Axiomathes Where Science Meets Philosophy 22: 355-383. DOI 10.1007/s10516-012-9185-0

Hierarchical Structures

Stanley N. Salthe

Professor Emeritus, Biology, City University of New York Visiting Scientist in Biological Sciences, Binghamton University

42 Laurel Bank Avenue, Deposit, New York 13754, USA

[email protected]

607-467-2623

Abstract This paper compares the two known logical forms of hierarchy, both of which have been used in models of natural phenomena, including the biological. I contrast their general properties, internal formal relations, modes of growth () in applications to the natural world, criteria for applying them, the complexities that they embody, their dynamical relations in applied models, and their informational relations and semiotic aspects.

Keywords change; composition; development; emergence; heterarchy; levels; meronomy; process; semiosis; subsumption; taxonomy

Introduction

Hierarchical models have been appearing in increasing numbers in scientific papers in recent years (see the Further Readings below), but without any fully developed reference on these forms. In this paper I aim to remedy this lacuna. My focus is on biology, where both forms of hierarchy have been used, but I have included references from all fields where I have discovered attempts to use these forms. Simpson (1961) noted that particularly influential relationships among objects have been ‘association by similarity’ and ‘association by contiguity’. These conceptual modes have come to be utilized in biology as hierarchical forms in connection with, respectively, biological classification (Rieppel, 2010), and physiological - ecological structure (Salthe, 1985; Ahl and Allen, 1996). Stanley (1979) and Eldredge (1985) enlisted association by contiguity to enlarge the scope of biological evolution discourse beyond the population, and this form also contextualized the ‘levels of selection’ discourse (Price, 1970; Wilson and Dugatkin, 1997; Gould, 2002). Additionally, in 1993, I enlisted association by similarity to serve as a format for modeling development. This paper presents my understanding of the nature and uses of the known hierarchical forms. I attempt to clarify, and distinguish between, the structures and implications of the two known logical forms of hierarchy. This seems timely in view of the fact that there has currently been a resurgence of interest in hierarchies (see the post 1990 instances in many fields shown in the Further Readings). As well, and despite their structural differences, these forms are sometimes conflated, presumably as a result of a common lack of explicit knowledge about hierarchical structures, which this paper attempts to remedy. Despite hierarchy’s presence in many discourses, a focus on biology seems especially appropriate because both forms have been used in that discourse (e.g., see above). As this paper is a distillation and consilience of what is found scattered throughout the literature, I will not make specific citations in the body of the text, which represents my own summary. The references in the Further Readings indicate which papers, chapters and books discuss or utilize which form of hierarchy.

Two known logical forms of hierarchy

(a) The compositional hierarchy (including a synchronic map of the command hierarchy), which in applications, for reasons given below, I have labeled the ‘scale hierarchy’. The picture of macromolecules inside living cells inside an organism is a familiar image of an important application. This modular form is suited to the synchronic modeling of systems as they are at any given moment, focusing on dynamic energy transactions and ongoing processes.

(b) The subsumption hierarchy (including a diachronic model of the trajectory of a given command), which I have called the ‘specification hierarchy’. The familiar Linnaean hierarchy as embodied in the cladograms and phylogenies of biological systematics has this structure, which is suitable as well to modeling the diachronic emergence of forms as stages in a developmental process of acquisition of new informational constraints.

Cliff Joslyn (personal communication) has provided the following comparison of the logical properties of the two kinds of hierarchy:

Meronomy Taxonomy ------Whole/part General/specific is-a-part-of is-a-kind-of Composition Subsumption Containment Inheritance Modularity Specification Using my representations: [whole [part]] and {general {specific}}

Some situations and relations can be interpreted either way. Consider the well-known ‘control hierarchy’ in the example of a corporation, with a CEO at the top and a series of managers at several levels between him/her and various workers. In the subsumption hierarchy, a suggestion from the top becomes an ever more specific command as it approaches the workers, with more particulars added at each intervening level, delivering a pattern of ‘coarse-to-fine’ control. In the compositional perspective, we see that the social role of the CEO – the sphere of interest and influence, -- is geographically much greater than that of others in a firm. A CEO’s interests span an entire business, or even an entire continent and beyond, and so involve a much larger scope than that of any of the subordinates, while a worker at a station at the bottom of the hierarchy would be concerned only with his or her current immediate transactions. So the social role of a CEO actually encompasses those of lower level workers, whose roles are contained within it, even though the workers’ bodies are not contained within the CEO’s body. This principle emerges from the role of money in society as well; wealth generally signifies the social status and personal power of an individual.

General philosophical outlook of hierarchy

Ontologically, any hierarchy presupposes that the world is in some ways discontinuous. The compositional hierarchy assumes that it is a whole made up of parts, and also that it just keeps getting larger and larger the further one looks outward, or, going inward from an observer’s location, smaller and smaller. So, there would formally be no ‘edge’ to the world in either direction. The subsumptive hierarchy assumes that every dynamical object is supported by all aspects of the world, and that it will have developed from earlier, simpler conditions, and so might be part of a developmental trajectory or evolutionary history. Epistemologically, the compositional hierarchy presupposes critical knowledge to be derivable by means of subdivision of a system (the traditional ‘biological reductionist’ view), while the subsumptive hierarchy implies that in order to understand a system it would be necessary to look for its sources in prior systems. Methodologically, the compositional hierarchy presupposes that systems can be conceptually divided into parts, while the subsumptive hierarchy implies that important information about a system would be obtained from seeking antecedent -- perhaps ancestral -- conditions, the development out of which could usefully be cut up into discrete stages, or series of ancestral kinds.

General properties

Hierarchies are conceptual tools rather than theories. They are methods of ‘cutting (a seemingly continuous) Nature at its joints’. They are examples of ‘partial ordering’ in logic. That is, the items being ordered could be ordered in other ways as well. Hierarchies order entities, processes or realms into a system of levels. The ordering principle (‘is-a-part-of’ or ‘is-a-kind-of’) is transitive across levels. In both of these hierarchies, when used to model actual systems, higher levels control (regulate, interpret, harness) lower levels, whose behaviors are made possible by properties generated at still lower levels (see below for the usage of ‘higher’ and ‘lower’). Higher levels function as formal causes, providing boundary conditions (in some cases, order parameters) on the behaviors of lower levels. This is the meaning of the term ‘downward causation’ in the hierarchy context. It is important to realize that only some users of hierarchical forms would insist that particular levels actually exist as such in natural systems. Levels are discerned from hierarchical analysis, aimed at constructing / discovering Nature's ‘joints’ with respect to given projects. Hierarchies thus provide models of any systems that may be susceptible to analysis into levels. If a system appears to be susceptible, then the logic of the hierarchy model used, as outlined in this paper, is imputed to the actual system being modeled -- science discourse must of course first be logical. In this way the model serves as an exploratory highway in search for corroboration. The magnitudes or frequencies of many aspects of the world (words in texts, earthquakes) can be mapped to power laws, ranging over many orders of magnitude. It is possible that levels in compositional hierarchies might also be susceptible to such a mapping, but it is worth noting that the ‘fractal ideology’ here is implicitly continuous rather than discontinuous, as with hierarchies.

(a) To use the compositional hierarchy to model a natural system we need to stipulate a focal level, as well as a lower and a higher, making up a ‘basic triadic system’ -- as, e.g., when the behavior of living cells is initiated by chemical events, and controlled by internal organismic events. The three level format models stability because with it in place a third level always anchors relations between the other two, and so the middle, focal level cannot be reduced either upward or downward by assimilation into a contiguous level. Here we should note that this hierarchy has been invoked to explain how the world manages to be as stable as it is, by avoiding tight coupling among components of complicated systems. A material system with this structure would be ‘nearly decomposable’, but not fully so. The triadic form also reflects the putative way in which levels would have emerged, by interpolation between primal highest and lowest ones, as when biology would have emerged as organizational forms of chemical activities occurring within an environmental energy-dissipative configuration. The question might arise as to why one could not make a two level version of this hierarchy. The answer is that there are always both material and formal causes bearing upon any material system. A third level will always be implicitly in play, even if not explicitly modeled.

(b) In the subsumption hierarchy the highest level is always the one in focus, with all lower levels subtending it and providing cumulative initiating conditions simultaneously upon it. The focal level supervenes upon all the other, supporting ones. Thus, biological configurations harness both physical forces and chemical potentialities. This dominance of the highest level being considered reflects the fact that this hierarchy is implicitly directional -- in applications that would be evolutionary or developmental -- with the levels being viewed as having emerged consecutively from the lowest, or most general (or most generally present in the world), up -- as with, e.g., biology being emergent from physics as mediated by chemistry, both historically and also at any given moment at some locale. Thus the system has dynamically a two-level form (highest and all lower), which is formally unstable, allowing new levels to emerge at the top of the hierarchy. Use of this form provides us with a model representing emergent changes in the world, as when hominids evolved from African apes, or when a gastrula develops from a blastula -- in both cases by the emergence of new informational constraints, logically a process of refinement. Hierarchical analysis is always driven by a given problem or project, located at the focal level in a compositional hierarchy or at the highest level in a subsumptive hierarchy.

Formal relations between levels

(a) The compositional hierarchy is one of parts nested within wholes, as, e.g., [... [species [population [organism [cell [...]]]]]], where [higher level [ focal level [lower level]]], hence the term ‘inclusion hierarchy’ is sometimes used. Nested processes or influences would not necessarily be reflected in actual nested things (recall the example of the CEO above, who does not contain the bodies of those subordinate to his wishes). The logic reflects Russell's logical types. In principle the levels just keep going, receding at both ends from any chosen focal level. If the parts of a modeled system are functional in some given analysis, they are referred to as components (of a ‘dynamical hierarchy’), if not they would be constituents. As one goes down the hierarchy, the relative number of constituents per level increases, providing a measure of the ‘span’ of the hierarchy, which may be ‘shallow’, with few levels, or ‘steep’, with many.

(b) The subsumption hierarchy is one of classes and subclasses, as, e.g., {material world {biological world (social world}}}, where {lower levels {highest level}}. It should be noted that this use of ‘higher’ differs from the usage in logic discourse, where the outermost class or set is traditionally labeled the highest level. This reversal is rhetorically necessary in scientific applications to prevent taking, e.g., the physical realm to be ‘higher’ than the biological realm. The focus of analysis in applications is always the highest level, which is the innermost level of the hierarchy. The logic reflects Ryle’s categories. Higher levels inherit all the properties of the lower levels.

Given {A {B}}, the following interpretations can be made:

Logically: B is a kind of A; B instantiates A; B generalizes to A; B is implicit in A

Functionally in an application: B regulates A; B harnesses A ; B conceptually subordinates A

Semiotically: B interprets A

Developmentally in an application: A gives rise to B; B supervenes upon A; B is a later stage of development than A; A is a material cause of B; A is vaguer than B with respect to properties of B that are immanent in A. Here it will be useful to examine in detail the application of these subsumptive hierarchy principles to a characteristic biological developmental trajectory – embryonic development. Referring to the basic properties of this hierarchy as enumerated above:

(1) Is an embryo more general than an adult? Yes, as von Baer showed, earlier embryos (or those at the phylotypic stage) are common to many species, and become gradually more different as development proceeds. (2) Is an adult a kind of embryo? Seemingly not; “kind of” requires further study here. (3) Do embryonic traits subsume those of the adult? Yes, from the epigenetic perspective, they are prior temporally and provide material causes. Adult properties cannot transcend embryonic ones; a later stage is more than an earlier one, but it is not other than it. Adult features are refinements of embryonic ones. (4) Do adults inherit embryonic features? Genetically, yes; anatomically, (for example, bilaterality; dorso-ventral and antero-posterior differentiation) by direct material derivation from them. (5) Are adults more highly specified than embryos? Presumably so, as one would need to deploy more information to describe them, minimally because the system has during development acquired structure at more scales. (6) Does an adult instantiate an embryo? Seemingly not. (7) Does an adult integrate or regulate the embryo? Yes, insofar as, if the adult fails to breed, its embryonic precursor has failed to give rise to a fertile adult – the selection principle. (8) Does the adult interpret the embryo? Yes, via epigenetic refinement. (9) Does the adult supervene upon the embryo. Yes, it emerges out of it. (10) Does the adult harness the embryo to its needs? Yes, by utilizing the precursor embryonic material and information storage. (11) Does the adult conceptually subordinate the embryo? Yes. Given what the adult has become, the embryo had to have been as it was. (12) Is the embryo a material cause of the adult. Clearly yes. This is not gainsaid by noting that the adult might be taken (via reproduction) as also being a material cause of the embryo! (13) Is the embryo vaguer than the adult? Yes. Embryonic anlage are only gradually refined into the definitive adult condition.

We must note the two exceptions here – numbers 2 and 6. The world is one thing, while models are another. It seems to me that with the other eleven queries being convincingly fulfilled, one might be justified in suggesting that the meanings of ‘being a kind of’ and ‘instantiate’ are really broader than we might suppose. I am suggesting that models can lead us toward further understandings that we would not have reached without them. It might be objected that I am here making a tendentious use of the set theory format by modeling a dynamical process using it. The answer to this is clear enough; I am here modeling successive stages in a trajectory as classes and subclasses, not the process itself. Then, it might seem that I am here denying that new forms can emerge during ontogeny, thereby going back to a kind of preformationism. But if we keep in the general process of moving from vague embodiment toward more definite expression, we can see that I am here emphasizing that the new, whatever it is, must logically be a refinement of a previous condition, This amounts to, in this format, not privileging the new as such, but treating it as an emergent from its material prior form. No model can emphasize everything. For example, no model and maximize all three of realism, precision and generality. Here I am emphasizing generality. We use different models as probes for different purposes.

(c) A note on levels terminology: The levels in a subsumption hierarchy have been referred to as ‘integrative levels’ inasmuch as the higher levels (as here defined) integrate the lower levels’ properties and dynamics under their own rules. ‘Levels of reality’ and ‘ontological levels’ have been used in subsumption as well. One sees other labels, such as ‘levels of organization, levels of complexity, or ‘levels of observation’ used for either kind of hierarchy. I have used ‘scalar levels’ or ‘levels of scale’ when applying the compositional hierarchy to material systems for dynamical reasons (see below under ‘Criteria’).

Mode of growth of the hierarchy

Biological systems grow, basically by way of cell division. This might result in an actual growth in size or scale, or the growth may be by intussusception (e.g., invagination, involution). The two hierarchies differ logically in the required way to visualize or model growth, or the emergence of new levels.

(a) In applications, a compositional hierarchy would need to add levels by interpolation between existing ones. For this to happen materially, the system must be an expanding one. Therefore, an assumption required for application of this hierarchy would be, e.g., the Big Bang, or other expanding system, like a growing population, or embryo, or phylogeny. The actual process of formation, or emergence, of a level would involve the cohesion of entities generated out of potential configurations of cooperating lower level components, as guided by a scaffolding of higher level boundary conditions, or as harnessed by order parameters imposed by the higher level. This would be a process that is therefore both bottom-up ‘causal’ and, simultaneously, top- down constrained (downward causation). This process is little understood since this hierarchy has largely been used for synchronic analyses. Some recent works on ‘emergence’ have been developing relevant viewpoints on this process. Given the reductionist orientation of most scientists, it is not surprising to find that in studies of the incorporation of individuals into a collective the individual properties (which I have called ‘initiating conditions) are emphasized rather than any properties of the collective itself, which would be acting as boundary conditions It may be noted that the obligatory triadic form, surrounding the emergent focal level by higher and lower ones, implies that this hierarchy must be unbounded both above and below, even if, in applications, practicality or evidence requires cutoffs, such as, in cosmology, at the Planck scale below and the ‘event horizon’ above. Given today’s knowledge about it, the cosmologist’s universe could not, therefore, be taken as a focal level as nothing is known about its environment. In biology we find always a bottom limit to populations or individuals, as well as a genetically imposed rather fuzzy upper limit for individuals. (b) In the subsumption hierarchy new levels in applications would emerge from the current highest one. So this system too can grow -- but not in space. Growth here is by the accumulation of informational constraints, modeled logically as a process of refinement by way of adding specification as those constraints become fixed. Perhaps ‘growth by intussusception’ would be an adequate label in some cases. New levels, marked in the model as added subclasses, reflect thresholds of system structural reorganization under the guidance of emerging upper level boundary conditions or order parameters. A new innermost (highest) level emerges when added information results in a reorganization delivering configurations that require new descriptors, as when biological form supervenes upon the products of chemical interactions, or a new subspecies is discovered in systematics. This process does not require, but may be accompanied by, system growth. This hierarchy is open at the top; the innermost, highest, level is unbounded above, and so is free to give rise to ever higher, more highly specified, levels. There are reasons, however (see below) to doubt that an embodied hierarchy of this kind could keep extending indefinitely. The system here is formally a tree (see below), and so growth is in principle accompanied by branching possibilities.

Criteria for application

(a) In order to apply the compositional hierarchy to actual natural systems or locales, components and / or the rates of change at the different levels must differ in size or magnitude roughly by at least an order of magnitude. As a result, entities at any level interact more frequently or more intensely with others at that level than -- if at all – with entities at other levels. Failing this, components at different levels would directly interact dynamically, in which case there would not be different levels functionally. Compositional levels transact indirectly, by reciprocally supplying relatively stable conditions above and, e.g., reliable substrate concentrations, genotype proportions, species compositions, etc. (all ensemble properties) below. The principal result is that no information can transit unmediated across levels of scale. In physiology, for example, the organism controls cells by way of broadcast hormones, but individual cells are screened off from the state of the organism as a whole. Thus, I cannot directly affect any particular cell in my body, and it cannot have, as an individual, any effect upon me. A related, possibly derived, criterion is frequency and strength of interactions. Nuclear forces are much larger than covalent bonds, which are larger than hydrogen bonds, which are larger than van der Waals interactions. This scaling by magnitudes would presumably continue with cells, organs, biological individuals, communities, as well as with solar system, galaxy, and clusters of galaxies.

(b) Levels in a subsumptive hierarchy mark the qualitative differences of various realms of being, as in 'physical realm' versus 'biological realm'. Some might argue that levels like ‘biological’ versus ‘physical’ were constructed by human discourses, and may not have the kind of ‘objectivity’ felt to inhere in applications of the compositional hierarchy, as, for example, in physiology or . I think a reasonable rejoinder would be that measured variables as used in compositional hierarchies are themselves products of discourse. It is worth noting that in the realm of linguistic thought processes, the process of generalizing moves from particulars to generals, as in the reconstruction of putative ancestral forms in biological systematics. My use here, however, tracing emergent properties or systems from precursors, relates to , where development moves from vaguer toward more fully explicit realization of the highest level. What appears as a general condition when looking ‘backwards’ would have been derived from a vaguer, precursor possibility during evolution at an earlier period or during development at an earlier stage. In evolution, for example, the gill arches of early fishes would only vaguely portend the later evolution of ear ossicles based on the redeployment of developmental processes, while during ontogeny the ear ossicles only gradually become refined into their definitive form during a ‘coarse to fine’ series of changes.

Complexity in applications

(a) An application of the compositional hierarchy provides a model of what I have labeled ‘extensional complexity’, a sign of which would be nonlinear and chaotic dynamics, allowed for by the fact that at any locale at any level in this hierarchy there could be a mixture of different kinds of information coming from different levels (e.g., genetic, cellular, organismic) constraining the dynamics. These could be various relations, rates of activity, constant properties of different kinds, and attractors, which are not fully co-determined by organizing principles from the overall structure itself. The result is that any material system organized this way will have many non-directly interacting, but yet mutually constraining, systems occupying the same locale. This would result in concatenations of contingencies at several levels. Note that it would not be the case that a higher level would be more complex than a lower one since ‘higher’ and ‘lower’ are relative relations transitive throughout the hierarchy. It is useful here to contrast complexity with complication. A flat hierarchy with few levels could tend to show more complicated behavior at any given level than a hierarchy with more levels, which would have more constraints imposed top-down. Thus, a prebiotic ocean will have chemical properties and physical forces in interaction, giving rise to a very complicated, quickly changing scene. This system today would have become more stabilized by the addition of constraints from cells, populations and species.

(b) A subsumption hierarchy embodies what I have termed ‘intensional complexity’, which characterizes a system to the degree that it is susceptible to many different kinds (physical, biological) of analyses. No one approach could exhaust what might be learned from investigating objects at any given level in such a system, except, arguably, the lowest. To this we might also add the several potential new levels presumably hovering just liminal above the highest level; for example: will a Noosphere emerge from the current global domination of the earth by the human species?

Dynamical relations in applications

(a) Typically, a compositional hierarchy represents a single moment at one locale, so its dynamics represent homeostasis, not change. Emergent levels are already present, having emerged, and are being maintained by a combination of constraints and dynamics. Large scale moments ‘contain’ many small scale moments. It is often suggested that levels differing in scale fundamentally signal rate differences rather than component size differences. We may note that the two most often do go together; relatively big things are usually relatively slow to change or accelerate. Comparison of , e.g., slow chameleons with fast anoles suggests that we might best use average rates of change per size range since there will be a range of rates at any scale. A problem appears in cases that are said to be non-nested, where, e.g., a much slower rate in a component of a cycle would regulate the rate of an entire cycle. It would be rare, however, for such rates to differ by orders of magnitude in any cycle, and so many such putative examples likely are not hierarchical in a functional sense at all. If we allowed mere size differences rather than scale differences to be the criterion, then the constraint of nestedness would be lifted. Because of the order of magnitude difference criterion between levels in applications of the compositional hierarchy, dynamics at different levels would not directly interact or exchange energy, but would transact by way of mutual constraint (i.e., via informational connections -- e.g., order parameters imposed from above). The levels are screened off from each other dynamically. Because of this dynamical separation, informational exchanges between levels are non-transitive, requiring interpretation at the boundaries between levels. While the mereological logic itself is transitive throughout a meronomy, facts as such do not transit across levels separated by scale in applications. For example, while metabolism in a cell involves oxidation, oxidation is not a cogent phenomenon at the level of cells themselves; the results of oxidation would impact a cell as, e.g., molar gradients of ATP. As well, organisms may die, but they do not (functionally in ecology) oxidize. And, while organisms can die, they cannot become extinct, while populations cannot die, but may become extinct. Ontologically, each level requires its own lexicon, which would not make sense applied at other levels. So, levels communicate by transforming information at their boundaries. Generally, because of the dynamical screening off between levels, a higher level entity 'reads' a statistical / macroscopic summary of ensemble, microscopic, behaviors at the next lower level, and, facing the other way, 'reads' a higher level as being an unchanging, or periodically changing (long period cyclic), set of boundary conditions. If focal level dynamics were represented by variables in an equation, then the results of dynamics at contiguous levels would be represented by (nonrecursive) constants. Larger scale dynamics are so slow with respect to those at the focal level, that the current value of their momentary result appears relatively unchanging with respect to processes at the focal level. Cumulated results of lower scale dynamics also appear -- in this case statistically -- unchanging at the focal level, as it takes a very long time for activities taking place in lower scale moments to effect a macroscopic change detectable at the focal level -- these points are the essence of the dynamical 'screening off' between levels in material applications of the compositional hierarchy model. Note that, because of these relations, thermodynamic equilibria would be more rapidly achieved per unit volume at a lower scalar level, delivering an adiabatic principle relating to screening off. While change of any kind (development, acceleration, diffusion) is relatively more rapid at lower levels, absolute translational motion can be more rapid at higher levels. Thus, higher levels provide modes of convection – dissipative structures -- for the dissipation of energy gradients, which would otherwise proceed only by slow conduction at the lowest level instead. Related to these , we should note that metabolic rates and development are absolutely faster in smaller dissipative structures (organisms, fluid vortices, etc.), and that their natural spans are on average comparatively shorter than would be the case for larger scale ones. Related to this line of thought is the ‘Price equation’ in evolutionary biology, which models relations between selective pressures at multiple levels in the relevant biological hierarchy -- [[[[genetic] organismic] trait group] population]. On the hierarchical principle here stated, rates of change at the lower levels would be faster than at the upper levels. This fact was used to argue against the efficacy of ‘group selection’ between populations because natural selection within populations would eliminate any altruistic genetic predispositions before these could be decisive in competition between populations. However, if the different populations do not lose their altruistic types at the same rates, maintaining a ‘variance in fitness’ between them, then if a large scale, catastrophic, selection pressure (unusual environmental change) descends upon all the populations, those with a critical number of altruists might survive better than the others, keeping the altruists well represented in the species. Thus, while rates of change would be faster at lower levels, comparatively more massive effects at slower rates in higher levels could be decisive in the longer run. One sometimes sees the term ‘heterarchy’, posed in opposition to the compositional hierarchy model because of supposed failures of actual systems to conform to hierarchical constraints. One needs to recall here again that hierarchy is a conceptual construction, an analytical tool, and use of it does not imply that the world itself is actually hierarchically organized. It does seem to be so in many ways, but to suppose that this logical principle is actually embodied in the world would be naive. Hierarchy is one conceptual tool among many. The heterarchy dissent needs to focus upon what some take to be the true basis of material applications of the scale hierarchy -- the order of magnitude separation of rates of change among levels separated by scale. If we have a heterogeneous field of systems of different sizes and rates, with no obvious separations between them, we would assign levels solely on the basis of this rate difference criterion. If no order of magnitude rate differences are found between entities, then the system would be judged to not be differentiated hierarchically. If we have a network of variably connected nodes, where contact between some are strongly lagged compared to most, then the systemic information flows might be hierarchically organized. In the heterarchy perspective, it could also be the case that higher level entities might have several alternative lower level components among which they could switch their regulatory influence. Thus, in one situation a higher level, A, might regulate x, y, and z, while in another context it would regulate a, b, x and z. This is fully consistent with the principles of compositional hierarchies, even in cases that are not nested Often the ‘hetero’ opposition to hierarchy is based merely on faulty understanding (sometimes politically motivated!). For example, the tides are affected (partially controlled) by gravitational effects associated with the moon; yet the oceans are not nested inside the moon. As in classical thermodynamics, it is important to see the whole system appropriately. The oceans are nested, along with the earth itself, within the solar system, and from the hierarchical point of view, these effects on the tides emanate from the level of the solar system, not merely from the moon. Another point concerning heterarchy is that the basic three-level scale hierarchy represents a system in a steady state configuration. Systems in transit may be highly turbulent, with episodic direct communications between levels distant in scale. Some systems that we can observe, like the surface of Jupiter, may be turbulent at a time scale very much slower than our own observational scale, and they might seem to be in a steady state on that account. But they should not be expected to display scale separated levels. Many systems we might observe would be in transit, but our models of things in the world tend to make the assumption of a tractable steady state, or at least momentary, conditions. As we descend in applications to the realm of fundamental particles, it may be that some of these rules would break down, via, e.g., quantum nonlocality. Compositional hierarchical models represent events and transactions in the material world -- a realm of friction and lag in the affairs of chemical elements and their compositions. From the scale hierarchy perspective, the quantum world could conveniently be viewed as in the quantum wave function – an electron would be ‘everywhere’ at once because its accelerated motion would be so relatively fast as to create a blur for a macroscopic observer.

(b) Dynamics in applications of the subsumption hierarchy are entrained by development, which is modeled as the process of refinement of a class, or increased specification of a category. It is important to note that this process is open-ended in the sense that there could be many coordinate subclasses of a given class, since the subsumptive hierarchy forms a tree. Thus, the potentials arising within any class form a tree. In the hierarchy, {physical realm {material realm {biological realm }}}, or in {mammal {primate {human }}} each of these hierarchies follows just one branch of an implied tree. Rylean categories can branch into new distinctions (and this forms a link with the scalar hierarchy because this process would give rise as well to new logical types). Evolution (unpredictable change) is one -> many, and thus we have been able to picture the results of biological evolution using the Linnaean hierarchy. Currently biological evolution is not viewed as having developmental aspects, but that does not vitiate use of the subsumptive model to track its changes because in a material world any change is necessarily launched upon previous forms. This allows a degree of predictability to evolution; for example, predictions of active flight in vertebrates would plausibly be focused upon the forelimbs (true even for flying fishes!). The fact that this is functionally a two-level hierarchy makes it susceptible to emergent evolution, because, without the anchoring provided by a third level, it can be, in a sense, reduced functionally to a single, newly emergent level subsuming all the previous levels. How is its direction of change into new subclasses insured, giving rise to the hierarchy? In models of the material world this is afforded by the fact that information, once in place (or once having had an effect), marks a system irrevocably. Marks in natural material systems are permanent, usually leaving traces even if subsequently obliterated. If a material system continues to exist, it must march forward if it changes; there can be no ‘reversal of evolution’. Its physical basis is spontaneously irreversible. Since change in the material world is entrained by the Second Law of thermodynamics, we would have here a link between material examples of the two hierarchy models because the Second Law can be seen to be a result of the expansion of the universe being too rapid to allow for the global equilibration of . As noted above, this expansion is also what affords the interpolation of new levels in examples of the compositional hierarchy. So, development in a subsumptive hierarchy model requires a two-level basic form. Yet such hierarchies typically involve more than just two levels. Why do not the more general levels prevent change, as by the weight of their accumulated information at some locale or in some system or entity? Here we are led to note another aspect of development, which is perfectly general. The amount of change (effort, energy) required to launch a new level is ever smaller as a material subsumptive hierarchy develops -- refinements are just that. This is also a materialist principle. The more general levels continue to exert their influence; thus, e.g., biology is mostly a kind of chemistry, and humans are mostly a kind of mammal. The key to understanding this situation is that in a subsumptive hierarchy informational relations between levels are transitive. Thus, physical dynamics are fully active players in a biological system. This means that we can sufficiently understand developmental change in this hierarchical model using only two contiguous integrative levels, since all prior levels would be active together in the emergence of a new level. New levels may branch off anywhere in a subsumptive hierarchy, potentially giving rise to collections of coordinate subclasses. This raises in our , e.g., the possibility of other kinds of life, or of other chemistries in other universes. Regarding causal relations in applications of either hierarchy, more work needs to be done. It has seemed to me that a systems approach like the Aristotelian causal categories could be a useful starting point in this regard. In applications of the compositional hierarchy, representing some ongoing process, my sketch would suggest material causes in the lowest of the three levels, efficient causes in the focal level, and both formal and final causes in the upper level. The subsumptive hierarchy representing development, would have final causes entraining the development in the innermost (highest or emerging) level, with mixtures of material and efficient causes in the lower levels, and with formal causes embodied in the current configurations of a ‘pregnant’ level.

Informational relations and semiotics

(a) As noted above, informational relations between levels in a compositional hierarchy are non- transitive. The levels are screened off from each other dynamically, and influence each other only indirectly, via transformed informational constraints. Impacts and perturbations moving from one level to another are transformed into signs at boundaries between the levels, as, for example, when the results of biosyntheses in cells have an effect on an organism only if, and after, a certain concentration is reached. When this constraint is not the case, as when a signal from a higher level occasionally transits directly to a much lower level, that level may suffer damage (as when an organism is hit by lightning, or, going the other way, when a particular cell affects the whole organism, this could come about only when and if its effect is promoted by cancerous growth). Here we can note again the idea that levels differing in the scale of their dynamics deliver stability to a system, via the screening-off effect. Unstable systems, e.g., turbulent ones, are not well represented using a compositional hierarchy. The interpolation of an emergent level between two others can be viewed as involving the appearance of a capability in the uppermost level (via fluctuation, self-organization and/or selection) for making a significant (to it) interpretation of events at what then becomes relegated to being the lowermost level of three. The upper level effectively disposes -- facilitates cohesion among -- some of what (has become) the lowest level proposes. As the arena of the upper level's interpretations, causal relations at the new level act as a filter or buffer between the now upper and lower levels bracketing it. This allows us to see levels emerging between each other by way of a classification procedure whereby relatively microscopic topological difference information (say, in chemical mixtures) is converted to, or coheres macroscopically as typological distinction information located in the new middle level as interpreted by the upper level, in an essentially top-down semiotic procedure. Thus, chemical concentrations may be detected at the upper level only when they reach some threshold effect in the middle level. In the absence of classification by an upper level, communication between levels cannot occur directly, as the ‘moments’ of levels separated by scale -- their ‘cogent moments’ -- would differ by order(s) of magnitude. For example, an upper level could not perceive individual actions at the lowest level, and would synthesize them as a blur, detecting only ensemble effects. So then, we could never communicate our intentions, as such, to, e.g., Gaia! But she might interpret the cumulating results of our activities, like the production of carbon dioxide from our technologies, as calling for the generation of massive fluid vortices like hurricanes. I note again that the ‘languages’ at different levels in a compositional hierarchy would be different. The way molecules combine to form a cell differs from the way cells combine to form organs or organisms, or from the way organisms form family groups. The statistical properties of compositional hierarchies are transitive across the whole, but meanings do not transcend particular levels, as such, remaining unique to each level. It is worth noting here that there have been attempts to locate isomorphic forms at different levels, partly in hopes of getting some initial leverage on forms at levels very far from our own in scale. The presence of such isomorphies would not invalidate the non-translatability of meanings across levels, but would raise interesting questions as to their interpretation by the outside observer using this model.

(b) In a subsumptive hierarchy the lower levels also make possible the emergence of a new realm, in an epigenetic (building-upon) process. And here too the process is top-down, but in a different sense, involving finality. Thus, e.g., we can see that organism sociality implies biology in the sense of material implication or conceptual subordination. Then, as organism sociality implies biology, biology implies chemistry, and so, because these relations will have come about as a process of refinement, only a relatively narrow set of possibilities could imply organism sociality. That is, chemistry could give rise to many kinds of subsystems, biology to fewer, and sociality to even fewer as the overall material system – as an epigenetic system -- develops. Developments (in contrast to evolution) are entrained by final causes, and approach them asymptotically with each emergence of a new condition. Involved here as well, as in all developments, is the process of senescence, a condition of information overload. Recall that information in this hierarchy is transitive across levels, leading in the higher levels toward a condition of overconnectivity, leading in turn to functional underconnectivity, leading in its turn to inflexibility and habit driven responses (loss of requisite variety), leading ultimately to loss of adaptability. From this viewpoint, the number of realms (chemical, biological, etc.) in the world would likely be quite limited. Thus, even though new higher levels could occasionally arise above the sociocultural level among humans (e.g., a Noosphere), they could be predicted, using the subsumptive hierarchy model, to have a difficult time maintaining themselves for very long, even as does a senescent organism. Evolutionary biologists might object to the role assigned here to finality, given that there is no evidence of final causes in observations of the fossil record, or any conscious use of it in the neoDarwinian theory of evolution. I note again that the subsumptive hierarchy is one where lower levels subsume the higher. Then we might note that the Second Law of thermodynamics at the lowest, physical, integrative level entrains all changes finalistically toward thermodynamic equilibration of the global system of the universe. At the chemical integrative level this is seen as changes directed toward the condition of least free energy locally. These directed changes are subtending biological changes, where we observe the activities of living dissipative structures. Given the inheritance of properties from lower integrative levels, these too could be supposed to be working to dissipate their supporting energy gradients as rapidly as possible -- short of damaging the system. We can note, for example, that the transcription of genetic information into protein products – a central biological image – depends upon the dissipation of energy stored in ATP, which would occur under the constraint of lowering the available free energy as expeditiously as possible locally. Here we face the possibility that a finalistic tendency subtending a higher integrative level must be being promoted at that highest level. It then becomes plausible that the expansion of biological systems, as represented in the Linnaean hierarchy, can be viewed overall as a process of promoting access to increasing numbers of as yet untapped energy gradients. From the currently ascendant perspective on organic evolution, adaptation would be entrained by no final causes. If that is the case, then the overall evolutionary phenomenon, as a series of happenstances that can be modeled in the subsumptive format merely because of material inheritance, would formally be a degenerate application, with no theoretical implications. I merely point out here that the Linnaean model, being in the subsumptive format, therefore generates a sense of conceptual unease. Models normally exemplify a theory, but it would not be surprising if they also implied one that is as yet unformulated. We know that developments are entrained by finalistic tendencies and can be modeled by a subsumptive hierarchy (as demonstrated above in the formal relations section), and so the question may arise as to whether that which is modeled in the Linnaean hierarchy might also be so entrained. Since science is mediated by logical discourse, might it not also on occasion be entrained by it? Considering semiotics, it has been suggested that higher integrative levels would have greater ‘semiotic freedom’. This would be a result of the greater elaboration of forms at these levels, allowing greater precision of interpretation, as well as reactions to finer distinctions. That is, reaction to (or interpretation of) a stimulus would at higher levels be more underdetermined by the actual physical interactions taking place in the lower integrative levels. In this way, e.g., the result of a light ray impacting the retina of, say, a fish could not be predicted without knowing further what species of fish the retina is part of and what its current context is. Thus, the hierarchy:

{physiosemiosis {chemosemiosis {biosemiosis {anthroposemiosis}}}} models an increase in semiotic freedom. As one moves into the higher levels, there would be an increasing burden of informational constraints bounding the behavior of individuals (e.g., mice can neither divide mitotically nor fly), but some of these are enabling constraints, allowing definite choices in the more detailed, as well as more limited, world of an individual in the innermost, upper, level. Thus, mice might reasonably be supposed to have the possibly of evolving flight. Languages, at the highest known (socio-cultural) integrative level can represent very many quite particular relations, but each language has its own realm, with none encompassing all possible linguistic references (viz. the Whorffian hypothesis). The more you can say in detail, the more (as located on another branch of the hierarchy) you cannot say! c) Relations between the compositional and subsumptive hierarchies are only now beginning to be examined using abstract tools, like hyperstructures. One possible approach already suggested could be to see applications of these forms as being orthogonally related, with the subsumptive hierarchy tracing change, while at any instant or stage the trajectory would be in the form of a compositional hierarchy. The diagram in Figure 1 shows these relations as seen from the point of view of an observer located as simultaneously at the top of a subsumptive hierarchy and in the middle of a compositional hierarchy.

Figure 1 The subsumptive hierarchy is shown as a pyramid surrounding the observer located at the highest level, with its levels listed horizontally. The compositional hierarchy is not shown, but is listed from left to right horizontally extending from the smallest scale at the left to the largest at the right, with the observer in the center. The levels on the left are contained within the observer, those on the right contain him/her. Conclusion

In view of the completely different organization of compositional and subsumptive hierarchies, users ought to become familiar enough with these forms and their possible uses so that choice of hierarchical structure for modeling will be informed rather than haphazard. Many natural systems can support either kind of model, and the choice would be made according to the nature of the investigation.

Acknowledgements I thank Arto Annila, Joseph Brenner, Michael Corner, Malcolm Dean, Andrew Finkelkurts, Paul Gerome, Sungchul Ji, Cliff Joslyn, Nadja Kunz, John McCrone, Gary G. Nelson, Stuart Newman, Bjorn Reese, Kim Sterelny, Jitse van der Meer, and Jerry Zhu for helpful discussion and comments.

Appendix – Further Readings

The following sources emphasize the historically important and logically basic, as well as recent (post 1990) references that seem to me to bring in new departures and interesting applications, which could have implications for the principles. These latter also show some of the recent diversity of approaches, usually made in ignorance of principles or of each other’s efforts. The presence of a post-1990 paper here does not indicate endorsement by me of all of these works.

Starred* references deal with the subsumption hierarchy, either exclusively or along with the compositional hierarchy.

§ References added after online publication. The Potochnik reference contains several further references missed in my list. It struggles with the conflation of compositional and subsumptive hierarchies. The Botvinick (’08) paper, and those of Ellis clearly distinguish the two forms of hierarchy, as does the Tecumseh Smith & Martin article.

§Abbot R ( ) The reductionist blind spot.. Complexity 14: 10-12. *Aghagolzadeh M, Soltanian H, Araabi BN (2011) Information theoretic hierarchical clustering. Entropy 2011, 13: 450-465. Agre PE (2003) Hierarchy and history in Simon’s “Architecture of Complexity”. J Learning Sci 12: 413-426. Ahl V, Allen TFH (1996) Hierarchy Theory: A Vision, Vocabulary, and Epistemology. Columbia University Press, New York § Al-Aidroos N, Said CP, Turk-Browne B (2012) Top-down attention switches coupling between low-level and high-level areas of human visual cortex. Proc Nat Acad Sci US www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1202095109 § Allen B, Blake CS, Bar-Yam Y (2014) An information-theoretic formalism for multiscale structure in complex systems. arXiv:I 409.4708v I Allen TFH, Starr TB (1982) Hierarchy: Perspectives For Ecological Complexity. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Alm E, Arkin AP (2003) Biological networks. Curr Opin Struct Biol 13: 193-202. Alvarez de Lorenzana J (1993) The constructive universe and the evolutionary systems framework. Appendix in Salthe, SN, Development and Evolution: Complexity and Change in Biology. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. pp. 291-308. Alvarez de Lorenzana J (1998) Self-organization and self-construction of order. In Van de van Vijver G, Salthe SN, Delpos, M (eds.) Evolutionary Systems: Biological and Epistemological Perspectives on Selection and Self-organization. Kluwer, Dordrecht. Alyushin A (2010) Time scales of observation and ontological levels of reality. Axiomathes DOI 10.1007/s10516-010-9099-7 *Andrade E (2003) The processing of information (analog/digital) is the causal factor of the emergence of natural hierarchies. Ludus Vitalis 11: 85-106. Anderson D, Tenzer A, Barley G, Girvan M, Antonsen TM (2011) Multiscale oscillator interactions in large networks. arXiv:1112.0060v1 [nlin.CD] *Anderson P (1972) More is different: broken symmetry and the hierarchical nature of science. Science 177: 393-396. Anderson PB, Emmeche C, Finnemann NO, Christiansen PB (2000) Downward Causation: Minds, Bodies, Matter. Aarhus University Press, Aarhus. § Annila A, Baverstock k (2014) Genes without prominence: a reappraisal of the foundations of biology. J Royal Soc: Interface 11: 20131017. Annila A, Kuismanen R (2008) Natural hierarchy emerges from energy dispersal. BioSystems 95: 227- 233. Anteneodo C, Da Luz MGD (2010) Complex dynamics of life at different scales: from genomic to global environmental issues. Phil Trans Royal Soc A, 368: 5561-5568. § Arnal, LH, Giraud A-L (2012) Cortical oscillations and sensory predictions. Trends Cogn Sci http://dx.doi.org/19.1016/j.tics.2012.06.003 § Arias CF, Catalan P, Manrubia S, Cuesta JA (2014) toyLIFE: a computational framework to study the multi-level organization of the genotype-phenotype map. http://arxiv.org/abs/ 1409.4904 § Armbrust EV (2014) Taking the pulse of ocean microbes. Science 345: 134-135. *Aronson LR (1984) Levels of integration and organization: a reevaluation of the evolutionary scale. In: Greenberg G, Tobach E (eds) Behavioral Evolution and Integrative Levels. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ § Attanasi et al (2014) Collective behavior without collective order without collective order in wild swarms of midges, PLoS Comput Biol 10(7): e1003697. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi. 1003697 Auffray C, Nottale L (2008) Scale relativity theory and integrative systems biology: 1, founding principles and scale laws. Progr Biophys Mol Biol 97: 79-114. Auger P (1989) Dynamics and Thermodynamics in Hierarchically Organized Systems. Pergamon Press, Oxford Auletta G, Ellis GFR, Jaeger L (2008) Top-down causation by information control: from a philosophical problem to a scientific research programme. J Roy Soc Interface doi:10.1098/rsif/ 2008.0018. § Aziz- Alaoui MA, Bertelle C (eds) (2009) From System Complexity to Emergent Properties. Springer. *Baas NA (2006) Hyperstructures as abstract matter. Adv Compl Sys 9: 157-182. § Bailly, F., and Longo, G. (2009). Biological organization and anti-entropy. J. Biol. Syst. 17: 63–96. § Balcan D et al (2009) Multiscale mobility networks and the large scale spreading of infectious diseases. 2009/07/20, arXiv:0907.3304 § Baldassarre G, Mirolli M (eds) (2013) Computational and Robotic Models of the Hierarchical Organization of Behavior. Springer. Barkley Rosser J Jr, Folke C, Günther F, Isomaki H, Perrings C, Puu T (1994) Discontinuous change in multilevel hierarchical systems. Sys Res Behav Sci 11: 77-94. § Barrett GW, Peles JD, Odum EP (1997) Transcending processes and the levels-of- organization concept. Bioscience 47: 531-535 Bar Yam Y (2004) Multiscale complexity/entropy. Adv in Complex Syst 7: 47-63. Bastin T, Noyes HP, Amson J, Kilmister CW (1979) On physical interpretation and mathematical structure of the combinatorial hierarchy. Int J Theor Phys 18: 445-488. Batty M (2010) Visualizing space-time dynamics in scaling systems. Complexity 2010:1-13. Bechtel W (2010) The cell: locus or object of inquiry? Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci doi: 10.1016/j.shpsc2010.07.006 Bedau MA (2003) Downward causation and the autonomy of weak emergence. Principia 6: 5-50. §Beer S. (1984) The viable system model: its provenance, development, methodology and pathology. J Operational Res Soc 35: 7–25 Behrens TEJ, Jocham, G (2011) How to perfect a chocolate soufflé and other important problems. Neuron Previews Bénichou, O, Loverdo C, Moreau M, Voituriez R (2011) Intermittent search strategies. arXiv: 1104.o639 Berntson GG, Norman GJ, Hawkley LC, Cacioppo JT (2012) Evolution of neuroarchitecture, multilevel analyses and calibrative reductionism. Interface Focus (2012) 2: 65-73. Bertalanffy L von (1968) General System Theory: Foundations, Development, Applications. Braziller, New York (see especially the Introduction) § Betzel RF, Griffa A, Avena-Koenigsberger A, Goñi J, Thiran J-P, Hagman P, Sporns O (2013) Multi-scale community organization of the human structural connectome and its relationship with resting-state functional connectivity. Network Sci 1:353-373. *Bickhard MH, Campbell DT (2003) Variations in variation and selection: the ubiquity of the variation-and-selective-retention ratchet in emergent organizational complexity. Found Sci 8: 215-282. Bishop RC (2007) Downward causation in fluid convection. Synthese 160: 229-248. Bishop RC (2012) Fluid convection, constraint and causation. Interface Focus (2012) 2: 4-12. § Biswas K, He H, Blum ID, Wu C-I, Hogan TP, Seidman DN, Dravid VP, Kanatzidis MG (2012) High-performance bulk thermoelectrics with all-scale hierarchical structures. Nature 489: 414-418. Bitbol M (2009) Downward causation without foundations. Synthese DOI 10.1007/s1 1229-010-9723-5 *Blitz D (1992) Emergent Evolution: Qualitative Novelty and the Levels of Reality. Kluwer, Dordrecht §* Bolhuis LL, Tattersall I, Chomsky N, Berwick RC (2014) How could language have evolved? PLOS Biology Bonabeau E, Dorigo M, Theraulaz G (1999) Swarm Intelligence: From Natural to Artificial Systems. Oxford University Press, New York Bonner J (1969) The Scale of Nature. Pegasus, Glendale Heights, IL § *Botvinick MM (2008) Hierarchical models of behavior and prefrontal function. Trends Cogn Sci 12: 201-208. *Botvinick MM, Niv Y, Barto AC (2009) Hierarchically organized behavior and its neural foundations: a reinforcement learning perspective. Cognition 113: 262-280. § Bouarfa S, Blum, HAP, Curran R, Mariken HCE (2013) Agent-based modeling and simulation of emergent behavior in air transportation. Complex Adapt Syst Model 2013 1:15 doi: 10.1186/2194-3206-1-15 § Brandon RN (1990) Adaptation and Environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Brenner JE (2008) Logic In Reality. Springer, New York §* Brier S (2003) Information seen as a part of the development of living intelligence: the five-leveled cybersemiotic framework for FIS. Entropy 2003, 5: 88-99 Buege, DJ (1997) An ecologically-informed ontology for environmental ethics. Biol. Philos 12: 1-20. *Bunge, M (1967) Scientific Research I: The Search For System. Springer, New York (Chapter 2) Bunge M (1977) Treatise of Basic Philosophy, Volume 3: The Furniture of the World. Reidel, Dordrecht Bunge, M. (1979) Treatise of Basic Philosophy, Volume 4: A World of Systems. Reidel, Dordrecht. Buss L (1987) The Evolution of Individuality. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ. *Butterfield J (2011) Laws, causation and dynamics at different levels. Interface Focus (2012) 2: 101-114. (Also 2014 arXiv:1606.4732v1) Callebaut W, Rasskin-Gutman D (eds) (2005) Modularity: Understanding the Development of Natural Complex Systems. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA Campbell DT (1974) ‘Downward causation' in hierarchically organized biological systems. In: Ayala FJ., Dobzhansky T (eds) Studies in the Philosophy of Biology. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA § Campbell, R J, Bickhard M (2011). Physicalism, emergence and downward causation. Axiomathes, 21, 33-56. Cantono S, Solomon S. (2010) When the collective acts on its components: economic crisis, autocatalytic percolation. New J Phys 12 075038. Caporael LR, Brewer MB (1995) Hierarchical evolutionary theory: there is an alternative, and it’s not creationism. Psychol Inquiry 6: 31-80. *Chaisson EJ (1998) The cosmic environment for the growth of complexity. BioSystems 46: 13-19. Chandler JLR (1997) Semiotics of complex systems: a hierarchical notation for the mathematical structure of a single cell. Proc Conf Euro 97. § Chandler JLR (2008) Ordinate logics of living systems. In: Vrobel S, Rössler OE, Marks- Tarlow T (eds) Simultaneity: Temporal Structures and Observer Perspectives. World Scientific, Singapore §*Changizi MA (2003) The Brain From Twenty-five Thousand Feet. Synthese Libr 317 § Chauvet GA (1993) Hierarchical functional organization of formal biological systems: a dynamical approach. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B, 339:425-444. § Chauvet GA (1993) Hierarchical functional organization of formal biological systems: a dynamical approach. II. The concept of non-symmetry leads to a criterion of evolution deduced from an optimum principle of the (O-FBS) sub-system. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B, 339: 445-461. § *Chibarro S. Rondoni L, Vulpiani A (2014) Reductionism, Emergence and Levels of Reality: The Importance of Being Borderline. Springer, New York. § *Choi W-J, Choi T-S (2013) Automated pulmonary nodule detection system in computed tomography images: a hierarchical block classification approach. Entropy 2013, 15: 507-523. § Clarke E (2014) The origins of evolutionary transitions. J Biosci 39: 303-319. Clauset A. Moore C, Newman MEJ (2007) Structural inference of hierarchies in networks. Lect Notes Comp Sci 2007, Vol. 4503/2007: 1-13. § C;auset A, Moore C, Newman MEJ (2008) Hierarchical structure and prediction of missing links in =20 networks. asXiv 2008/11/04, DOI: 0811.0484, =20= Clements FE (1916) Plant Succession: An Analysis of the Development of Vegetation. Carnegie Institute of Washington, Washington DC § Clune J, Mouret, J-B; Lipson H (2012) The evolutionary origins of modularity. arXiv: 1207.2743v1 [q-bio.PE] 11 July 2012 Coffman JA (2006) Developmental ascendency: from bottom-up to top-down control. Biol Theory 1: 165-178. Collier J (1989) Supervenience and reduction in biological hierarchies. Can J Philos 14: 209-234. Collier J (2003) Hierarchical dynamical systems with a focus on biology. Entropy 5: 100-124. Collier J (2008) Information in biological systems. In Adriaans P, van Benthem J (eds) Handbook of Philosophy of Science, Volume 8, Philosophy of Information. Elsevier, New York. § *Collier J (2011) Kinds of information in scientific use. tripleC 9:295-304. Collier J, Muller S (1998) The dynamical basis of emergence in natural hierarchies. In: Farre G, Oksala T (eds) Emergence, Complexity, Hierarchy and Organization: Selected and Edited Papers From the ECHO III Conference. Acta Polytechnica Scandinavica. MA91 Finnish Academy of Technology, Espoo *Comte A (1830) Cours de Philosophie Positive. Bachelier, Paris *Conger GP (1925) The doctrine of levels. J Philos 22: 309-321. Conrad M (1983) Adaptability: The Significance of Variability from Molecule to Ecosystem. Plenum, New York. Conrad M (1996) Cross-scale information processing in evolution, development and intelligence. BioSystems 38: 97-109. *Cook DL, Bookstein FL, Gennari JH (2011) Physical properties of biological entities: an introduction to the ontology of physics for biology. PLoS ONE 6(12): e28708. doi:10.1371/ journal.pone.0028708. *Corner, M (1977) The nature of : some persistent conceptual difficulties and a practical solution. Progr Brain Res 45: 471-475 *Corominas-Murta B, Goni J., Ridriguez-Caso C, Solé R (2010) Hierarchy and information in feed-forward networks. arXiv:1011 4394vI. § *Corominas-Murta B, Goni J, Solé RV, Rodriguez-Caso C (2013) Hierarchy in complex systems: the possible and the actual. arXiv:1303.2503v1 [physics.soc-ph] §Corominas-Murta B, Goni J, Solé RV, Rodriguez-Caso c (2013) On the origins of hierarchy in complex networks. Proc Nat. Acad, Sci. www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1300832110 Cottam R, Ranson W, Vounckx R (2000). Autocreative hierarchy I: structure – ecosystemic dependence and autonomy, SEED Journal 4: 24-41. Cottam R, Ranson W, Vounckx R (2003) Autocreative hierarchy II: dynamics - self- organization, emergence and level-changing. In: Hexmoor H (ed.), International Conference on Integration of Knowledge Intensive Multi-Agent Systems, IEEE: Piscataway, NJ, pp. 766-773. § Craver CF (2001) Role unctions, mechanisms and hierarchy. Philos Sci 68: 31-55. § Craver CF (2007) Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Clarendon Press: Oxford UK. (Chapter 5: A Field-Guide to Levels) § Craver CF (2009) Levels. In: Symons J, Calvo P (eds) Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Psychology. Routledge, New Jersey. Craver CF, Bechtel W (2007) Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biol Philos 22: 547-563. § *Crews D, Gore AC (2012) Epigenetic synthesis: a need for a new paradigm for evolution in a contaminated world. Biol Rep 4: 18 Crutchfield JP (2011) Between order and chaos. Nature Physics 8:17-24. § Curato G, Lillo F (2014) Multiscale model selection for high frequency financial data of a large tick stock by means of the Jensen-Shannon metric. Entropy 2014 16: 567-581. § D-Agostino G, Scala A (2014) Networks of Networks: The Last Frontier of Complexity . Springer Dayan P, Hinton GE (1996) Varieties of Helmholtz machine. Neural Netw 9: 1385-1403. Deguet J, Demazeau Y Magnin L (200). Elements about the emergence issue: a survey of emergence definitions. ComPlexUs 3: 24-31. § delle Site L (2014) What is a multiscale problem in molecular dynamics. Entropy 2014 16: 23-40. Dusenbery DB (2009) Living at Micro Scale: The Unexpected Physics of Being Small. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA § Efatmaneshnik M, Ryan MJ (2015) On optimal modularity for system construction. http:// dx.doi.org/10.1002/cplx.21646 Ehresmann AC, Vanbremeersch JP (2007) Memory Evolutive Systems: Hierarchy, Emergence, Cognition. Elsevier, New York. *Elder-Vass D (2012) Top-down causation and social structures. Interface Focus (2012) 2: 82-90. Eldredge N (1985) Unfinished Synthesis: Biological Hierarchies and Modern Evolutionary Thought. Oxford University Press, New York. § Eldredge N (1986) Information, economics, and evolution. Ann Rev Ecol Syst 17: 351-369. § Eldredge N (2003) The sloshing bucket: how the physical realm controls evolution. In Crutchfield JP, Schuster P (eds) Evolutionary Dynamics. Oxford University Press, New York. § Eldredge N (2008) Hierarchies and the sloshing bucket: toward a unification of evolutionary biology. Evo Devo Outreach 1: 10-15. Eldredge N, Salthe SN (1984) Hierarchy and evolution. Oxford Surv Evol Biol 1: 184-20 § *Ellis. GFR (2004) True complexity and its associated ontology. In: Barrow P, Davies CW, Harper CL (eds) Science and Ultimate Reality: Quantum Theory, Cosmology and Complexity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. § *Ellis, GFR (2008) On the nature of causation in complex systems. Trans Royal Soc Sooth Africa 63: 69-84. *Ellis GFR, (2012) Top-down causation and emergence: some comments on mechanisms. Interface Focus 2: 126-140. *Emmeche C, Koppe S, Stjernfelt F (2000) Levels, emergence, and three versions of downward causation. In Andersen PB, Emmeche C, Finnemann NO, Christiansen PV (eds) Downward Causation: Minds, Bodies and Matter. Aarhus University Press, Aarhus. § *Esbjorn-Hargens S, Zimmermann ME (2009) Integral Ecology: Uniting Multiple Perspectives on the Natural World. Integral Books, Boston *Fanelli D (2010) “Positive” results increase down the hierarchy of the sciences. PLoS ONE 5(4):e10068.doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0010068 §*Fanelli D, Glänzel W (2013) Bibliometric Evidence for a Hierarchy of the Sciences. PLoS ONE 8(6): e66938. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0066938 § *Fanelli D, Glånzel W (2013) Bibliometric evidence for a hierarchy of the sciences. PLoS ONE 8(6): e66938.doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0066938 Fazekas P, Kertész G (2011} Causation at different levels: tracking the commitments of mechanistic explanations. Biol Philos 26: 365-383. *Feibleman JK (1954) Theory of integrative levels. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 5: 59-66. § *Feynman, R. (1994) The Character of Physical Law. MIT Press: Cambridge, MA. § Felipe del Castillo L, Vera-Cruz P (2011) Thermodynamic formulation of living systems and their evolution. J Mod Phys 2: 379-391. § Findlay SD, Thagard P (2012) How parts make up wholes. Frontiers in Physiology 3: Article 455. *Fingelkurts AA, Fingelkurts AA, Neves CFH (2010) Natural world physical, brain operational, and mind-phenomenal space-time. Phys Life Rev 7: 195-249. *Fingelkurtz AA, Fingelkurts AA (2011) Mind as nested operational architectonics of the brain: comment on “Neuroontology, neurobiological naturalism, and consciousness: a challenge to scientific reduction and a solution.” by Todd E. Feinberg. Phys Life Rev DOI: 10.1016/ j.plrev.2011.10.019. § *Fiscus, D, Fath Bd, Goerner S (2012) A trimodal nature of life applied for actualizing a win-win human environmental relation and sustainability. Emergence, Complexity & Organization 14: 44-88. § Fleury P, Dupuy H.Uzan J-P (2013) Can all cosmological observations be accurately interpreted with a unique geometry? Phys Rev Lett 111, 091302 *Floridi L (2008) The method of levels of abstraction. Minds and Machines 18: 303-329. § *Fleissner P, Hofkirchner W (1996) Emergent information: towards a unified information theory. BioSystems 38: 243-248. Folse HJ, III, Roughgarden J (2010) What is an individual organism: a multilevel selection perspective. Quart Rev Biol 85: 447-472. § *Foskett DJ (1978) The theory of integrative levels and its relevance to the design of information systems. ASLIB Proceedings 30: 6, 202-208. § *Foster, J (2005) From simplistic to complex systems in economics. Cambridge J Econ 29: 873-892. § Fotouhie B, Rabbat MG (2013) Dynamics of influence on hierarchical structures. Phys Rev E 88 022105 § Foucault M (1980) Truth and Power, Harvester Press, Brighton. Ch. 6, p. 114. § *Frank SL, Bid R, Christiansen MH (2012) How hierarchical is language use? Proc Royal Soc B 279: 4522-4531. Freeman WJ, Vitiello G (2011) The dissipative brain and non-equilibrium thermodynamics. J Cosmol 14: 4461-4468. *Friston KJ (2008) Hierarchical models in the brain. PLoS Comput Biol 4: e1000211. § * Gaertner L, Sedikides C, Luke M, O’Mara EM, Iuzzini J, Jackson LE, Cai H, Wu Q (2012) A motivational hierarchy within: primacy of the individual self, relational self, or collective self? J Exp Social Psychol 48: 997-1013. Gafiychuk VV, Lubashevsky IA, Ulanowicz RE (1997) Distributed self-regulation in ecological and economic systems. Complex Syst 4: 357-372. Galvao V, Miranda JGV, Andrade RFS, Andrade JS Jr, Gallos LK, Makse HA (2010) Modularity map of the network of human cell differentiation. Proc Nat Acad Sci US www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.0914748107 § Gershenson C, Fernanez N (2012) Complexity and information: measuring emergence, self- organization, and homeostasis at multiple scales. Complexity DOI 10.1002/cplx arXiv: 1205.2026v1 [cs.IT] 9 May 2012 Ghoniem N, Hatsopoulos GN (eds) (2011) Meeting the Entropy Challenge. American Institute of Physics Conference Proceedings 1033. Melville. Giampietro M, Mayumi K (2004) Complex systems and energy. Encyclopedia of Energy, Volume 1. Elsevier, New York § Gibcus JH, Dekker J (2013) Review the hierarchy of the 3D genome. Mol Cell 49: 773-782. Gibson CC, Ostrum E, Ahn TK (2000) The concept of scale and the human dimensions of global change. Ecol Econom 32: 217-239. § Gibson LJ (2012) The hierarchical structure and mechanics of plant materials. J R Soc Interface doi: 10.1098/rsif.2012.0341 § Giesebrecht B, Jocelyn S. Dundesen C, Killingsbaek S (2014) A new perspective on the perceptual selectivity of attention under load. Ann. NY Acad Sci 1316L 71-86. Gladyshev GP, (1999) On thermodynamics, entropy and evolution of biological systems: what is life from a physical chemist’s viewpoint. Entropy 1999 1: 9-20. Gladyshev GP, (2006) The principle of substance stability is applicable to all levels of organization of living matter. Int J Mol Sci 7: 98-110. Gleiser PM, Spoormaker VI (2010) Modelling hierarchical structure in functional brain networks. Philos Trans Royal Soc A, 368: 5633-5644. § Goldammer E. von, Paul, J, Newbury, J (2003) Heterarchy -- Hierarchy. Vordenker. *Goldstein JA (2011) Introduction to Conger’s ‘The doctrine of levels’. Emergence, Complexity and Organization: E:CO Annual Volume 11: 453-466. Emergent Publications, Litchfield Park, AZ. *Goldstein JA (2011) Chaos and complexity, branches and trees, and the advantages of vague concepts. Emergence, Complexity and Organization: E:CO Annual Volume 11: 583-590. Emergent Publications, Litchfield Park, AZ: § Gorbach NS, Schütte C, Melzer C, Goldau M, Sujazow O, Jitsev J, Douglas T and Tittgemeyer M (2011) Hierarchical information-based clustering for connectivity-based cortex parcellation. Front. Neuroinform. 5:18. doi: 10.3389/fninf.2011.00018 § *Gordon, R (1999) The Hierarchical Genome and Differentiation Waves: Novel Unification of Development, Genetics and Evolution. World Scientific and Imperial College Press, Singapore and London. § *Gordon R (2012) Walking the tightrope: the dilemmas of hierarchical instabilities in Turing’s morphogenesis. In Cooper SB, Hodges A (eds) The Once and Future Turing: Computing the World. Cambridge University Press. Gould SJ (2002) The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Grmela M (2004) Geometry of mesoscopic dynamics and thermodynamics. J Non- Newtonian Fluid Mech 120: 137-147. Grmela M (2010) Multiscale equilibrium and nonequilibrium thermodynamics in chemical engineering. Adv Chem Engin 39: 76-129. § Grmela M, Grazzini G, Lucia U, Yahia l (2013) Multiscale mesoscopic entropy of driven macroscopic systems. Entropy 2013 15: 5053-5064. Grobstein C (1973) Hierarchical order and neogenesis. In Pattee HH (ed) Hierarchy Theory: The Challenge of Complex Systems. Braziller, New York. §*Gröschel AH, Walther A, Löbling TI, Schacher FH, Schmalz H, Müller AHE (2013) Guided hierarchical co-assembly of soft patchy nanoparticles. Nature 503: 247-251, Guidolin D, Albertin, G, Guescini M, Fuxe K, Agnati LF (2011) Central nervous system and computation. Quart Rev Biol 86: 265-285. § Gunji Y-P, Kamiura M (2004) Observational heterarchy enhancing active coupling. Physica D 198: 74-105. Hawlena D. Schmitz OJ (2010) Physiological stress as a fundamental mechanism linking predation to ecosystem functioning. Amer Naturalist 176: 537-556. Haken H (1988) Information and Self-organization. Springer, Berlin. § Hall, WP (2011) Physical basis for the emergence of autopoiesis, cognitions and knowledge. Kororoit Institute, Working Paper No. 2. http://kororoit.org § *Hartmann N (1952) New Ways of Ontology. Greenwood Press. § Hemelrijk CK, Hildenbrandt H (2012) Schools of fish and flocks of birds: their shape and internal structure by self-organization. Interface Focus doi:10.1098/rsfs.2012.0025 *Henriques G (2003) The tree of knowledge system and the theoretical unification of psychology. Rev Gen Psychol 7: 150-182. § *Hirabayashi T, Takeuchi D, Tamura K, Myashita Y (2013) Microcircuits for hierarchical elaboration of object coding across primate temporal areas. Science 341: 191- 195. § Hirata H, Ulanowicz RE (1985) Information theoretical analysis of the aggregation and hierarchical structure of ecological networks. J Theor Biol 116: 321-341. *Hodgson GM (2006) What are institutions? J Econ Issues 40: 1-25. *Hoffkirchner W (2010) Twenty Questions About a Unified Theory of Information. Emergent Publications, Litchfield Park,AZ (Chapters 7 and 12) Hoffmeyer J (2008) Biosemiotics: An Examination Into the Signs of Life and the Life of Signs. University of Scranton Press, London Hölldobler B, Wilson EO (2009) The Superorganism: The Beauty, Elegance, and Strangeness of Insect Societies. W.W. Norton, New York Holling CS (2001) Understanding the complexity of economic, ecological and social systems. Ecosystems 4: 390-405. Holling CS, Gunderson LH, Peterson GD (2002) Sustainability and panarchies. In: Gunderson LH, Holling CS (eds) Panarchy: Understanding Transformations in Human and Natural Systems. Island Press, Washington DC *Hopwood JO (1952) The Organic Foundation of Society and Enterprise. Exposition Press, New York Hulswit, M (2006) How causal is downward causation? J Gen Philos Sci 36: 261-287. Iordache O (2011) Modeling Multi-Level Systems. Springer, Berlin. Jamshidi N, Palsson BO (2008) Top-down analysis of temporal hierarchy in biochemical reaction networks. PLoS Comput Biol 4:e1000177.doi:10- 1371/journal.pcbi.1000177/ *Jagers op Akkerhuis GAJM (2008) Analyzing hierarchy in the organization of biological and physical systems. Biol Rev 83: 1-12. §* Jagers op Akkerhuis GAJM (2014) General laws and centripetal science. European Rev 22, Suppl S1: S113-S144. *Jolley C, Douglas T (2012) Topological biosignatures: large-scale structure of chemical networks from biology and astrochemistry. Astrobiology 12, DOI: 10.1089/ast.2011.0674 *Jolley JL (1973) The Fabric of Knowledge: A Study of the Relations Between Ideas. Barnes and Noble, New York Julesz J (1991) Early vision and focal attention. Rev Mod Physics 63: 735-772. § Kaczmarek J (2013) On a structure of mathematical theory which reflects multiscale aspects and integrity of biological systems, I. Far East J Appl Math 76: 79-117. § Kelso S (1995). Dynamic Patterns. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. §* Kember G, Armour JA, Zamir M (2013) Neural control hierarchy of the heart has no evolved to deal with myocardial ischemia. Physiol Genomics 45: 638-644. *Kercel SW (2007) Entailment of ambiguity. Chem Biodiversity 4: 2369-2385. § Kicheva A, Cohen M, Briscoe J (2012) Developmental pattern formation: insights from physics and biology. Science 338: 210-212. Kiebel SJ, Daunizeau J, Friston K (2008) A hierarchy of time-scales and the brain. PLoS Comput Biology 4: e1000209. *Kim J (1993) Supervenience and Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. *Klapwijk J (2009) Purpose in the Living World: Creation and Emergent Evolution. Cambridge University Press, New York. § Kleidon A. (2010): Non-equilibrium Thermodynamics, Maximum Entropy Production and Earth-system evolution, Phil Trans Royal Soc A, 368: 181-196. Koestler A (1967) The Ghost in the Machine. Macmillan, New York Kolasa J (2005) Complexity, system integration, and susceptibility to change: biodiversity connection. Ecol Complexity 2: 431-442. Kolasa J, Pickett STA (1989) Ecological systems and the concept of biological organization. Proc Nat Acad Sci US 86: 8837-8841. § Kolchinsky A, Rocha LM (2013) Prediction and modularity in dynamical systems. arXiv: 1106.3703v1 [nlin.AO] § Kolchinsky A, et al (2014) Multiscale integration and predictability in resting state brain activity. Neiroinform 8: 66 http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fninf.2014.00066 Koslicki K (2008) The Structure of Objects. Oxford University Press, New York § *Kravitz DJ, Saleem KS, Baker CI, Ungerleider LG, Mishkin M (2012) The ventral visual pathway: an expanded neural framework for the processing of object quality. Trends Cog Sci 17: 26-49. Kubik A (2003) Toward a formalization of emergence. Artif Life. 9: 41-66. § *Kull K (2000) An introduction to phytosemiotics: semiotic botany and vegetative systems. Sign Syst Stud 28: 326- 351. Kulish VV (2006) Hierarchical Methods: Hierarchy and Hierarchical Asymptotic Methods in Electrodynamics. Volume 1, Chapter 2: Hierarchy and Hierarchical Systems. Springer, New York. Kusumi A, Suzuki KGN Kasai RS, Ritchie K, Fujiwara TK (2011) Hierarchical mesoscale domain organization of the plasma membrane. Trends Biochem Sci doi:10.1016/j.tibs. 2011.08.001 § Lambiotte R. (2010) Multiscale modularity in complex networks. 2010/04/24, arXiv:1004.4268 *Lane D (2006) Hierarchy, complexity, society. In: Pumain D (ed) Hierarchy in Natural and Social Sciences. Springer, New York (Chapter 4) Lemke JL (2000) Opening up closure: semiotics across scales. In: Chandler JLR, Van de Vijver G (eds) Closure: Emergent Organizations and Their Dynamics. Ann NY,Acad Sci 901: 100-111. Lerner VS (2004) Introduction to information systems theory: concepts, formalism and application. International J Syst Sci 35: 405-424. Lerner, VS (2006) About the biophysical conditions initiating cooperative complexity. J Biol Syst 14: 315-322. Liow LH, Van Valen L, Stenseth NC (2011) Red Queen: from populations to taxa and communities. Trends Ecol Evol 26: 349-358. Liu G, Yang Z, Chen B, Zhang L (2011) Analysis of resource and emission impacts: an emergy-based multiple spatial scale framework for urban ecological and economic evaluation. Entropy 2011, 13: 720-743. §Liu YY, Slotine JJ, Barabasi AL (2012) Control centrality and hierarchical structure in complex networks. PLoS One 7(9): e44459. Lorente S, Bejan A (2010) Few large and many small: hierarchy in movement on Earth. Int J Design Ecodyn 5: 1-14. § Lorenz DM, Jeng A, Deem MW (2012) The emergence of modularity in biological systems. arXiv:1204.5999v1 [q-bio.PE] 26 Apr 2012 Losee RM (1997) A discipline independent definition of information. J Amer Soc Info Sci 49: 254-269. § *Louie AH, Poli R (2011) The spread of hierarchical cycles. Int J Gen Syst 40: 237-261. *Love AC (2012) Hierarchy, causation and explanation: ubiquity, locality and pluralism. Interface Focus (2012) 2: 115-125. *Luo J, Magee CL (2011) Detecting evolving patterns of self-organizing networks by flow hierarchy measurement. Complexity DOI 10.1002/cpx.20368 § Machta BB, Chachra R, Transtrum MK, Sethna JP (2013) Parameter space compression underlies emergent theories and predictive models. Science 342: 604-607 *Mahner M, Bunge M (1997) Foundations of Biophilosophy. Springer, New York (pp. 177-180.) Mandelbrot B (1983) The Fractal Geometry of Nature. Freeman, San Francisco. Mann RP, Prna A, Strömbom D, Garnett, R, Herbert-Read JE, Sumpter DT, Ward AJW (2012). Multi-scale inference of interaction rules in animal groups using Bayesian model selection. PLoS Computational Biology 8(1): e1002308. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002308 § Marraffa M, Paternoster A (2013) Functions, levels, and mechanisms: explanation in cognitive science and its problems. ap,sagepub.com, 2013.1.29 Marshall A (2002) The Unity of Nature: Wholeness and Disintegration in Ecology and Science. Imperial College Press, London. § Marston SA, Jones III JP, Woodward k (2005) Human geography without scale. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, N.S. 30: 416-432. Martin RM (1992) Logical Semiotics and . John Benjamins, Amsterdam § Matsuno K, Salthe SN (2012) Chemical affinity as material agency for naturalizing contextual meaning. Information 2012, 3: 21-35. Maurer BA (1999) Untangling Ecological Complexity: The Macroscopic Perspective. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. McCrone J (2011) Dichotomistic. http://www.dichotomistic.com.index.html. § McCulloch W (1945) A heterarchy of values determined by the topology of nervous nets. Bull Math Biol 7: 89-93. § McLaughlin B, Bennett K. (2011). Supervenience. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/supervenience/ McShea DW (2001) The hierarchical structure of organisms: a scale and documentation of a trend in the maximum. Paleobiology 27: 405-423. § McShea, DW (2011) Upper-directed systems: a new approach to teleology in biology. Biol Philos DOI 10.1007/s10539-012-9326-2 Mesarovic M, Macko D, Takahara Y (1970) Theory of Hierarchical, Multilevel, Systems. Academic Press, New York. § Mesarovic M, Sreenath N, Keene J (2004) Search for organizing principles: understanding in systems biology. Syst Biol 1: 19-27. § Mesarovic M, Sreenath N (2005) Beyond the Flat Earth perspective in systems biology. Biol Theor 1: 33-34. Meunier D, Lambiotte R, Fornito A, Ersche KD, Bullmore ET (2010) Hierarchical modularity in human brain functional networks. http://arxiv.org/ftp/arxiv:1004.3153 Meyer LB (1998) A universe of universals. J Musicol 16: 3-25. Miller JG (1978) Living Systems. McGraw Hill, New York *Mills Fleming J, Jonsen LD, Myers RA, Field CA (2010) Hierarchical state-space estimation of leatherback turtle navigation ability. PLoS ONE 5 (12):e14245. doi:10.1371/ journal.pone.0014245 Minati G (2009) Steps of the meta-structures project to model general processes of emergence. http://arxiv.org/ftp/arxiv/papers/0910/0910.1753.pdf § Mitchell S (2012). Emergence: logical, functional and dynamical. Synthese 185: 171-186. Morrison P, Morrison P (1982) Powers of Ten. Scientific American Books, New York. § Mossio M, Bich L, Moreno A (2013) Emergence, closure and inter-level causation in biological systems. Erkenntnis DOI 10.1007/s10670-013-9507-7 § Murphey N, Ellis GFR, O’Connor T (eds) (2009) Downward Causation and the Neurobiology of Free Will. Understanding Complex Systems, 2009, ISBN 978-3-642-03204-2; DOI:10.1007/978-3-642-03205-9 §* Musel B, et al (2014) Coarse-to-fine categorization of visual scenes in scene-selective cortex. J Cog Neurosci doi:10.1162/jocn_a_00643 Nagy M, Akos Z, Biro D, Vicsek T (2010) Hierarchical group dynamics in pigeon flocks. Nature 464: 890-893. § Nardecchia I, Spinelli L Preto J, Gori M, Floriani E, Jaeger S, Ferrier P, Pettini M (2014) Experimental detection of long-distance interaction between biomolecules through their diffusive behavior: numerical study. arXiv: 1403.2415v1 [physics.bio-ph] *Needham J (1937/1943) Integrative levels: a revaluation of the idea of progress. In: Needham J (ed) Time: The Refreshing River. George Allen & Unwin, London. Neri P (2011) Coarse to fine dynamics of monocular and binocular processing in human pattern vision. Proc Nat Acad Sci 13 June 2011; doi:10.1073/pnas.1101246108 § Neuman Y, Marwan N, Cohen Y (2014) Change in the embedding dimension as an indication of an approaching transition. PLOS ONE 9/issue 6/e101014 § *Newman, SA (2003) Hierarchy. In: Hall BK, Olson WM (eds) Keywords and Concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Harvard, Cambridge, MA. Newman SA, Christley S, Glim T, Henschel HE, Kazmierczak B, Zhang Y-T, Zhu J, Alber M (2010) Multiscale models for vertebrate limb development. Curr Topics Devel Biol 81: 311-340. Nielsen SN (2009) Thermodynamic constraints of life as downward causation in ecosystems. Cybernet Hum Know 16: 27-49. Nicolis JS (1986) Dynamics of Hierarchical Systems: An Evolutionary Approach. Springer, Berlin Noble D (2012) A theory of biological relativity: no privileged level of causation. Interface Focus (2012) 2: 55-64. § Norris V, Cabin A, Zemerline A (2005) Hypercomplexity. Acta Biotheoretica 53: 313-330. § Norris V, den Blaauwen T, Doi RH, Harshey RM, Janniere L, Jiminez-Sanchez A, Jin DJ, Levin PA, Mileykovskaya E, Minsky A, Misecic G, Ripoll, Saier M Jr., Skarstad K, Thellier M (2007) Toward a hyperstructure taxonomy. Ann Rev Microbiol 61: 309-329. Norton B (2005) Sustainability: A Philosophy of Adaptive Ecosystem Management. University of Chicago Press, Chicago § Nottale L (2011) Scale Relativity and Fractal Space-time: A New Approach to Unifying Relativity and Quantim Mechanics. World Scientific, Singapore § Nottale L. (2014) Macroscopic quantum-type potentials in theoretical systems biology. Cell 2014 1: 1-34. O’Connor T (1994) Emergent properties. Amer Philos Quart 31: 91-104. Odum HT, Odum EC (2000) Modeling For All Scales: An Introduction to System Simulation. Academic Press, New York Okasha S (2012) Emergence, hierarchy and top-down causation in evolutionary biology. Interface Focus (2012) 2: 49-54. Oldershaw R (2008) Discrete scale relativity. http://www.arxiv.org. § O’Neill RV, DeAngelis DL, Waide JB, Allen TFH (1986) A Hierarchical Concept of Ecosystems. Princeton University Press, Princeton. § *Oppenheim P, Putnam H (1958) as a working hypothesis. In: Feigel H, Scriven M, Maxwell G (eds) Condpts, Theories and the mind-body problem. Minnesota Stud Phil Sci II: 3-36. § Overton, WS (1981) On constructing a hierarchical model in the FLEX paradigm, illustrated by structural aspects of a hydrological model. Int J Gen Syst 6: 191-216. Paine RW, Tani J (2005) How hierarchical control self-organizes in artificial adaptive systems. Adapt Behav 13: 211-225. § Palus M (2014) Cross-scale interactions and information transfer/ Entropy 2014 16: 5263-5289. §* Parthemore J (2014) Conceptual change and development in multiple time scales: from incremental evolution to origins. Sign Sys Stud 42: 193-218. Pattee HH (1973) The physical basis and origin of hierarchical control. In: Pattee HH (ed) Hierarchy Theory: The Challenge of Complex Systems. Braziller, New York. §Pattee, HH (2000) Causation, control, and the evolution of complexity. In: Anderson PB, Emmeche C, Finneman NO, Christiansen PV (eds) Downward Causation: Minds, Bodies, Matter. Aarhus University Press: Aarhus. § *Pattee, HH (2013) Epistemic, evolutionary, and physical conditions for biological information. Biosemiotics 6: 9-31. § Paz Gutierrez M, Lee LP (2013) Multiscale design and integration of sustainable building functions. Science 341: 247-248. § Peixoto TP (2014) Hierarchical block structures and high-resolution model selection in large networks. Phys Rev X 4, 011047 § Pekowska A, Klaus B, Klein FA, et al (2014) Neural lineage induction reveals multi-scale dynamics of 3D chromatin organization. bioRxiv beta doi: 10.110/004168 Perdikis, D., R. Huys and V. Jirsa, 2011. Complex processes from dynamical architectures with time-scale hierarchy, PLoS one 6(2): e16589.doi:10.1371/ § Perret N (2012) A symmetrical approach to causality in biology. Philosophia Scientiae 16: 177-195. Perrow C (1984) Normal Accidents: Living With High-Risk Technologies. Basic Books, New York § *Peter IS, Davidson EH (2011) Evolution of gene regulatory networks that control embryonic development of the body plan. Cell 144: 970-985. Petterson M (1996) Complexity and Evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK § Petroff A, Libchaber A (2014) Hydrodynamics and collective behavior of the tethered bacterium. Proc US Nat Acad Sci 111 E537-E545 *Peyrin C, Michel CM, Scwartz S, Thut G, Seghier M, Landis T, Marendez C, Vuilleumier P (2010) The neural substrates and timing of top-down processes during coarse-to-fine categorization of visual scenes: a combined fMRI and ERP study. J Cognit Neurosci 22: 2768-2780. Pfenniger D (2006) Virial statistical description of non-extensive hierarchical systems. arXiv:cond-mat/0605665v1 [cond-mat.stat-mech] *Phillips JD (2012) Synchronization and scale in geomorphic systems. Geomorphology 137: 150-158. § Pievani T (2014) Individuals and groups in evolution: Darwinian pluralism and the multilevel selection debate. J Biosci 39: 319-325. § Pines D (2014) Emergence: a unifying theme for 21st Century science. https://medium.com/ sfi-30-foundations-frontiers/emergence-a-unifying-theme-for-21st-century- science-4324ac0f951e Polanyi M (1968) Life's irreducible structure. Science 160: 1308-1312. §* Poli, R. 2006. Levels of reality and the psychological stratum. Revue Internat Philos, 236:163–180. *Poli R (2006) The theory of levels of reality and the difference between simple and tangled hierarchies. In: Minati G, Pessa E, and Abrams M (eds) Systemics of Emergence: Research and Development. Springer, New York. § *Potochnik, A, McGill B (2012) The limitations of hierarchical organization. Phil Sci 79: 120-140. Poznanski, R.R. 2011. Dynamic continuity across scale: the missing ingredient in multi- scale modeling. http://romanpoznanski.blogspot.com Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227: 520-521. § Pulendran S, Artis D (2012) New paradigms in Type 2 immunity. Science 337: 431-435. *Pumain D (ed) (2006) Hierarchy in Natural and Social Sciences. Springer, New York Queiroz J, El-Hani CH (2001) Towards a multi-level approach to the emergence of meaning process in living systems. Acta Biotheoretica 54: 179-206. Rabosky DL, McCune AR (2010) Reinventing species selection with molecular phylogenies. Trends Ecol Evol 25: 68-74/ Ratti S., Sobolevsky S, Calabrese F, Andris C, Reades, J, Martino M, Claxton R, Strogatz SH (2010) Redrawing the map of Great Britain from a network of human interactions. PLoS 5: e14248. Ratze C, Gillet F, Müller J-P, Stoffel K (2007) Simulation modelling of ecological hierarchies in constructual dynamical systems. Ecol Complexity 4: 13-25. § Reggio G (1982) Koyaanisquatsi. Pacific Arts (film) § Renormalization. Wikipedia. *Rieppel O (2010) The series, the network, and the tree: changing metaphors of order in nature. Biol Philos 25: 475- 496. § Robledo AA (2012) A dynamical model for hierarchy and modular organization: the trajectories en route to the attractor at the transition to chaos. J Phys Conf Ser 2012, 394, 012007 § Robledo AA (2013) Generalized statistical mechanics at the onset of chaos. Entropy 2013 15: 5178-5222. Robinson WS (2005) Zooming in on downward causation. Biol Philos 20: 117-136. § Roehner, B (1982_ Order transmission efficiency in large hierarchical organizations. Int J Syst Sci 13: 531-346. § Rodriguez-Caso C, Corominas-Murta B, Sol R ( ) Dynamical hierarchy and modularity in gene regulatory networks. DOI: SFI-WP 08-12-049, SFI Working Papers §* Roensch K, Tazaki A, Chara O, Tanaka EM (2013) Progressive specification rather than intercalation of segments during limb regeneration. Science 342: 1375-1379. *Rosen R. (2000) Essays on Life Itself. Columbia University Press, New York. § Rowe JS (1961) The level-of-integration concept and ecology. Ecology 42: 420-427. Rubinov M, Spoms O, Thivierge JP, Breakspear M (2011) Neurobiologically realistic determinants of self-organized criticality in networks of spiking neurons. PLoS Comput Biol, June 2, 2011. Rubinstein R, Bos WJT (2010) On the unsteady behavior of turbulence models. arXiv: 1009.0127v1 Saaty TL (1990) Multicriteria Decision Making: The Analytical Hierarchy Process. McGraw- Hill, New York. *Sabelli HC (2005) Bios: A Study of Creation. World Scientific, Hong Kong *Sabelli HC, Carlson-Sabelli L (1989) Biological priority and psychological supremacy: a new integrative program derived from process theory. Am J Psychiat 146: 1541-1551. Sales-Pardo M, Moreira A, Nunes-Amaral LA (2007) Extracting the hierarchical organization of complex systems. Proc Nat Acad Sci US 104: 15224-15229. Salthe SN (1985,a) Evolving Hierarchical Systems: Their Structure and Representation. Columbia University Press, New York (*Figure 16) Salthe SN (1985,b) From Cartesian dualism thru dual aspect complementarities to hierarchical resolution. Proc Soc Gen Syst Res 1985, Volume I:118- 120. *Salthe SN (1988) Notes toward a formal history of the levels concept. In: Greenberg G and Tobach (eds) Evolution of Social Behavior and Integrative Levels. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ. *Salthe SN (1991) Two forms of hierarchy theory in Western discourses. Int J Gen Syst 18: 251- 264. *Salthe SN (1993) Development and Evolution: Complexity and Change in Biology. MIT, Cambridge, MA. *Salthe SN (2002) Summary of the principles of hierarchy theory. Gen Syst Bull 31: 13-17. Salthe SN (2004) The spontaneous origin of new levels in dynamical hierarchies. Entropy 2004, 6 [3], 327 -343. http://www.mdpi.net/entropy/list04.htm *Salthe SN (2006) Two frameworks for complexity generation in biological systems. In: Gershenson C, Lenaerts T (eds) Evolution of Complexity. ALifeX Proceedings. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN. http://ecco.vub.be/EDO/Salthe.pdf *Salthe SN (2008) A hierarchical framework for levels of reality: understanding through representation. Axiomathes 19: 87-99. § *Salthe SN (2010) Review of E.T. Wimberley, Nested Ecology. Environ Conserv 36: 353. § Samu D, Seth AK, Nowotny T (2014) Influence of wiring cost in the large scale architecture of human cortical connectivity. PLOS Comput Biol DOI: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003557 § Sanchez T, Chen TN, DeCamo SJ, Heymann M Dogic z (2012) Spontaneous motion in hierarchically assembled active matter. Nature 491: 431-434. § Santos GS, Gireesh Ed, Plenz D, Nakahara H (2010) Hierarchical interaction structure of neural activities in cortical slice. J. Neurosci 30: 8720-8733. *Sato N (2012) Scientific ´Elan Vital: entropy deficit or inhomogeneity as a unified concept of driving forces of life in hierarchical biosphere driven by photosynthesis. Entropy 2012, 14: 233-251. Scheiner SM (2010) Toward a conceptual framework for biology. Quart Rev Biol 85: 293-318. § Schramski et al (2014) Metabolic theory predicts whole-ecosystem properties. PNAS www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1423502112 § Seo M et al (2015) Hierarchically porous polymers from hyper-cross-linked polymer precursors. J Amer Chem Soc 2015; 150107150852009 DOI: 10.1021/ja511581w Sejnowsky T (2006) The computational self. Ann New York Acad Sci 1001: 262-271. Sexton T, Yaffee E, Kenigsberg E, Bantignies F et al (2012) Three dimensional folding and functional organization principles of the Drosophila genome. Cell, doi: 10.1016/j.cell. 2012.01.010 Shah M (2010) Visual Crowd Surveillance is Like Hydrodynamics. http://videolectures.net/ acmmm2010_shah_vcs/ Sherrington D (2010) Physics and complexity. Phil Trans Roy Soc, A. 368:1175-1189. Shklarsh AG, Schneiderman E, Ben-Jacob E (2011) Smart swarms of bacteria-inspired agents with performance adaptable interactions. PLoS Comput Biol 7(9): e1002177. doi:10.1371/ journal.pcbi.1003177 § *Shpitzer I, Pearl J (2008) Complete identification methods for the causal hierarchy. J Machine Learn Res 9: 1941-1979. Sih GC (2010) Mechanics of energy and mass interaction for dissipative systems. Phys Mesomechanics 13: 233-244. Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity. Proc Amer Philos Soc 106: 467-482. *Simpson GG (1961) Principles of Animal Taxonomy. Columbia University Press, New York. *Sommers F (1963) Types and ontology. Philos Rev 72: 327-363. Soodak H, Iberall A (1978) Homeokinetics: a physical science for complex systems. Science 201: 579-582. Stansinopoulos P, Smith MH, et al. (2009) Whole system design: An integrated approach to sustainable engineering. Earthscan, London UK Stanley SM (1979) Macroevolution: Pattern and Process. Freeman, San Francisco. Steinke GK, Galán RF (2011) Brain rhythms reveal a hierarchical network organization. PLoS Comput Biol 7(10) doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002207 Stewart JE (1997) Evolutionary transitions and artificial life. Artif Life 3: 101-120. § Stewart JE (2014) The direction of evolution: the rise of cooperative organization. BioSystems http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2014.05.006 §* Sun G, Krasnitz A (2014) Significantly distinct branches of hierarchical trees: a framework for statistical analysis and applications to biological data. bioRxiv 10.1101/002188 §* Tecumseh Smith W, Martins MD (2014) Hierarchical processing in music, language, and action: Lashley revisited. Ann NY Acad Sci ISSN 0077-8923 *Teilhard de Chardin P (1959) The Phenomenon of Man. Harper and Row, New York. Thiese ND (2009) Beyond cell doctrine: complexity theory informs alternate models of the body for cross-cultural dialogue. Ann NY Acad Sci 1172: 263-269. § Theraulaz G, Bonabeau E (1999) A brief history of stigmergy. Artif Life 5:97-116. § t’Hooft G, Vandoren S (2014) Time in Powers of Ten: Natural Phenomena and Their Timescales. World Scientific, Singapore. § Tong C (2014) Ecology without scale: unthinking the World Zoom. Animation July 2014 9: 196-211, doi:10.1177/1746847714527199 § Troncale LR (1982) Some key, unanswered questions about hierarchies. In: Troncale, LR (ed.) A General Survey of Systems Methodology: Vol. I. Conceptual and Mathematical Tools. Intersystems, Seaside, Ca., pp. 77-81. § Troncale LR (1984) A hybrid systems method: tests for hierarchy and links between isomorphs” in Progress In: Trappl R (ed.) Cybernetics and Systems Research 2 North-Holland, New York, pp. 39-46. *Turchin V (1995) A dialog on metasystem transition. World Futures 45: 5-57. *Tyrell T (1993) The use of hierarchies for action selection. Adapt Behav 1: 387-420. § Uhrig L, Dehaene S, Jarraya B (2014) A hierarchy of responses to auditory regularities in the macaque brain. J Neurosci 34: 1127-1132. Ulanowicz RE (2000) Ontic closure and the hierarchy of scale. Ann New York Acad Sci 901:266-271. Uyeda JC, Hansen TF, Arnold SJ, Pienaar J (2011) The million-year wait for macroevolutionary bursts. Proc Nat Acad Sci US; doi:10.1073/pnas.1014503108. Valentine JW, May CL (1996) Hierarchies in biology and paleontology. Paleobiology 22: 23-33. § Valles-Catala T, Massuccio FA, Guimera R, Sales-Pardo M (2014) Multilayer stochastic block models reveal the multilayer structure of complex networks. arXiv:1411.1098v1 [physics.soc-ph] § *van Dijk S, Polani D, Nehaniv CL (2011) Hierarchical behaviors: getting the most bang for your bit. Lecture Notes in Compl Sci 5778: 342-349. Varzi AC (2009) Mereology. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. *Vernadsky VI (1945) The biosphere and the noösphere. Amer Scientist 33: 1-12. § Vicsek T, Zafeiris A (2012) Collective motion. Phys Reports 517- 71-140. §Villani M, Filisetti A, Benedettini S, Roli A, Lane DA, Serrae R (2013) The detection of intermediate-level emergent structures and patterns. ECAL General Track http://dx.doi.org/ 10.7551/978-0-262-31709-2-ch054 *Volk T (2003) Gaia’s Body: Toward a Physiology of Earth. MIT, Cambridge, MA. § Voorhees, BH (1983) Axiomatic theory of hierarchical systems. Behavioral Science 28: 24-38. Voronin AN (2008) Multicriteria evaluation and optimization of hierarchical systems. Int J Inform Theories Applic 15: 108- 114. § Vrobel S (2011) Fractal Time: Why a Watched Kettle Never Boils. World Scientific: Singapore. § Vrobel S (2013) Measuring the temporal extension of the now. Progr Biophys, Mol Biol doi.org/10.1016/j.pbiomolbio.2013.03.009 § Walker SI (2014) Top-down causation and the rise of information in the emergence of life. Information 2014, 5: 424-430. § Walker SI, Cisneros, L, Davies, PCW (2012) Evolutionary transitions and top-down causation. arXiv:1207.4808v1 [nlin.AO] 19 Jul 2012 § Walker SI, Davies PCW (2012) The algorithmic origins of life. J Roy Soc Interface 10: 20120869. http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2012.0869 § Walker SI, Callahan BJ, Gaurav A, Barry JD, Bhattacherya T, Grigoryev S, Pellgrini M, Rippe K, Rosenburg SM (2013) Evolutionary dynamics and information hierarchies in biological systems. Annals NY Acad Sci xxx: 1-17. § Watson, RA (2006) Compositional Evolution: The Impact of Sex, Symbiosis, and Modularity on the Gradualist Framework of Evolution. MIT , Cambridge, MA Watson RA, Mills R, Buckley CL (2011) Transformations in the scale of behavior and the global optimization of constraints in adaptive networks. Adapt Behav 19: 227-249. Weiss PA (1971) The basic concept of hierarchic systems. In: Weiss PA (ed) Hierarchically Organized Systems in Theory and Practice. Hafner, New York § Wensink HH, Dunkel J, Heidenreich S, Drescher K, Goldstein RE, Löwen H, Yeomans JM (2012) Meso-scale turbulence in living fluids. Proc Nat Acad Sci US http://www.pnas.org/ content/early/2012/08/16/1202032109.abstract § Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the Cognitive World. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Wheeler WM (1911) The ant colony as an organism. J Morphol 22: 669-807. Whyte LL, Wilson AG, Wilson D (eds) (1969) Hierarchical Structures. Elsevier, New York *Wikipedia, The Free Encyclopedia. Supervenience. Wikipedia, The Free Encyclopedia. Price Equation. § Wilby JM (2007) Hierarchy Theory and Epidemiology: A Narrative Critique. Ph.D. Thesis University of Leeds. *Wilson, D (1969) Forms of hierarchy. In: Whyte LL, Wilson AG, Wilson D (eds) Hierarchical Structures Elsevier, New York Wilson DS, Dugatkin LA (1997) Group selection and assortative interactions. Amer Natural 149: 336-351. Wilson DS, Sober ER (1989) Reviving the superorganism. J Theoret Biol 136: 337-356. Wilson DS, Wilson EO (2007) Rethinking the theoretical foundation of sociobiology. Quart Rev Biol 82:327-348. § Wimberley, ET (2009) Nested Ecology: The Place of Humans in the Ecological Hierarchy. Johns Hopkins, Baltimore § Wimsatt, ET (1976) Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem. In: Globus G, Savodnik I, Cohen IS (eds) PSI (1972) Boston Stud Philos Sci 2: 67-86. Wimsatt WC (1994) The ontology of complex systems levels, perspectives, causal thickets. Can J Philos, Suppl 20: 201-274. Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering Philosophy For Limited Beings: Piecewise Approximations To Reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA § Winther RG, Wade MJ, Dimond CC (2013) Pluralism in evolutionary controversies: styles and averaging strategies in hierarchical selection theories. Biol Philos 28 DOI 10.1007/ s10539-013-9378-y Woodger JH (1929) Biological Principles: A Critical Study. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, London. § Wu S-D, Wu P-H, Wu C-W, Ding J-J, Wang C-C (2012) Bearing fault diagnosis based on multiscale permutation entropy and support vector machine. Entropy 2012 14: 1343=1356. Wu J, Loucks OL (1995) From balance of nature to hierarchical patch dynamics: a paradigm shift in ecology. Quart Rev Biol 70: 439-466. *Yildiz IB, Kiebel SJ (2011) A hierarchical neuronal model for generation and online recognition of birdsongs. PLoS Computational Biology 7 (12) e1002303. www.ploscompbiolorg *Young G (2011) Development and Causality: Neo-Piagetian Perspectives. New York: Springer. Zhirmunsky AV, Kuzmin VI (1988) Critical Levels in the Development of Natural Systems. Springer, New York Zhang Z, Zhang Y-W, Gao H (2010) On optimal hierarchy of load-bearing biological materials. Proc Royal Soc, B doi:10.1098/rspb.2010.1093 § Zhou H, et al (2014) Four levels of organization, including noncovalent chainmail, brace the mature tumor herpes virus capsid against pressurization. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.str. 2014.05.019 *Zhu L, Lin C, Huang H, Chen Y, Yuille A (2008) Proc Europ Conf Comput Vision. ECCV, October, 2008. §* Zlatev J (2009) The semiotic hierarchy: life, consciousness, signs and language. Cognitive Semiotics 4: 169-200.

References to the text

Ahl V, Allen TFH (1996) Hierarchy Theory: A Vision, Vocabulary, and Epistemology. Columbia University Press, New York Eldredge N (1985) Unfinished Synthesis: Biological Hierarchies and Modern Evolutionary Thought. Oxford University Press, New York Gould SJ (2002) The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227: 520-521. Rieppel O (2010) The series, the network, and the tree: changing metaphors of order in nature. Biol Philos 25: 475- 496. Salthe SN (1985) Evolving Hierarchical Systems: Their Structure and Representation. Columbia University Press, New York Salthe SN (1993) Development and Evolution: Complexity and Change in Biology. MIT, Cambridge, MA. Salthe SN (2006) Two frameworks for complexity generation in biological systems. In: Gershenson C, Lenaerts T (eds) Evolution of Complexity. ALifeX Proceedings. Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN. http://ecco.vub.be/EDO/Salthe.pdf Simpson GG (1961) Principles of Animal Taxonomy. Columbia University Press, New York. Stanley SM (1979) Macroevolution: Pattern and Process. Freeman, San Francisco. Wilson DS, Dugatkin LA (1997) Group selection and assortative interactions. Amer Natural 149 : 336-351.