Acquaintance and Assurance

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Acquaintance and Assurance Philos Stud DOI 10.1007/s11098-011-9747-9 Acquaintance and assurance Nathan Ballantyne Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Abstract I criticize Richard Fumerton’s fallibilist acquaintance theory of nonin- ferential justification. Keywords Acquaintance Á Noninferential justification Á Assurance Á Skepticism Á Regress Á Richard Fumerton Should the acquaintance theorist be committed to fallibilism or infallibilism? Richard Fumerton (2010) and Ted Poston (2010) have recently discussed that question. Poston has argued that there is trouble for the acquaintance theorist either way—the theory faces a dilemma—and Fumerton has responded to Poston by defending a fallibilist acquaintance theory of noninferential justification. Here, I shall offer a new objection to the theory Fumerton defends. Fumerton claims that ‘‘[w]hen everything that is constitutive of a thought’s being true is immediately before consciousness, there is nothing more that one could want or need to justify a belief’’ (2001, p. 14). ‘‘What more,’’ asks Fumerton, ‘‘could one want as an assurance of truth than the truth-maker before one’s mind?’’ (2006a, p. 189). Yet Fumerton also grants that false beliefs can enjoy noninferential justification. This admission, I’ll contend, brings trouble for the acquaintance theorist whenever she asks whether she has assurance for a belief. In what follows, I shall outline Fumerton’s notion of philosophical assurance (Sect. 1) before turning to state his account of noninferential justification (Sect. 2), describing how assurance is a critical motivation for the acquaintance theory. Then I will argue that if the acquaintance theorist endorses fallibilism, as Fumerton does, N. Ballantyne (&) Philosophy Department, Fordham University, Collins Hall 101, 441 E. Fordham Road, Bronx, NY 10458, USA e-mail: [email protected] 123 N. Ballantyne acquaintance provides no assurance (Sect. 3). I’ll conclude by considering an objection to my argument (Sect. 4). 1 Assurance Central to Fumerton’s notion of philosophical assurance is a particular conception of the philosophical enterprise. Fumerton observes that in commonplace inquiry, we assume that we know about the past by memory, the future by inductive inference, and the external world by perception. But once we turn to philosophy, Fumerton continues, ‘‘we stop getting gifts. We must justify what we normally do not bother to justify’’ (2001, p. 19). What is involved in having philosophical assurance that a particular belief is true? According to Fumerton, satisfying philosophical curiosity yields assurance. To see what is involved in satisfying curiosity, consider Fumerton’s example of a child pestering a parent with ‘why’ questions (e.g., ‘‘Why is the sky blue?’’ or ‘‘Why can’t you tickle yourself?’’): The looming regress of ‘‘Why?’’ questions inevitably ends with an impatient parent responding ‘‘That’s just the way it is,’’ a response that, no doubt, did little to satisfy the child’s curiosity. The epistemologist…wants to know why we can legitimately conclude that a certain way of forming a belief is legitimate, and the epistemologist’s philosophical curiosity isn’t going to be satisfied by being told at any stage of the game that it just is. (2006a, p. 184) Fumerton connects satisfying one’s curiosity about the truth of a belief and obtaining assurance. Someone has assurance if her curiosity is satisfied. Fumerton’s thought is that if someone is acquainted with the truth-maker for a belief, then her curiosity is fully satisfied and she thereby has assurance. ‘‘What is relevant to getting the assurance one wants as a philosopher,’’ Fumerton says, is getting the truth-maker for the belief ‘‘before one’s consciousness’’ (2006a, p. 189). Consider a representative passage from Fumerton (where the proposition in question is his pet example, I am in pain): The fact that I am acquainted with is the very fact that makes P true. The very source of justification includes that which makes true the belief. In a way it is this idea that makes an acquaintance foundation theory so attractive. I have no need to turn to other beliefs to justify my belief that I am in pain because the very fact that makes the belief true is unproblematically before conscious- ness… Again, everything one could possibly want or need by way of justification is there in consciousness. (2001, p. 15, cf. 2006a, p. 189, 2004, pp. 81–82) Let us say that someone is philosophically satisfied, in Fumerton’s sense, with respect to believing P only if she has an answer to the question, Why think that P is true?; someone is philosophically unsatisfied so long as she has no answer to that question. Even if this question about the truth of P is answered, the answer itself may raise a new question—Why think this answer is true? And the new question 123 Acquaintance and assurance brings with it further curiosity. If the chain of ‘why’ questions ends with the confession, ‘‘That’s just the way it is, kid,’’ curiosity remains. Fumerton makes it clear that he seeks assurance that precludes curiosity: ‘‘the epistemologist’s philosophical curiosity,’’ he says, ‘‘isn’t going to be satisfied by being told at any stage of the game that it just is.’’ If someone is fully satisfied, then she has philosophical assurance for believing that P. The notions of philosophical satisfaction and assurance raise some questions. Is the satisfaction of curiosity an objective or a subjective, thinker-relative matter? Different philosophers seem to have different thresholds for satisfaction, and what satisfies one might not satisfy another. What satisfied Thomas Reid1 or G.E. Moore, for instance, won’t satisfy the likes of Descartes or a Pyrrhonian skeptic. Is someone seeking to be completely satisfied more likely to reach truth or avoid error than someone who isn’t? Why would anyone want assurance? I will leave these questions aside, turning now to Fumerton’s account of noninferential justification and its connection to assurance. 2 Fallibilist noninferential justification by acquaintance Fumerton’s account of noninferential justification has two main parts. First, he proposes a condition for noninferentially justified belief that entails truth. According to this condition, someone is noninferentially justified in believing that P if (but not only if2) she is acquainted with the following: the belief that P, the fact that P, and the relation of correspondence between the belief that P and the fact that P. Fumerton says that acquaintance is a sui generis relation that holds between a thinker and a fact or property; and correspondence is also a sui generis relation. Neither notion can be analyzed using other (simpler) concepts.3 It is important to appreciate how this first part is linked with assurance. Imagine that Buxtehude is in pain and that he believes as much. And suppose he is acquainted with the belief that he is in pain, the pain itself, and the relation holding between the belief and the pain. Buxtehude is then ‘‘directly aware’’ of the truth- 1 A common foil in Reid’s writings, the Skeptic, sounds downright Fumertonian at moments: ‘‘There is nothing so shameful in a philosopher as to be deceived and deluded; and therefore you ought to resolve firmly to withhold assent, and to throw off all this belief of external objects, which may be all delusion’’ (An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense VI, xx). For more on Reid’s Skeptic, see Wolterstorff (2001, chapter VIII, esp. 185–192). 2 Some commentators have taken Fumerton to offer a necessary condition for justification—not merely a sufficient condition, as I’ve stated it. These commentators read the ‘‘if’’ as ‘‘only if’’ (see Plantinga (2001, p. 60)) or ‘‘if and only if’’ (see Poston (2006, p. 332)). Given that Fumerton notes that false beliefs can enjoy noninferential justification in many of the places he expounds his theory, however, a maximally charitable reading of his account’s first part will include only a sufficient condition—otherwise the admission of noninferentially justified false belief is a straightforward counterexample to his view. We can do better than to state Fumerton’s theory so that it faces a counterexample that’s due to his own handiwork. In email correspondence on 15 February 2008, Fumerton wrote to me that he has been ‘‘torn’’ on the issue of whether to include a necessary condition as well as a sufficient one; cf. Fumerton (2010, pp. 379–380) and Poston (2010, pp. 370–371). The arguments below do not hinge on the way I have stated the acquaintance theory. 3 Fumerton (1995, pp. 74–76). 123 N. Ballantyne maker for the belief; the pain is ‘‘there’’ before his mind. He has a ‘‘completely satisfying way’’ of assuring himself that he is in pain (Fumerton 2006a, p. 189). Therein lies a key motivation for Fumerton’s acquaintance theory. ‘‘The very source of justification,’’ Fumerton says, ‘‘includes that which makes true the belief. In a way it is this idea that makes an acquaintance foundation theory so attractive’’ (2001, p. 15). What apparently motivates the acquaintance theory is this: acquaintance allegedly explains how we can get assurance. And there is more. Fumerton thinks that externalist theories—and presumably all kinds of non-acquaintance views— lack precisely this virtue of his theory: such theories can’t provide assurance. The proponent of simple reliabilism, for example, says roughly that the reliability of a belief-producing process is sufficient to generate justified output beliefs. Given reliabilism, someone is noninferentially justified in believing he is in pain if the belief is caused by a reliable process. According to Fumerton, the philosopher must ask the obvious next question: Is my belief caused in the right way? ‘‘The question is irresistible,’’ says Fumerton, ‘‘because having a belief caused in a certain way when we don’t know whether or not it is caused in that way is clearly not something that would give us assurance of truth’’ (2006a, pp.
Recommended publications
  • EPISTEMIC CIRCULARITY: MALIGNANT and BENIGN Michael Bergmann
    EPISTEMIC CIRCULARITY: MALIGNANT AND BENIGN Michael Bergmann Consider the following dialogue: Juror #1: You know that witness named Hank? I have doubts about his trustworthiness. Juror #2: Well perhaps this will help you. Yesterday I overheard Hank claiming to be a trustworthy witness. Juror #1: So Hank claimed to be trustworthy did he? Well, that settles it then. I’m now convinced that Hank is trustworthy. Is the belief of Juror #1 that Hank is a trustworthy witness justified? Most of us would be inclined to say it isn’t. Juror #1 begins by having some doubts about Hank’s trustworthiness, and then he comes to believe that Hank is trustworthy. The problem is that he arrives at this belief on the basis of Hank’s own testimony. That isn’t reasonable. You can’t sensibly come to trust a doubted witness on the basis of that very witness’s testimony on his own behalf.1 Now consider the following soliloquy: Doubter: I have some doubts about the trustworthiness of my senses. After all, for all I know, they are deceiving me. Let’s see ... Hey, wait a minute. They are trustworthy! I recall many occasions in the past when I was inclined to hold certain perceptual beliefs. On each of those occasions, the beliefs I formed were true. I know that because the people I was with confirmed to me that they were true. By inductive reasoning, I can safely conclude from those past cases that my senses are trustworthy. There we go. It feels good to have those doubts about my senses behind me.
    [Show full text]
  • Acquaintance and Skepticism About the Past
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 9/1/2016, SPi 9 Acquaintance and Skepticism about the Past Ted Poston How long does it take you to read this sentence? Did you rely on memory at all in reading that sentence?1 What is the most complex thought you can entertain without relying on memory at all? These questions raise a fundamental epistemological issue concerning our ability to justify our extensive reliance on memory. Nearly every thought relies on memory. Even simple thoughts we entertain in the fleeting present—e.g., ‘green here now’—rely on our apparent memory that the meanings of our terms are constant and that the ‘I’ which now thinks is the same ‘I’ that thought a moment ago. My goal in this chapter is to consider the epistemological problem of how our beliefs about the past can be justified within an acquaintance theory. Fumerton explicitly acknowledges that the problem of justifying our beliefs about the past is the most fundamental epistemological problem (1985: 119), and yet his solution to the problem relies on acquaintance with the quasi-logical relation of making-probable which he strongly suspects is an illusion (1985: 218). I argue that an acquaintance theory does not offer an adequate solution to memory skepticism. At the same time I am not a skeptic and honesty requires a reply to memory skepticism. As Fumerton acknowledges, the problem is stark and the answers are few (1985: 185). I defend another response to memory skepticism which Fumerton rejects. I will argue for an epistemic conservative response to memory skepticism by arguing that the theoretical economy of a conservative epistemology combined with its virtue of actually addressing memory skepticism gives us a reason to accept it.
    [Show full text]
  • Corel Ventura
    Richard Fumerton Epistemology. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing 2006. Pp. x + 145. US$51.95 (cloth ISBN-13: 978-1-4051-2566-6); US$19.95 (paper ISBN-13: 978-1-4051-2567-3). This book will interest those who teach undergraduate or graduate episte- mology, like the idea of using a single-author text, but are unsatisfied with the current options. It differs in a few ways from books like Richard Feld- mans Epistemology, Robert Audis Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduc- tion to the Theory of Knowledge, Laurence Bonjours Epistemology, and Adam Mortons A Guide Through the Theory of Knowledge. Chapter 1 begins with propositional knowledge and the evaluation of epistemic reasons for belief. The rest of the chapter draws a distinction between metaepistemology and applied epistemology. Applied epistemology is concerned with what we know and how we know it. Meta-epistemology is concerned with what knowledge is. Though this makes meta-epistemology more like normative ethics, Fumerton does not label it normative epistemol- ogy because of his qualms with thinking of epistemology as normative he returns to this issue in Chapter 3. Newcomers to epistemology will find much of this book difficult, especially Chapter 2, The Analysis of Knowledge. It begins with familiar reasons for including truth and belief conditions on knowledge. Fumerton says evidence is also needed. However, lottery cases suggest that the evidence must be strong enough that it entails the truth of the proposition believed. This coupled with Closure the principle that if you know P, and you know P entails Q, then you are in a position to know Q leads to skepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of the Criterion1
    The Problem of the Criterion1 Introduction: The problem of the criterion in epistemology raises certain fundamental questions concerning the methods a philosopher ought to use in arriving at both analyses of epistemic concepts and conclusions concerning legitimate principles of reasoning and justification. The answers one gives to these questions are thought to bear directly on the challenge of skepticism. The outcome of battles is often determined by the ground occupied by opposing forces. Interest in the problem of the criterion is often a function of the desire to occupy favorable ground in the battle with the skeptic. Despite the title of this paper, there are, I believe, at least two different problems one might associate with “the criterion.” One is, perhaps, best known through the work of Roderick Chisholm, whose various editions of Theory of Knowledge all devote a chapter to it. As Chisholm develops the problem, it concerns methodological questions concerning how to identify sources of knowledge or justified belief. But there is a closely related question concerning how to identify necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of epistemic concepts like knowledge and justified belief. In the following discussion I’ll distinguish these two methodological issues, and I’ll begin by looking at the question of how one should go about discovering the correct analysis of epistemic concepts. Metaepistemology and the Problem of the Criterion: Metaepistemological questions seek to uncover through philosophical analysis the nature of fundamental epistemic concepts or properties. In metaepistemology, we are interested in getting an account of what knowledge, evidence, justified belief, and so on are.
    [Show full text]
  • SARAH WRIGHT Curriculum Vitae
    SARAH WRIGHT Curriculum Vitae Department of Philosophy Cell: (706) 254-2990 University Of Georgia Fax: (706) 583-0530 107 Peabody Hall Email: [email protected] Athens, GA 30602-1627 http://www.phil.uga.edu/directory/sarah-wright EDUCATION: University of Arizona Ph.D. in Philosophy, 2005. Dissertation: Virtue Epistemology: Its Proper Form and Its Applications Committee: Keith Lehrer (chair), Terence Horgan, and David Schmidtz Brown University M.A. in Philosophy, 1999. University of Colorado at Boulder B.A. magna cum laude, with Honors, in Philosophy, 1995. Honors Thesis: Fregean Logic and Russell’s Paradoxes Director: George Bealer ACADEMIC EMPLOYMENT: University of Georgia Associate Professor, Fall 2012- Present Assistant Professor, Fall 2005- Spring 2012 University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Visiting Graduate Instructor, Spring 2005 University of Arizona Undergraduate Advisor, Fall 2003 - Fall 2004 Teaching Assistant and Teaching Associate Fall 1999-Spring 2003 AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION: AREAS OF COMPETENCE: Epistemology Feminist Philosophy Cognitive Science Metaethics Environmental Ethics Logic PUBLICATIONS: “Virtue Responsibilism” forthcoming in the Oxford Handbook of Virtue, Oxford University Press. “Epistemic Authority, Epistemic Preemption, and the Intellectual Virtues.” Episteme, forthcoming. “The Stoic Epistemic Virtues of Groups.” in Essays in Collective Epistemology, ed. Jennifer Lackey, Oxford University Press, 2014 “The Norms of Assertion and the Aims of Belief.” in Epistemic Norms: New Essays on Action, Belief, and Assertion,
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    9781405150873_4_001.qxd 8/13/08 14:34 Page 1 chapter 1 introduction Biography: John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) ohn Stuart Mill was born in London in 1806. His father, James Mill, was a philosopher, economist, and historian, who also held a pro- Jminent position in the East India Company. James Mill, along with Jeremy Bentham, was a founding father of a group known as the Philosophical Radicals, of which John Stuart Mill also became a pro- minent member. The group was known for its enthusiastic endorsement of utilitarianism as a moral and political philosophy, a philosophy they hoped would transform the political shape of the western world. James Mill played a critical role in the intellectual development of his eldest son, John Stuart Mill. John Stuart Mill was pushed very hard – he was taught Greek at the age of three and Latin at the age of eight. His studies in philosophy, economics, and politics, began early, and under the influence of both his father and Jeremy Bentham, Mill became a com- mitted utilitarian determined to carry on the legacy of his teachers. The pressure of his education and of living up to his father’s intellectual expectations took its toll and Mill suffered a “mental crisis” in his early twenties. Mill himself credits his discovery of and interest in poetry, and in particular Wordsworth, with giving his life a kind of balance that made it richer and more fulfilling. Rather than continue a formal educa- tion, Mill followed his father in working for the East India Company from 1823 to 1858, a position that allowed him enough flexibility to pur- sue his intellectual writing.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Richard Feldman Curriculum Vita University Professor of Philosophy University of Rochester Rochester, New York 14627 E-mail: [email protected] EDUCATION: B.A., Cornell University, 1970 Ph.D., University of Massachusetts, 1975 EMPLOYMENT EXPERIENCE: Sep. 1974 - June 1975: Instructor, Franklin and Marshall College July 1975 - June 1981: Assistant Professor, University of Rochester July 1981 - June 1988: Associate Professor and Chair, Department of Philosophy, University of Rochester July 1989 - July 1991: Associate Professor, University of Rochester July 1991 - June 1997: Professor and Chair, University of Rochester July 1997 - Professor, University of Rochester Spring 2002: Visiting Professor, Massachusetts Institute of Technology Fall 2003: Professor (part-time), Syracuse University Spring 2006-June 2017: Dean of the College, University of Rochester Jan. 2018-June 2019: President, University of Rochester June 2019 - : University Professor of Philosophy HONORARY POSITION Fall 2017: The Romanell-Phi Beta Kappa Professorship in Philosophy AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION: Epistemology, Metaphysics PUBLICATIONS: Books 1. Reason and Argument, Prentice-Hall, 1993; 2nd Edition, 1999. 2. Epistemology, Prentice Hall (Foundations of Philosophy Series), 2003. 3. Evidentialism (with Earl Conee), Oxford University Press, 2004. 4. The Good, The Right, Life and Death, ed. (with Jason Raibly, Kris McDaniel, and Michael Zimmerman), Ashgate, 2006. 5. Disagreement, ed. (with Ted A. Warfield), Oxford University Press, 2010. 6. Thinking Things Through (in preparation) Papers 1. “An Alleged Defect in Gettier Counterexamples,” The Australasian Journal of Philosophy 52 (1974): 68-69; reprinted in Paul K. Moser, ed., Empirical Knowledge, Rowman & Allanheld, 1986, Paul Moser and Arnold vander Nat, eds., Human Knowledge, Oxford University Press, 1986, Kenneth Lucey, ed., On Knowing and the Known: Introductory Readings in Epistemology, Prometheus Books, 1996, and in Sven Bernecker and Fred Dretske, eds., Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology, Oxford, 2000.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Features of Richard Fumerton's Philosophical
    1 SOME FEATURES OF RICHARD FUMERTON’S PHILOSOPHICAL VIEWS (Orange Beach Epistemology Workshop, May 2014) PART ONE I first met Richard at Brown where we were part of the same entering class. From the beginning, he was the star of the class. We both learned a lot about doing philosophy there, but I was doubly fortunate, since I also learned in talking philosophy with Richard. I also saw first hand with him just how productive and how much sheer fun talking philosophy could be. In the years since, Richard has produced an enormous number of important publications: seven authored books, two edited books, and more articles than I was willing to try to count, including two we jointly authored. I’ll talk briefly about one of them later. For the most part, I’m going to be focusing on Richard’s latest book: Knowledge, Thought, and the Case for Dualism (Cambridge University Press, 2013). The first thing to say about this book is that it’s terrific. I mean really terrific. Not just run of mill, grade inflation “terrific.” All of Richard’s usual characteristics are on display, most especially, tremendous clarity and a contrarian spirit that is willing to follow the argument wherever it goes. Something I want to emphasize, however, is the remarkable scope of the book. It’s primarily a defense of property dualism, but in the process of mounting the defense, there’s a vast range of other positions Richard defends. Here’s a very partial list: *A radical empiricist version of foundationalism. *A particular version of internalism, what he calls “internal state internalism,” which asserts that the epistemic status of a belief depends solely on the internal states of the believer; the contrast is to 2 access internalism, which implies that one can always determine by introspection whether one is justified.
    [Show full text]
  • Read the Preface
    MAR-31-2010 10:25 She rri Katz Working Without a Net A Study of Egocentric Epistemology RICHARD FOLEY New York Oxford OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 1993 Oxford University Press Oxford New York Toronto Delhi Bombay Calcutta Madras· Karachi Kuala Lumpur Singapore Hong Kong Tokyo Nairobi Das es Salaam Cape Town Melbourne Auckland Madrid and associated companies in Berlin Ibadan Copyright © 1993 by Richard Foley Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 200 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 Oxford is a registered (trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of his publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, to any form or by any means electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Foley. Richard Working without a net: a study of egocentric epistemology / Richard Foley. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-19-.507699-0 1. Knowledge, Theory of. 2. Descartes, Rene, 1596—1650. I. Tittle. tz BD161.F58 1992 12[—dc20 91-48108 a K i r r e h S 10:25 0 -201 24 6 8 9 7 5 3 1 R-31 Printed in the United States of America MA on acid-free paper Preface Part of the fascination of philosophy is the way topics blend into one another You are writing on what you take to be a well-defined topic, but to your surprise you soon find yourself writing about something that antecedently would have seemed to have been a quite different topic. This is the experience I had with this book.
    [Show full text]
  • Skepticism and Reasoning to the Best Explanation
    PHILOSOPHICAL ISSUES, 2 9 Rationality in Epistemology, 1992 Skepticism and Reasoning to the Best Explanation Richard Fumerton In this paper I want to evaluate the extent to which reasoning to the best explanation provides a source of justification that will defeat traditional skeptical arguments. Unfortunately, however, so much of contemporary epistemology takes place in the shadow of certain metaepistemological debates over the nature of justified belief. The approach one should take to traditional skepticism, for example, depends very much on where one stands on the now famous internalism/externalism controversy. It is also impossible to adequately assess the plausibility of reasoning to the best explanation as a response to the skeptic without a more general discussion of the logic of reasoning to the best explanation. In 1, I shall discuss one version ofthe internalism/externalism controversy and assess its implications for the place of reasoning to the best expla­ nation as a bulwark in the defense of commonsense against skepticism. In short, I will argue that unless one embraces 150 RICHARD FUMERTON the view I call inferential internalism, it is extremely doubtful that one will have any need to employ reasoning to the best explanation in replying to the skeptic. In 2, I shall explore the question of whether there is a legitimate sort of reasoning that we may reasonably call reasoning to the best explanation and that constitutes a genuine alternative to classical enu­ merative induction. Although I will conclude that the exis­ tence of such a mode of reasoning is at least doubtful, I will go on to discuss the question of whether standard models of rea­ soning to the best explanation, even if they were legitimate, would provide one with ammunition against skepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Knowledge
    Third Edition THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE Roderick M. Chisholm Brown University This edition may be sold only in those countries to which' it is consigned by Prentice-Hall International. It is not to be re-exported and it is not for sale in the U.S.A., Mexico, or Canada. © 1989, 1977, 1966 by Prentice-Hall, Inc. A Division of Simon & Schuster Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey 07632 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, in any form or by any means, without permission in writing from the publisher. Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 ISBN D-13-^mifi5-S Prentice-Hall International (UK) Limited, London Prentice-Hall of Australia Pty. Limited, Sydney Prentice-Hall Canada Inc., Toronto Prentice-Hall Hispanoamericana, S.A., Mexico Prentice-Hall of India Private Limited, New Delhi Prentice-Hall of Japan, Inc., Tokyo Simon & Schuster Asia Pte. Ltd., Singapore Editora Prentice-Hall do Brasil, Ltda., Rio de Janeiro Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey Contents Preface vii CHAFFER 1 The Skeptic's Challenge 1 CHAFFER 2 Epistemic Justification 8 CHAFFER 3 Certainty and the Self-Presenting 18 CHAFFER 4 The A Priori 26 CHAFFER 5 The Evidence of the Senses 39 CHAPTER 6 The Transfer of Justification 49 CHAPTER 7 The Structure of Empirical Knowledge 61 CHAPTER 8 Internalism and Externalism 75 CHAPTER 9 Foundationalism and the Coherence Theory 85 CHAPTER 10 What Is Knowledge? 90 Index Foundations of Philosophy Many of the problems of philosophy are of such broad relevance to human concerns, and so complex in their ramifications, that they are, in one form or another, perennially present.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE Richard Anthony Fumerton
    1 CURRICULUM VITAE Richard Anthony Fumerton PERSONAL Born, October 7, 1949, Toronto, Ontario Married, two children Home Address: 608 Whiting Ave, Iowa City, Iowa 52245 Office Phone: (319) 335-0022 Home Phone: (319) 338-5602 Cell Phone: (319) 621-8148 E-mail: [email protected] Fax: (319) 353-2322 EDUCATION Ph.D. Brown University, 1974, Philosophy M.A. Brown University, 1973, Philosophy B.A. University of Toronto (Victoria College), 1971, Philosophy TEACHING Professor, University of Iowa, 1985-present Associate Professor, University of Iowa, 1979-1985 Visiting Assistant Professor, University of Minnesota, Fall Quarter, 1978 Assistant Professor, University of Iowa, 1974-1979 HONORS AND AWARDS Michael J. Brody Award (for Faculty Service), 2016 University of Iowa Presidential Lecturer, Spring, 2016 F. Wendell Miller Professorship, 2003-present Regents Award for Faculty Excellence, 1997 Collegiate Teaching Award, University of Iowa, 1996 M. L. Huit Award for Excellence in Teaching, 1994, University of Iowa Canada Council Fellow, 1973-74 Woodrow Wilson Fellow, 1971-72 DISSERTATIONS DIRECTED Justin Christopher, Testimony in Narrative Research (co-director). Summer, 2017 Bryan Appley, Skepticism and Reasoning to the Best Explanation. Spring, 2016 Greg Stoutenburg, Knowledge, Infallibility, and Skepticism. Spring, 2015 Brian Collins, A Utilitarian Account of Political Obligation. (Co-director). Summer, 2014. Samuel Taylor. The Problem of Easy Justification: An Investigation of Evidence, Justification and Reliability. Summer. 2013. Kalyn Kappelman. A Critical Evaluation of Virtue Consequentialism. In progress. Ian MacMillan. Internalism, Externalism, and Epistemic Source Circularity. November, 2012. 2 Brett Coppenger. Achieving Epistemic Descent. Summer, 2012. Travis Dickinson. Direct Awareness of Fit as the Solution to all Sellarsian Dilemmas.
    [Show full text]