A Conversation With... Patricia Churchland

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Conversation With... Patricia Churchland A Conversatonwit Patrnica Churchiand NeilA. Campbell Nervoussystems distinguish tions about the brain and that I needed to know the iiSf,' .9X#. animals from all other king- nuts and bolts of the brain, what neurons were and jx i i X doms of life. And certain how they talked to each other. The more neuro- propertiesof thehuman brain science I knew, the more it seemed to me that we distinguishour speciesfrom really had the key to understanding the nature of the all other animals. The human mind via neuroscience. This is not to say that we had Downloaded from http://online.ucpress.edu/abt/article-pdf/58/3/154/47484/4450104.pdf by guest on 29 September 2021 brain is, after all, the only a key that you could use independently of psychol- ii *1 11Pknown collection of matter ogy-behavioral descriptions-but that it was a cru- thattries to understanditself. cial element. l!!11 To most biologists,the brain I was always unconvinced by arguments that in and the mindare one and the addition to the brain, there is a nonphysical soul; and same; understandhow the it's the soul that makes decisions, the soul that feels brainis and how it and thinks. If you're unconvinced by that, then the Patricia Churchland organized works,and we'll understand nature of the brain and its organization have to be such mindfulfunctions as abstractthought and feelings. relevant in understanding these fundamental ques- Somephilosophers are less comfortablewith this mechanis- tions that philosophers are interested in. tic view of the mind, finding Descartes'concept of a mind-bodyduality more attractive. Patricia Churchland has Campbell: How did you then begin to learn neuro- takencenter stage in this debateabout the humanmind. science? Dr. Churchlandis a professorof philosophyat the Churchland:Well, I knew some basic biology, basic Universityof California,San Diego, and an adjunctpro- cell physiology and biochemistry, but I realized that I fessorat the SalkInstitute. Boundaries between the human- needed to know brain anatomy. By this time, I was a ities and the sciences dissolve as ProfessorChurchland faculty member at the University of Manitoba. So I attemptsto synthesizea philosophyof the mind basedon phoned the head of the anatomy department at the whatneuroscience is learningabout the brain.Her seminal University of ManitobaMedical School and explained bookin this new synthesisis Neurophilosophy: Toward my interests. He said, "Why don't you just come and a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain(MIT Press, 1986). take the basic neuroscience course with the medical Biologyis a multidisciplinaryadventure that integrates the students and do as much or as little as you want." I naturalsciences and connectsto the humanitiesand social did all the anatomy and the basic physiology, but that sciences.Neurophilosopher Patricia Churchland is helping wasn't enough. Then I got associated with a lab and makethose connections. learned the basic techniques, such as recording from single cells. But once you have a leg up, you start Campbell: What led you, as a philosopher, to neu- learning more on your own. roscience? Churchland:The questions I was interested in as a Campbell: So you started to bridge that neuroscience philosophy graduate student were really questions training to philosophy of the mind? about the human mind, about the nature of learning Churchland:At a certain point, it seemed to me that and perception, about what it is for something to be if the brain is the thing that does the thinking, the conscious, about the difference between the actions feeling, and the decision making, then we really have we call voluntary and actions we call involuntary- to pay attention to basic brain anatomy and physiol- the free-will problem. As time went on, it became ogy in order to answer some of the philosophical increasingly clear to me that these were really ques- questions. And some of the answers are going to be counterintuitive. Those ideas that seem very likely to us via introspection might well turn out to be false, NellA. Campbell is a MslslngScholar in the Departmentof Plant Sciences,at the Universityof California,Rlverside, CA 92521. just as in any other science. One theme in my book, Neurophilosophy,is that if you stick with your basic 154 THEAMERICAN BIOLOGY TEACHER, VOLUME 58, NO. 3, MARCH1996 intuitions about the way things must work in the understand. With the advent of artificialneural nets mind and don't take the route through neuroscience, that we can design on computers, we are beginning you are going to miss all the depth and the richness to get at least a conceptual frameworkfor making that that underlies the reality. This is partly an argument bridge between the individual neurons on the one for materialism-that there is only the brain-and hand and the systems on the other. We have a long partly an attempt to convince psychologists, who are way to go. So far, we can find really interesting also materialists, that it isn't enough to look just at propertiesof artificialneural nets when they're small: behavior. They learn from examples, and they find approxi- mately good answers when there is no precise an- swer to be found. They can do things fast. They can Campbell: Was it uncomfortable for you, coming have a kind of short-term memory. What we don't from a philosophy background, to challenge the understand is how you can get really interesting tradition of mind-body duality? effects out of big nets, or whether the nervous system Churchland:Not for me personally, because I don't takes lots of little nets and treats them as units of a big think that distinction of mind and body, or brain, net. ever seemed terribly plausible. I was always part of Take the case of categorization,for example. Some that traditionthat says that complexity is not predict- Downloaded from http://online.ucpress.edu/abt/article-pdf/58/3/154/47484/4450104.pdf by guest on 29 September 2021 regions of the brain seem to be specialized for han- able from looking at the constituents, but put them dling categories for natural things and others for together in certain ways, and you get these really manmade things. And within the regions specialized extraordinaryproperties. The mental properties for for manmade things, there is further categorization: perception, for knowledge, for learning, for memory, for example, tools that you use with your hands, and all had to come out of the complexity of the organi- other kinds of things like automobiles. We don't zation of matter. My own backgroundwas very much know how brains do this regionalization,so we don't in that line of thinking. The Darwinian perspective know how to make nets that can help us understand always seemed to me to be the key to making things it. Another key question about brains is how they get sensible. I don't find rejecting a nonphysical soul things done in time. How can an eagle intercept its personally wrenching, but I realize that some people prey? How can you catch an outfield fly? How you do. When students first encounter the thought that get the timing right is a majorissue for a lot of neural maybe there is only the brain-which means that network theory now. What we desperately need is when the brain dies, I die-it's something they have more understanding of neuroanatomyat the network to think through, not just in scientific terms but in level. very personal terms. They will sometimes ask me, doesn't it make you feel as if the world is a very bleak place or that there is no meaning to life? My response Campbell: Modeling neural nets on a computer is is that in lots of ways the idea of an afterlifedoes you one thing, but is the brain itself a type of computer? an enormous disservice. It gives you the idea that you Churchland:It's useful to think of the brain as a kind can defer lots of things and make it all come out right of computer because that allows you a frameworkfor later. I think if you take the view that the planet is the thinking about how individual neurons interact to thing to love and to care for and to see the future achieve a certain effect. Suppose you are trying to for-if you see that as a source of meaning and visually tracka given object and your head is turning value-you'll see that the other story doesn't help in as you walk. Viewing the brain as a kind of computer making life decisions and in feeling comfortable. It helps conceptualize the interactionbetween the neu- doesn't help particularlywith tragic situations and rons in the vestibular organ, which detects head death and the things that we all find deeply trou- movement, and the neurons that control eye move- bling. When students think about it in that context, ment. There are, however, many contrasts between they often do say, yeah, maybe you're right about the brain and a desktop computer. For example, in that, I'll just have to live it for awhile and see if I can. the brain the very elements that process perception are also elements that store information about what you perceive. It isn't that the memory is in one place If we view the mind functions as Campbell: major and the processing for perception is in another place. of the brain what emergent properties organization, The brain's style is parallel and analog computation. do we need to understand about neural complexity to explain these mental functions? Churchland:I think the majorarea we're missing is at Campbell: Do you think knowledge of the brain can the level of neural networks.
Recommended publications
  • Neurophilosophy and Its Discontents How Do We Understand Consciousness Without Becoming Complicit in That Understanding?
    Neurophilosophy and Its Discontents How Do We Understand Consciousness Without Becoming Complicit in that Understanding? BY GABRIELLE BENETTE JACKSON dependent on empathy or imagination. Though presumably it would not capture everything, its goal would be to describe, at least in part, the subjective character of hat is consciousness? “It is being awake,” “being responsive,” “acting,” “being experience in a form comprehensible to beings incapable of having those experi- Waware,” “being self-aware,” “paying attention,” “perceiving,” “feeling emo- ences. […] It should be possible to devise a method of expressing in objective terms tions,” “feeling feelings,” “having thoughts,” “thinking about thoughts,” “it is like much more than we can at present, and with much greater precision.” The proposal, this!” simply put, was to develop a language to describe subjectivity in non-subjective Who is conscious? “We humans, surely!” Well, maybe not all the time. “Animals!” terms. And although it is definitely not the case that all theorists pushing past the Debatable. “Computers?” No—at least, not yet. “Other machines?” Only in fiction. problem of consciousness consider themselves to be implementing Nagel’s plan, it “Plants?” Absolutely not, right? does help to understand a particular set of accumulated answers. Two fundamental Nearly twenty-five years ago, we lived through “the project of the decade of the approaches have been neurophilosophy and neurophenomenology, each emphasizing brain,” a governmental initiative set forth by President one aspect of Nagel’s suggestion—either the objective part George H. W. Bush.1 Presidential Proclamation 6158 (viz. neurophilosophy) or the phenomenology part (viz. begins, “The human brain, a three-pound mass of inter- neurophenomenology).
    [Show full text]
  • Churchland Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Reduction, Qualia, and the Direct Introspection of Brain States Author(s): Paul M. Churchland Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 82, No. 1 (Jan., 1985), pp. 8-28 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026509 Accessed: 07-08-2015 19:14 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 142.58.129.109 on Fri, 07 Aug 2015 19:14:45 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 8 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY structureof this idiom, moreover-its embeddingof a subordinate sentence-would have been clearly dictatedby its primitiveuse in assessing children's acquisition of observationsentences. Analogi- cal extension of the idiom to other than observation sentences would follow inevitably,and the developmentof parallel idioms for other propositional attitudeswould then come naturally too, notwithstanding their opacity from a logical point of view. Naturalness is one thing, transparencyanother; familiarityone, clarityanother. W. V. QtJINE Harvard University REDUCTION, QUALIA, AND THE DIRECT INTROSPECTION OF BRAIN STATES* DO the phenomenological or qualitative featuresof our sen- sations constitutea permanentbarrier to thereductive aspi- rations of any materialisticneuroscience? I here argue that theydo not.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defence of Folk Psychology
    FRANK JACKSON & PHILIP PETTIT IN DEFENCE OF FOLK PSYCHOLOGY (Received 14 October, 1988) It turned out that there was no phlogiston, no caloric fluid, and no luminiferous ether. Might it turn out that there are no beliefs and desires? Patricia and Paul Churchland say yes. ~ We say no. In part one we give our positive argument for the existence of beliefs and desires, and in part two we offer a diagnosis of what has misled the Church- lands into holding that it might very well turn out that there are no beliefs and desires. 1. THE EXISTENCE OF BELIEFS AND DESIRES 1.1. Our Strategy Eliminativists do not insist that it is certain as of now that there are no beliefs and desires. They insist that it might very well turn out that there are no beliefs and desires. Thus, in order to engage with their position, we need to provide a case for beliefs and desires which, in addition to being a strong one given what we now know, is one which is peculiarly unlikely to be undermined by future progress in neuroscience. Our first step towards providing such a case is to observe that the question of the existence of beliefs and desires as conceived in folk psychology can be divided into two questions. There exist beliefs and desires if there exist creatures with states truly describable as states of believing that such-and-such or desiring that so-and-so. Our question, then, can be divided into two questions. First, what is it for a state to be truly describable as a belief or as a desire; what, that is, needs to be the case according to our folk conception of belief and desire for a state to be a belief or a desire? And, second, is what needs to be the case in fact the case? Accordingly , if we accepted a certain, simple behaviourist account of, say, our folk Philosophical Studies 59:31--54, 1990.
    [Show full text]
  • Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World
    Reconciling Eros and Neuroscience: Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World by ANDREW J. PELLITIERI* Boston University Abstract Many people currently working in the sciences of the mind believe terms such as “love” will soon be rendered philosophically obsolete. This belief results from a common assumption that such terms are irreconcilable with the naturalistic worldview that most modern scientists might require. Some philosophers reject the meaning of the terms, claiming that as science progresses words like ‘love’ and ‘happiness’ will be replaced completely by language that is more descriptive of the material phenomena taking place. This paper attempts to defend these meaningful concepts in philosophy of mind without appealing to concepts a materialist could not accept. Introduction hilosophy engages the meaning of the word “love” in a myriad of complex discourses ranging from ancient musings on happiness, Pto modern work in the philosophy of mind. The eliminative and reductive forms of materialism threaten to reduce the importance of our everyday language and devalue the meaning we attach to words like “love,” in the name of scientific progress. Faced with this threat, some philosophers, such as Owen Flanagan, have attempted to defend meaningful words and concepts important to the contemporary philosopher, while simultaneously promoting widespread acceptance of materialism. While I believe that the available work is useful, I think * [email protected]. Received 1/2011, revised December 2011. © the author. Arché Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy, Volume V, Issue 1: Winter 2012. pp. 60-82 RECONCILING EROS AND NEUROSCIENCE 61 more needs to be said about the functional role of words like “love” in the script of progressing neuroscience, and further the important implications this yields for our current mode of practical reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Tools of Pragmatism
    Coping with the World: Tools of Pragmatism Mind, Brain and the Intentional Vocabulary Anders Kristian Krabberød Hovedoppgave Filosofisk Institutt UNIVERSITETET I OSLO Høsten 2004 Contents 1. Introduction.................................................................................................. 2 2. Different Ways of Describing the Same Thing ........................................... 7 3. Rorty and Vocabularies ............................................................................. 11 The Vocabulary-Vocabulary ...............................................................................................13 Reduction and Ontology......................................................................................................17 4. The Intentional Vocabulary and Folk Psychology: the Churchlands and Eliminative Materialism ................................................................................ 21 Eliminative Materialism......................................................................................................22 Dire Consequences..............................................................................................................24 Objecting against Eliminative Materialism..........................................................................25 1. The first objection: Eliminative materialism is a non-starter........................................27 2. The second objection: What could possibly falsify Folk Psychology?...........................29 3. The third objection: Folk Psychology is used
    [Show full text]
  • Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2Nd Edition, Macmillan Press, 2005
    Ronald Endicott, “Multiple Realizability” (Final Draft) Forthcoming in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition, MacMillan Press, 2005 Multiple realizability is a key issue in debates over the nature of mind and reduction in the sciences. The subject consists of two parts: “multiplicity” and “realizability.” “Multiplicity” designates a kind of variability in the mechanism and materials from which a particular type of thing can be made. “Realizability” designates a specific relation that exists when there is the stated variability. Realizability Apart from the broad folk notion of realization meaning that a thing is “made real,” philosophers apply several technical notions to paradigm cases such computational states realized by engineering states, minds realized by brains, and persons realized by their bodies. The technical notions fall into three broad traditions: “mathematical,” “logico- semantic,” and “metaphysical.” The mathematical tradition equates realization with a form of mapping between objects. Generally speaking, x mathematically realizes y because elements of y map onto elements of x. The notion is useful for many purposes, for example, when constructing a formal model of a particular domain. However, since mapping extends to models as well as reality, it fails to distinguish between “simulated” versus “genuine” realizations. Heavenly stars can be mapped onto grains of sand, but grains of sand do not realize heavenly stars in any genuine sense. Similarly, the mental states described by a cognitive program can be mapped onto unthinking groups of things, but unthinking groups of things do not realize mental states in any genuine sense (Block, 1978). Hence, to capture what is essential to genuine realization, William Lycan (1987) adds ideas about evolutionary function, while David Chalmers (1994) emphasizes facts about causal structure.
    [Show full text]
  • 5 Human Dignity from a Neurophilosophical Perspective
    1 2 3 4 5 6 5 7 8 9 10 Human Dignity From a 11 Neurophilosophical Perspective 12 13 Patricia S. Churchland 14 15 his essay on human dignity and bioethics will have six parts. In 16T the first, I argue that dignity is an important concept whose 17 meaning is inherently ambiguous and cannot be settled by appeals 18 to religious authority, conceptual analysis, or philosophical argu- 19 ment; instead, the meaning of human dignity—and its specific con- 20 sequences for today’s biomedical controversies—must be worked 21 out pragmatically, in a spirit of compromise. In the second part, I 22 suggest that we can gain some clarity about human dignity by exam- 23 ining where morality comes from, and in particular the biological 24 and social origins of human moral behavior. In the third part, I ar- 25 gue that moral progress is possible, but that misplaced moral certi- 26 tude can do more harm to human dignity than good. In part four, I 27 describe historical cases in which medical progress was impeded by 28 moral and theological opposition, and I predict that those who to- 29 day are morally opposed to embryonic stem cell research will fall 30 silent once the clear medical benefits begin to emerge. Part five 31 considers a deeper question concerning human dignity: whether 32 modern biology has exposed human dignity itself as something that 33 doesn’t really exist. Part six addresses the related question of 34 whether, in the light of modern neuroscience, holding people mor- 35 ally responsible makes any sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Empfindungsfähigkeit Und Moralischer Status Eine Kritik Der Pathozentrischen Ethik
    Empfindungsfähigkeit und moralischer Status Eine Kritik der pathozentrischen Ethik Inauguraldissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Philosophie im Fachbereich A Geistes- und Kulturwissenschaften der Bergischen Universität Wuppertal vorgelegt von Erasmus Scheuer aus Düsseldorf Wuppertal, im Januar 2018 Die Dissertation kann wie folgt zitiert werden: urn:nbn:de:hbz:468-20180503-133904-3 [http://nbn-resolving.de/urn/resolver.pl?urn=urn%3Anbn%3Ade%3Ahbz% 3A468-20180503-133904-3] alles bleibt wie es ist Geheimnis in einem Geheimnis Muster in einem Muster (Norbert Scheuer – Nichts) Meinen Eltern, Elvira und Norbert Scheuer Vorwort Der Pathozentrismus betrachtet die Leidens- oder Empfindungsfähigkeit aller, auch nichtmenschlicher Spezies als zentrales moralisches Kriterium. Diese Arbeit hat die pathozentrische Position zum Gegenstand und bewegt sich bewusst zwischen Kritik und Verteidigung eines solchen Ansatzes. Einerseits liegen die Schwächen des Pa- thozentrismus m.E. mehr oder weniger offen zu Tage, da die Kluft zwischen Empfin- dungen des Menschen und den Empfindungen anderer Spezies nur schwer inner- halb eines naturwissenschaftlich-physikalistischen Weltbildes überbrückbar erscheint. Andererseits vertrete ich als Verfasser dieser Arbeit die Ansicht, dass eine Erweiterung der Moralobjekte über die Menschen hinaus erfolgen muss, dass das Leiden anderer Kreaturen Teil einer jeden ethischen Betrachtung sein sollte. Der Pa- thozentrismus vertritt mit seinem Kriterium der Leidens- bzw. Empfindungsfähigkeit eine ethische Position, die vom Ansatz her eine Erweiterung der Moralobjekte an- strebt. Aus diesem Grund liegt meine Sympathie beim Pathozentristen. Infolgedes- sen versucht diese Arbeit, einerseits die Kritik am Pathozentrismus aufzuzeigen, an- dererseits dem Pathozentristen auch Argumente an die Hand zu geben, die es ihm erlauben, seine Position zu verteidigen. Der Pathozentrist hat nach meiner Ansicht zwei schwerwiegende und grundlegende Probleme, wenn er seine Ethik innerhalb eines tendenziell physikalistischen Weltbildes zu verteidigen sucht.
    [Show full text]
  • Precis of Psychoneural Reduction: the New Wa Ve
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 61 (2001) 249-255 PRECIS OF PSYCHONEURAL REDUCTION: THE NEW WA VE John BICKLE University of Cincinnati Although her plumb for eliminative materialism generated the most sound and fury, three other projects in Patricia Churchland's (1986) Neurophilosophy were of greater philosophical significance: Contributing to a new theory of cross-levels intertheoretic reduc- tion for science in general and reformulating the traditional mind-body problem using these resources; Replying to dualists' arguments based on features of conscious ex- perience (qualia, subjectivity); Replying to multiple realizability arguments for both functionalism and the methodological autonomy of cognitive psychology from the neurosciences. Churchland did not invent any of these projects, but her book gave them a unified focus grounded on a post-logical empiricist philosophy of science and a wealth of empirical neuroscientific detail. Unfortunately, these three projects and the progress Church land and other reductionists made got lost in the bombast over eliminativism. By the late-1990s interest in eliminativism had waned, but recent de- velopments in philosophy of mind had also eclipsed these specific pro- jects. Some flaws in the theory of intertheoretic reduction remained unad- dressed. (Clifford Hooker 1981 had first noticed these in the very paper that remained the benchmark for the theory.) New "dualistic" arguments based on more sophisticated metaphysics emerged (Chalmers 1996), along with "New Mysterian" worries about humans' capabilites of solv- ing the consciousness-brain problem (McGinn, 1989). Nonreductive physicalism replaced functionalism, and supervenience replaced realiza- tion as the preferred alternative to reduction. Clearly, if "neurophiloso- phy" was to remain viable, these three projects and their unity within a philosophy of science and the empirical neurosciences required reformu- 250 lation and a new focus.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE John Bickle December 2020
    CURRICULUM VITAE John Bickle December 2020 Mailing Address: Department of Philosophy and Religion P.O. Box JS Mississippi State University Mississippi State, MS 39762 (662) 325-2382 fax: (662) 325-3340 E-mail Addresses: [email protected] URLs: http://www.philosophyandreligion.msstate.edu/faculty/bickle.php https://www.umc.edu/Education/Schools/Medicine/Basic_Science/Neurobiology/John_Bi ckle,_PhD.aspx ___________________________________________________________________________ CURRENT ACADEMIC POSITIONS Professor (Tenured) of Philosophy Mississippi State University Affiliate Faculty Department of Neurobiology and Anatomical Sciences University of Mississippi Medical Center EDUCATION B.A. University of California, Los Angeles, June 1983 M.A., Ph.D. University of California, Irvine, June 1989 Field: Philosophy; Scientific Concentration: Neurobiology. Doctoral Dissertation: Toward a Scientific Reformulation of the Mind-Body Problem AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Philosophy of Neuroscience, Philosophy of Science (especially Scientific Reductionism), Cellular and Molecular Mechanisms of Cognition and Consciousness AREAS OF COMPETENCE Moral Psychology and the Moral Virtues, Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI). Logical Positivism (especially the Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap), Libertarian Political Philosophy ______________________________________________________________________________ PROFESSIONAL PUBLICATIONS (94) BOOKS (4) 2014 Engineering the Next Revolution in Neuroscience. (Co-authors: Alcino J. Silva and Anthony Landreth).
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Patricia Churchland's
    FACTS AGAINST SPECULATIONS: UNDERSTANDING PATRICIA CHURCHLAND’S NEUROPHILOSOPHY By FARINOLA AUGUSTINE AKINTUNDE INTRODUCTION “The more informed our brains are by science at all levels of analysis, the better will be our brains’ theoretical evolution” -Patricia Churchland (1986) Discourse in philosophy about how human being could attain knowledge, right from the medieval period to the modern period has witnessed scholars making references to the ‘intellect’, the ‘mind’ or the ‘soul’. A radical change in this linguistic reference was challenged by Gilbert Ryle with his analysis of ‘ghost in the machine’. It is appear to be a primitive way of thinking, especially in our age, to still hold on to the view that there is an invisible and immaterial substance, other than the brain, that influence human or regulate human feelings, decisions and means of knowing. Meanwhile, within the tradition of philosophy, idealists and rationalists (along with religiously inclined scholars) will prefer to be consistent with their metaphysical heritage and postulations by challenging any materialistic reduction of a human person to just a material being whose movements, actions, and phenomena surrounding him could be explain simply in empirical terms. Furthermore, a quick glance at the history of ideas, one would recall a moment (starting from David Hume down to the emergence of logical empiricists/positivists and linguists) in which a brutal war was launched against metaphysical ideas, leading to a periodical triumph of science. Though this tension was resolved by scholars like Thomas Kuhn, Karl Popper, Paul K Feyerabend and most post-modern scholars, yet it creates two camps among the scholars of science and philosophy – as the academic protector of metaphysics.
    [Show full text]
  • A Treatise on the Outwardly Nature of Consciousness Ramy Amin
    The American University in Cairo School of Humanities and Social Sciences A Treatise on The Outwardly Nature of Consciousness A Thesis Submitted to The Department of Philosophy In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts By Ramy Amin Under the supervision of Dr. Robert W. McIntyre February 2020 The American University in Cairo A Treatise on The Outwardly Nature of Consciousness A Thesis Submitted by Ramy Amin To the Department of Philosophy February 2020 In partial fulfillment of the requirements for The degree of Master of Arts Has been approved by Dr. Robert W. McIntyre Thesis Committee Advisor____________________________________________ Affiliation_________________________________________________________ Dr. Alessandro Topa Thesis Committee Reader____________________________________________ Affiliation_________________________________________________________ Dr. Patrick Hassan Thesis Committee Reader____________________________________________ Affiliation ________________ __________ ________ __________ Dept. Chair Date Dean of HUSS Date II Acknowledgments I’d like to thank Dr. Robert McIntyre for his continuous support and guidance, Dr. Alessandro Topa for his perceptive comments and insights, Dr. Patrick Hassan for his valuable remarks and encouragement, and Dr. Matthew Crippen for his early support that helped shape the thesis into what it is now. III Abstract In this thesis we propose a sketch towards an outwardly understanding of the nature of consciousness. We begin by arguing that all thought involves phenomenal character, then establish that all phenomenal character involves phenomenal concepts, which allows us to conclude that all thought involves phenomenal concepts. Finally, we survey the philosophical theoretical space to ground our thesis within established theories of consciousness, perception, and epistemology. IV Table of Contents Introduction 1 Chapter I: On Sensory Restriction 4 Section I: An Introduction to Sensory Restriction 4 1.
    [Show full text]