Ronald Gregor Smith. Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1996.

Buford, Thomas O. Trust, Our Second Nature . Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2009.

—. Know Thyself, An Essay in Social Personalism . Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2011.

—. ‘Personalism’ in Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy , accessed 26/02/2016, www.iep.utm.edu/personal/.

Byrne, Peter. God and Realism . Aldershot: Ashgate, 2003.

Conti, Charles. Descriptive Metaphysics: An Examination of Austin Farrer’s Use of Cosmological Inference (D. Phil. Thesis). Oxford, 1973.

—. ‘Austin Farrer and the Analogy of Other Minds’ in For God and Clarity, New Essays in Honour of Austin Farrer , edited by Jeffrey C. Eaton and Ann Loades, 51-91. Pennsylvania: Pickwick, 1983.

—. Metaphysical Personalism . Oxford: Clarendon, 1995.

—. ‘The Author Responds’ in The Personalist Forum 12, no. 1 (1996) 81- 121.

—. ‘God as Other (Feuerbach on the Psychology of Religion)’. Lecture delivered at the University of Glasgow, 3 rd February 2003.

—. ‘Appeal for a Theological Regenitorum ’ unpublished; quoted with permission of the author.

Copleston, F. C. Aquinas . Harmondsworth: Pelican Books, 1961

Crombie, I. M. ‘The Possibility of Theological Statements’ in Faith and Logic , edited by Basil Mitchell, 31-83. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1958.

Bibliography 239

de Beauvoir, Simone. The Second Sex , translated and edited by H. M. Parshley. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1972.

Devitt, Michael. Realism and Truth , Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997.

Descartes, Rene. Selected Philosophical Writings , translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge: CUP, 1993.

Eaton, Jeffrey C. The Logic of Theism: An Analysis of the Thought of Austin Farrer . Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1980.

Farrer, Austin. The Glass of Vision , Dacre Press, 1948.

—. ‘A Starting-Point for the Philosophical Examination of Theological Belief’ in Faith and Logic , edited by Basil Mitchell, 9-30. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1958.

—. ‘Revelation’ in Faith and Logic , edited by Basil Mitchell, 84-107. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1958.

—. Finite and Infinite , 2 nd Edition. Westminster: Dacre Press 1959.

—. The Freedom of the Will (The Gifford Lectures for 1956-1957). New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1960.

—. ‘Old Age: Why Do We Have To Bear It?’, delivered to the Portsmouth Abbeyfield Society, reprinted in the North End Review , July 1964.

—. Saving Belief . London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1964 .

—. A Science of God? London: Geoffrey Bles Ltd, 1966.

—. Love Almighty and Ills Unlimited . London & Glasgow: Fontana Library, 1966.

—. Faith and Speculation . London: Adam & Charles Black, 1967.

—. A Celebration of Faith , edited by Leslie Houlden. London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1970.

240 Bibliography

—. Reflective Faith , edited by Charles Conti. London: SPCK, 1972.

—. Interpretation and Belief , edited by Charles Conti. London: SPCK, 1976.

—. The Brink of Mystery , edited by Charles Conti. London: SPCK, 1976.

Feuerbach, Ludwig. The Essence of Christianity , translated by George Eliot. New York: Harper & Row, 1957.

—. The Principles of the Philosophy of the Future , translated by M. H. Vogel. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Co. 1986.

—. The Essence of Religion , translated by Alexander Loos. New York: Prometheus Books, 2004.

Findlay, J. N. ‘Can God’s Existence Be Disproved?’ in New Essays in Philosophical Theology , edited by A. G. N. Flew and A. C. MacIntyre, 47-56. London: SCM Press, 1955.

Flew, Antony. ‘Theology and Falsification’ in New Essays in Philosophical Theology , edited by A. G. N. Flew and A. C. MacIntyre, 96-99. London: SCM Press, 1955.

—. The Presumption of Atheism and other Philosophical Essays on God, Freedom and Immortality . London: Pemberton, 1976.

—. God: A Critical Enquiry/God and Philosophy , 2 nd Edition. LaSalle, Ill: Open Court, 1984.

Freud, Sigmund. Totem and Taboo . London: Routledge, 2004.

Hampshire, Stuart. Thought and Action . Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983.

—. Innocence and Experience. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1992.

Hartshorne, Charles. Beyond Humanism: Essays in the New Philosophy of Nature . New York: Willett, Clark and Co., 1937.

Bibliography 241

Hartt, Julian. ‘Austin Farrer as Philosophical Theologian: A Retrospective and Appreciation’, in For God and Clarity, New Essays in Honour of Austin Farrer , edited by Jeffrey C. Eaton and Ann Loades, 1-22. Pennsylvania: Pickwick, 1983.

Harvey, Van A. Feuerbach and the Interpretation of Religion . Cambridge: CUP,1995.

Hick, John. Philosophy of Religion . Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall, 1963.

—. An Interpretation of Religion . Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1989.

Hegel, G. W. F. Phenomenology of Spirit , translated by A. V. Miller. Oxford: OUP, 1977.

Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time , translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. London: SCM Press, 1962.

Henderson, Edward. ‘The Divine Playwright’ in The Personalist Forum 12, no. 1 (1996), 35-80.

—. ‘The Supremely Free Agent’ in Human and Divine Agency: Anglican, Catholic, and Lutheran Perspectives , edited by F. Michael McLain and W. Mark Richardson, 97-120. Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1999.

Hepburn, Ronald W. Christianity and Paradox . London: C. A. Watts & Co., 1958.

—. ‘From World to God’ in The Philosophy of Religion , edited by Basil Mitchell, 168-178. Oxford: OUP, 1971.

Hibbard, Bill. ‘The Technology of Mind and a New Social Contract’ in Journal of Evolution and Technology 17, no. 1 (2008).

James, William. The Writings of William James , edited by John J. McDermott. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977.

242 Bibliography

—. ‘Is Life Worth Living’ in The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy , 32-62. New York, London, Bombay: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1897.

Jantzen, Grace M. Becoming Divine: Towards a Feminist Philosophy of Religion . Manchester University Press, 1998.

—. God’s World, God’s Body . London: Darton, Longman & Todd, 1984.

Kamenka, Eugene. The Philosophy of Ludwig Feuerbach . London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970.

Kenny, Anthony. Wittgenstein . Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1976.

—. Aquinas . Oxford: OUP, 1980.

Kilby, Karen. Karl Rahner. London: Fount, 1997.

Kojeve, Alexandre. Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, Lectures on the Phenomenology of Spirit , assembled by Raymond Queneau, edited by Alan Bloom, translated by James H. Nichols. Ithaca, London: Cornell University Press, 1980

Kristeva, Julia. ‘Stabat Mater’ in Tales of Love , translated by Leon S. Roudiez, 234-264. New York: Columbia University Press, 1987.

Lacan, Jacques. Ecrits , translated by Alan Sheridan. London: Routledge, 1997.

Laing, R. D. Self and Others . Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1972.

—. The Divided Self . Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1974.

Levinas, Emmanuel. The Levinas Reader , edited by Seán Hand. Oxford: Blackwell,1997.

Lowth, Karl. From Hegel to Nietzsche , translated by David E. Green. New York: Anchor Books, 1967.

Malinowski, Bronislaw. Sex and Repression in Savage Society . London: Routledge, 1961.

Bibliography 243

Maritain, Jacques. The Person and the Common Good . Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1947.

McCulloch, Greg. Using Sartre: An Analytical Introduction to Early Sartrean Themes . London: Routledge, 1994.

Mitchell, Basil. ‘Overview and Analysis’ in The Personalist Forum 12, no. 1 (1996), 1-10.

Murdoch, Iris. Sartre, Romantic Rationalist . London: Fontana, 1967.

Nagel, Thomas. The Last Word . Oxford: OUP, 1997.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science , edited by Bernard Williams, translated by Josefine Nauckhoff. Cambridge: CUP, 2001.

Otto, Rudolph. The Idea of the Holy . Oxford: OUP, 1950.

Phillips, Adam. Side Effects . London: Hamish Hamilton, 2006.

Phillips, D. Z. Death and Immortality . London: Macmillan, 1970.

—. The Concept of Prayer . Oxford: Blackwell, 1981.

Pinkard, Terry. Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason . Cambridge: CUP, 1994.

Ratzinger, Joseph (Pope Benedict XVI). ‘Address to the German Bishops, 21 st August 2005’. The Vatican, http://www.vatican.va/holy- _father/benedict_xvi/index.htm.

—. ‘Angelus, St Peter’s Square 4 th December 2005’. The Vatican, http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/index.htm.

—. ‘Address to the Writers of the College of La Civiltá Cattolica 17 th February 2006’. The Vatican, http://www.vatican.va/holy- _father/benedict_xvi/index.htm.

—. ‘Homily Delivered by the Holy Father in Warsaw on the 26 th May 2006’. The Vatican, http://www.vatican.va/holy- _father/benedict_xvi/index.htm.

244 Bibliography

—. ‘Address to the Bishops of the Episcopal Conference of Canada- Ontario on their ad limina visit, 8 th September 2006’. The Vatican, http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/index.htm.

Richardson, Mark W. ‘A Look at Austin Farrer’s Theory of Agency’ in Human and Divine Agency: Anglican, Catholic, and Lutheran Perspectives , edited by F. Michael McLain and W. Mark Richardson, 121-148. Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1999.

Ricoeur, Paul. Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation , translated by Denis Savage, Yale University Press, 1970.

Russell, Bertrand. An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth . Harmondworth: Penguin Books, 1962.

—. Why I Am Not A Christian . London: Unwin Books, 1967.

—. ‘Analogy’ in Essays on Other Minds , edited by Thomas O. Buford. Illinois: University of Illinois Press, 1970, 3-8.

Reade, W. H. V. The Christian Challenge to Philosophy . London: SPCK, 1951.

Reese, William L. Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion: Eastern and Western Thought , Expanded Edition. New York: Humanity Books, 1999.

Roberts, Richard H. A Theology on Its Way? Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1991.

Rout, Paul. Francis and Bonaventure . London: Fount, 1996.

Ryerson Charles A. ‘An Imminent Transcendence’ in The Princeton Seminary Bulletin XVI, no. 3 (1995), 313-26.

Ryle, Gilbert. The Concept of Mind . London: Hutchinson, 1960.

Sartre, Jean-Paul. No Exit , translated by S. Gilbert. New York: Vintage Books, 1989

—. Being and Nothingness , translated by Hazel E. Barnes. London: Routledge, 1995.

Bibliography 245

Schedler, Norbert Oscar. Methodology in the Metaphysics of Theism: a Philosophical Analysis of the Method of Austin Farrer and Ian Ramsey , (Ph.D. Thesis). Princeton, 1967.

Shipley, J. T. Dictionary of Word Origins . New York: Philosophical Library, 1945.

Smith, Anne-Marie. Julia Kristeva: Speaking the Unspeakable . London: Pluto Press, 1998.

Strawson, P. F. Individuals . London: Methuen & Co. 1959.

—. Introduction to Logical Theory . London: Methuen & Co., 1952.

Stead, G. C. ‘How Theologians Reason’ in Faith and Logic , edited by Basil Mitchell, 108-131. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd, 1958.

Tanney, Julia. ‘Rethinking Ryle: A Critical Discussion of The Concept of Mind ’ in , The Concept of Mind, 60 th Anniversary Edition . Oxford: Routledge, 2009.

Torrance, Steve. ‘The “Drop-Out Question” and the Emergence of Artificial Consciousness’. Presentation delivered at 3 rd AISB Workshop: The Emergence of Consciousness , London, May, 2013.

Waismann, Friedrich. ‘Verifiability’ in The Theory of Meaning , edited by G. H. R. Parkinson, 35-60. Oxford: OUP, 1968.

—. ‘ The Resources of Language’ in The Importance of Language edited by Max Black. Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall, 1962.

Wartofsky, Marx W. Feuerbach , Cambridge: CUP, 1982.

Whitehead, Alfred North. Adventures of Ideas . Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1948.

—. Process and Reality , Corrected Edition, edited by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. New York: Free Press, 1978.

246 Bibliography

Williams, Thomas D. and Bengtsson, Jan Olof, ‘Personalism’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = .

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations , translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell, 1953.

—. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus , translated by D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness. London: Routledge, 1974.

PAGES MISSING

FROM THIS FREE SAMPLE

Index

Being-just-being-itself, 128, 140, A 141, 146, 294 A contingentia mundi , 112, 129, Binitarianism, 304 281, 291, 295, 316 Buber, Martin, 2, 93, 189, 200, Absolute Being, 24, 148, 175, 224 207, 220, 223, 296, 319, 322 Activist epistemology, 4, 24, 27, Buford, Thomas O., 254 42, 50, 61, 69, 82, 99, 102, 121, 136, 155, 159, 178, 189, 199, C 223, 231, 263, 275, 284, 287, Cobb, John, 4 290, 291, 294, 299, 302, 306, Consciousness as la valeur , 196, 308, 320, 325 197, 198 Actus Purus , 7, 116, 117, 126, 131 Consciousness as self-critical Analogy, 61, 67, 72, 105, 115, dialectic, 310 125, 132, 137, 145, 154, 165, Consciousness, embodiment in 174, 216, 224, 234, 280, 282, action, 5, 8, 23, 31, 47, 49, 50, 287, 289, 294, 295, 297, 302 71, 114, 122, 126, 128, 129, Anthropic principle, 177, 311 137, 142, 145, 148, 150, 154, Anthropomorphism, 66, 92, 117, 163, 177, 214, 261, 265, 279, 174, 202, 213, 215, 218, 219, 280, 284, 286, 289, 292, 298, 235, 269, 302, 325 299, 300, 301, 309, 312, 314, Aquinas, Thomas, 2, 85, 147, 316, 327 149, 158, 294, 295, 302, 303 Consciousness, interpersonal Aristotle, 132, 149, 216, 265, 299, development of, 7, 172, 173, 309, 317 175, 191, 202, 204, 208, 213, Austin, J. L., 34, 62, 63, 258, 261, 254, 314, 317, 321, 323, 327 262, 268, 275, 276, 288 creative participation in others, 7, Ayer, A. J., 24, 40, 58, 76, 86, 141, 11, 209, 210, 226, 227, 232, 258 234, 239, 254 B theological application, 9, 125, 145, 162, 165, 223, 224, 225, Bad faith, 7, 198, 218 227, 228, 232, 234, 239, 308, Barth, Karl, 171, 307 324 Beattie, Tina, 317, 321 Consequent Being, 72, 94, 112, 116, 117, 126, 273

324 Index

Copleston, F. C., 94, 284 Hick, John, 2, 4, 259 Correspondence theory of High Transcendence, 124 language, 36, 43, 44 Creatio ex nihilo , 72, 82, 95, 96, I 119, 123, 124, 127, 128, 290 Idealism, 93, 181, 188, 202, 209, D 238, 323 Incarnation, 143, 157, 161, 162, De Beauvoir, Simone, 14, 15, 317 231, 232, 233, 236, 326 Deus Absconditus , 98 Intentionality, hairsbreadth, 121 Diagrammatic fictions, 102, 103, Intentionality, logic of, 113, 121, 153, 165, 318 139, 142, 165, 178, 272, 286, Dualism, 26, 38, 48, 50, 63, 260 289, 297, 298 Ipsum Esse , 74, 108, 132, 147 E J Epiphenomenalism, 48, 87, 279 Esse est operari , 52, 81, 101, 114, James, William, 92, 93, 103, 264, 123, 136, 146, 147, 154, 195, 282, 285, 287, 318, 323 219, 290, 294, 309, 313 Jantzen, Grace M., 43 Evil, 64, 65, 70 K F Kamenka, Eugene, 171, 307 Filter theory of language, 27, 63 Kristeva, Julia, 213

G L

God’s eye view, 37, 43, 102, 147 Lacan, Jacques, 197, 215, 216 Laing, R. D., 315 H Language-games, 23 Levinas, Emmanuel, 9, 194, 197, Hampshire, Stuart, 33, 49, 50, 54, 207, 319, 327 62, 258, 260, 261, 263, 275, 286 Logical Positivism, 3, 5, 23, 71, Hartshorne, Charles, 125, 229, 91, 95, 108, 133, 258, 306 289, 292 Harvey, Van, 171 M Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 4, 189, 231, 238, 272, 303, 306, Maritain, Jacques, 247, 253 307 Mitchell, Basil, 2, 125, 255, 288, Hegelian dialectic, 189, 275 289, 290

Index 325

Murdoch, Iris, 196, 197, 315 Praxis , 3, 4, 13, 64, 92, 94, 118, 119, 124, 144, 146, 157, 176, N 202, 204, 207, 225, 233, 235, 273 Natura naturans , 73, 97, 112, Predestination, 159 117, 119 Presuppositional logic, 113, 122, Naturalist reduction, 58, 60, 106, 138, 149, 152, 164, 195, 203, 109, 112, 114 211, 212, 219, 281, 326 Naturalistic fallacy, 59, 124, 138, Primordial Being, 72, 81, 82, 83, 139, 218 108, 112, 115, 116, 118, 272, Necessary Being, 219, 220, 221, 273, 277, 293 235, 291, 293, 294, 322 Prior actuality, 108, 115, 121, Non-self-explanatory-ness, 59, 124, 133, 138, 145, 163, 172, 60, 112, 119, 131, 136, 139, 201, 221, 232, 282, 297, 328 213, 218, 222, 239, 281, 287, 309, 320 Q No-ownership theory of mind, 72, 111, 113, 189, 271 Quine, W. V. O., 33, 37, 86

O R

Onto-theology, 174, 175, 177, Russell, Bertrand, 5, 42, 94, 95, 203, 218, 220, 221, 222, 223, 281, 283 231, 323 Ryle, Gilbert, 5, 72, 252, 291 Open texture, 35, 36, 38, 78, 88 Ordo cognoscendi , 195, 236, 301 S Ordo essendi , 86, 195, 236 Other minds, knowledge of, 7 Sartre, Jean-Paul, 98, 108, 196, by analogy, 5 219, 238, 315 Other Minds, knowledge of Spaltung , 216 Scepticism, 6 Strawson, P. F., 6, 7, 47, 72, 110, Other possible worlds, 67, 270, 113, 177, 253, 258, 261, 271, 324 286

P T

Patriarchal epistemologists. See Thatness (or Thereness), 33, 95, Phal-logo-centric projection 141, 194 Phillips, Adam, 312 Theodicy, 64, 65, 66, 269 Phillips, D. Z., 58, 218, 276 Thereness (or Thatness), 35, 141 Porositat der Begriffe , 35

326 Index

Trinity, 123, 157, 299, 302, 303, Via analogia , 25, 83, 85, 86, 101, 304 316

U W

Usiology , 7, 294, 305 Waismann, Friedrich, 34, 35, 36, 275 V Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 6, 7, 23, 28, 38, 63, 205, 258, 272, 276, Verificationism, 57, 92, 262, 265 319