Critique of Worldmaking»? Nelson Goodman’S Conception of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Critique of Worldmaking»? Nelson Goodman’S Conception of Philosophy Enrahonar. Quaderns de Filosofia 49, 2012 29-40 What is «Critique of Worldmaking»? Nelson Goodman’s Conception of Philosophy Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim [email protected] Abstract The contribution examines Goodman’s conception of philosophy, in particular his remark that his project can be understood as a «critique of worldmaking». It is argued that, despite dealing with epistemological questions, the general theory of symbols and worldmaking does not answer them. Rather, it can be conceived as a practical conception comparable to Kant’s critique of reason or to Wittgenstein’s critique of language games, i. e., as a philosophy of world orient ation. It is claimed that Goodman himself could not artic ulate this dimension of his position appropriately as he kept using the language of epistemol- ogy. Yet many aspects of his thinking become much clearer if they are interpreted with in a non-epistemological frame. Keywords: Goodman; symbol theory; worldmaking; world orientation; world disclosure. Resumen. ¿Qué es la «crítica de la construcción de mundos»? La concepción de la filosofía de Nelson Goodman Esta contribución examina la concepción de la filosofía de Goodman, concretamente su afirmación de que su proyecto puede entenderse como una «crítica de la construcción de mundos». Se argumenta que, a pesar de tratar cuestiones epistemológicas, la teoría general de los símbolos y de la construcción de mundos no las contesta. Más bien se puede conside- rar como una concepción práctica comparable a la crítica de la razón de Kant o a la crítica de los juegos del lenguaje de Wittgenstein, esto es, como una filosofía de la orientación del mundo. Se defiende que Goodman no podría haber articulado esta dimensión de su postura de un modo apropiado puesto que siguió usando el lenguaje de la epistemología. Ahora bien, muchos aspectos de su pensamiento son mucho más claros si se interpretan en un marco no epistemológico. Palabras clave: Goodman; teoría de los símbolos; construcción de mundos; orientación del mundo; apertura del mundo. 30 Enrahonar 49, 2012 Lars Leeten Summary 1. Introduction 4. The language of representation 2. Constructionalism and the idea 5. Beyond representation of mapmaking References 3. Worldmaking as mapmaking 1. Introduction In Ways of Worldmaking, Nelson Goodman describes his philosophical project as a critique of worldmaking: «Worlds are made by making [...] versions with words, numerals, pictures, sounds, or other symbols of any kind in any medi- um; and the comparative study of these versions and visions and of their making is what I call a critique of worldmaking» (WW, 94). Elsewhere Good- man says that his «main under taking [...] is examination and compar ison of the ways we make what we make — call them versions or worlds as you like — and of the criteria we use in judging what we make» (MM, 43). — What does the label «critique of world­­making» exactly mean? What is the conception of philo sophy Goodman has in mind? And how do we have to interpret his general symbol theory if it is primarily a critique of world making? It is tempting to think that «critique of world making» is just a different label for «epi stemology», only that its scope is broader. One basic assumption of this article, though, is that Goodman is not engaged in epistemology at all, at least not in the usual sense. The question is not whether epistemology has to be conceived narrow or broad. Symbol theory is not so much a theory but rather a practical conception, a certain technique of thinking. This might seem rather far-fetched at first sight, as Goodman more than once emphasizes that a philosopher «is driven not by practical needs but by an impractical desire to understand» (PP, 169). Even though he discovers language practice as a fun- damental point of reference in his theory of induction (especially, FFF, 4.3- 4.4), he never takes into account the details of the pragmatic dimension of sign use and everyday language (Goodman, 1996, 205). His refusal to go into questions of ethical rightness (WW, 109, Fn. 1) only underlines a general lack of normative discussion in Good man’s work. Therefore one is inclined to perceive his «general theory of under stand ing» (R, 53) as a general theory of knowl edge, an extended epistemological con ception concerned with «under- standing or cog nition in all of its modes» (R, 4). Accordingly, rightness is taken to be Goodman’s epi stemo­­logical criterion, representing the standard to sep- arate acceptable from inacceptable world descriptions. Right ness takes the place of truth, only that it is, «unlike truth, [...] multi dimen sional» (R, 156). The expressions may have changed, but the project is still the same. Here, this perspective is called into question. Goodman, to be sure, uses the vocabulary of epistemology and he starts with the problems of epistemol- Nelson Goodman's Conception of Philosophy Enrahonar 49, 2012 31 ogy. Still, many elements of his thinking become much clearer if they are interpreted in a frame beyond epistemology. His philosophy is done more justice if one presupposes that it does not answer to epistemological questions. In order to show this, I will first examine some of Goodman’s early general con sider ations on philo sophy, in particular the idea of constructional systems (2). Second, I will try to develop my thesis in the context of his later philoso- phy of symbols and worldmaking (3). Finally I will come back to the question of epistemology (4) and try to give an alternative account of what «critique of world making» might mean (5). My claim will be that this label points into the direction of a practical reflection comparable to Kant’s critique of reason or to Witt gen stein’s critique of language games, i. e., as a philosophy of world orient ation and world disclosure under the conditions of finiteness — a claim which, of course, does not include a «truth about Good man», but only suggests a certain way of ca tegorization. 2. Constructionalism and the idea of mapmaking Goodman’s philosophical work contains many issues from quite diverse fields like ontology, logic, epistemology, symbol theory and aesthetics. It would be difficult to extract his conception of philosophy from this starting point. So what does he say about his notion of philosophy? In the final chapter of Reconceptions in Philosophy and Other Arts and Sci­ ences, under the heading «A Reconception of Philosophy», we find the idea of a three-staged undertaking that starts with the examination of symbols, then turns to their constitutive meaning for world dis closure, and finally results in a revision of philosophy (R, 164). The consider ations of Languages of Art, then, could be the first step of a project that continues with Ways of Worldmaking, and ends with the outline of a new notion of philo sophy. This notion, though, is presented as a certain epi stemological position called «constructionalism» (R, 166). In the follow ing, I claim that Good man’s thinking implicitly suggests a much more radically revised conception of philo sophy. Indeed, the label «epistemology» is misleading here, as the philosophy of worldmaking should better be interpreted as a conception presupposing a primacy of practice. In order to show this, though, we have to go back to The Structure of Appearance and Problems and Projects. One of the main motives in Goodman’s early work is his repudiation of the ideas of certainty and immediacy. The position that becomes apparent in The Structure of Appear ance seems to be the result: Goodman obviously rejects any epistemological founda tion alism in favor of an epistemological stance called pheno menalism. But the second sight shows that things are slightly more complicated. Goodman does develop a phenomenalistic system in his early work. Yet this does not mean that he supports phenomenalism as the right system of epistemology. Indeed, in the introduction to The Structure of Appear­ ance it is underlined that the frame of the con ception is the theory of construc- tional systems which includes strong relativist and pluralist assumptions, in 32 Enrahonar 49, 2012 Lars Leeten particular the assumption that phenomenalism is only one of many possibilities of reconstruction (SA, il-l). His con ception must not be taken as an immediate expression of Good man’s philo so phical standpoint. He does not want to explain the world or give a fundament to knowledge. His aim is to systematize knowledge. The phenomenalist conception is rather an example of the philo- sophical stance Good man takes. From the view point of the phenomenalist theory, the basic assumptions of this position are part of a meta theory (Hell- mann 1977, xxvi f and SA, l). What we have to ask, then, is what this metatheory, namely the theory of constructional systems implies. Goodman develops this theory in the first part of The Structure of Appear ance. A constructional system is a system of construc- tional definitions, i. e., of definitions «introduced for explanatory purposes» (SA, 3). Unlike a notational definition, a constructional de finition defines everyday or pre system atic ex pres sions while preserving their original interpretation. It serves to clarify the presystematic domain by reaching both economy (a reduc- tion of primitive terms) and a systematic order (SA, 47f). «To economize and to systematize are the same» (SA, 48). In order to serve this purpose, a con- structional de finition does not only have to fulfill formal requirements: «A con struc tional de finition is correct — apart from formal considerations — if the range of application of its definiens is the same as that of the definiendum. Nothing more is required than that the two expressions have identical exten- sions» (SA, 3).
Recommended publications
  • On Moral Understanding
    COMMENTTHE COLLEGE NEWSLETTER ISSUE NO 147 | MAY 2003 TOM WHIPPS On Moral Understanding DNA pioneers: The surviving members of the King’s team, who worked on the discovery of the structure of DNA 50 years ago, withDavid James Watson, K Levytheir Cambridge ‘rival’ at the time. From left Ray Gosling, Herbert Wilson, DNA at King’s: DepartmentJames Watson and of Maurice Philosophy Wilkins King’s College the continuing story University of London Prize for his contribution – and A day of celebrations their teams, but also to subse- quent generations of scientists at ver 600 guests attended a cant scientific discovery of the King’s. unique day of events celeb- 20th century,’ in the words of Four Nobel Laureates – Mau- Orating King’s role in the 50th Principal Professor Arthur Lucas, rice Wilkins, James Watson, Sid- anniversary of the discovery of the ‘and their research changed ney Altman and Tim Hunt – double helix structure of DNA on the world’. attended the event which was so 22 April. The day paid tribute not only to oversubscribed that the proceed- Scientists at King’s played a King’s DNA pioneers Rosalind ings were relayed by video link to fundamental role in this momen- Franklin and Maurice Wilkins – tous discovery – ‘the most signifi- who went onto win the Nobel continued on page 2 2 Funding news | 3 Peace Operations Review | 5 Widening participation | 8 25 years of Anglo-French law | 11 Margaret Atwood at King’s | 12 Susan Gibson wins Rosalind Franklin Award | 15 Focus: School of Law | 16 Research news | 18 Books | 19 KCLSU election results | 20 Arts abcdef U N I V E R S I T Y O F L O N D O N A C C O M M O D A T I O N O F F I C E ACCOMMODATION INFORMATION - FINDING SOMEWHERE TO LIVE IN THE PRIVATE SECTOR Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy WARNING: Under no circumstances inshould the this University document be of taken London as providing legal advice.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Epistemological Significance of Aesthetic Values in Architectural Theory
    On the Epistemological Significance of Aesthetic Values in Architectural Theory by Ritu Bhatt Master of Architecture (1993) Kansas State University Bachelor of Architecture (1990) University of Roorkee, India Submitted to the Department of Architecture in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Architecture: History and Theory of Architecture at the T yTT Massachusetts Institute of Technology January, 2000 @ 2000 Ritu Bhatt. All rights reserved The author hereby grants to MIT permission to reproduce and to distribute publicly paper and electronic copies of this thesis document in whole or in part. Signature of Author...................................................................... Department of Architecture January 7, 2000 C ertified b . ... .................... .. tanrord A son ark Jarzo Professor of History and Assoc. Pro essor of History and Architecture Architecture Thesis Co- Supervisor Thesis Co- Supervisor Accepted by................................. V ... - ........ Stanford Anderson Chairman, Department Committee on Graduate Students Thesis Readers Professor Stanford Anderson Professor of History and Architecture Head, Department of Architecture, MIT Professor Mark Jarzombek Associate Professor of History and Architecture, MIT Professor Sibel Bozdogan Adjunct Professor, Graduate School of Design, Harvard University Professor Diane Ghirardo Professor of Architecture, University of Southern California Professor Satya P. Mohanty Professor of English, Cornell University Professor Catherine
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of Nelson Goodman's Aesthetics: Music As Process
    PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research & Ideas Volume 1 Number 1 Article 6 2020 A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process William S. Gilbert University of North Florida, [email protected] Faculty Mentor: Sarah Mattice, PhD, Associate Professor Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies This paper was a co-winner of the Philosophy Program's 2019-2020 Paper Prize. Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/pandion_unf Part of the Comparative Philosophy Commons, and the Esthetics Commons Recommended Citation Gilbert, William S. (2020) "A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process," PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research and Ideas: Vol. 1 : No. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/pandion_unf/vol1/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at UNF Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research & Ideas by an authorized administrator of UNF Digital Commons. For more information, please contact Digital Projects. © 2020 All Rights Reserved A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process Cover Page Footnote The advice and mentorship offered by Dr. Sarah Mattice was absolutely critical in not only the essays development but also my development as a student and thinker. Her feedback and generosity with time in meetings is something I am deeply grateful for. Dr. Jean Miller of Virginia Tech is also responsible for highly valuable suggestions for a much needed revision. I am very grateful for her advice. Finally I would like to thank Jason Simpson of the UNF Writing Center.
    [Show full text]
  • Nelson Goodman's Arguments Against Perspective: a Geometrical
    Branko Mitroviü Research Department of Architecture Nelson Goodman’s Arguments Against Unitec Institute of Technology Carrington Rd., Mt Albert Perspective: A Geometrical Analysis Auckland, NEW ZEALAND Presented at Nexus 2012: Relationships Between Architecture [email protected] and Mathematics, Milan, 11-14 June 2012 Keywords: Nelson Goodman, Abstract. Nelson Goodman’s highly influential book perspective theory, geometry of Languages of Art argued that that all visual experience is perspective, Ernst Gombrich, merely a cultural construct. In presenting his thesis Goodman Erwin Panofsky relied on a series of geometrical arguments intended to show that the geometrical construction of perspective does not rely on the geometry of light rays. In this article I analyze the geometrical validity of Goodman's arguments. Introduction For the past fifty years few books by English-speaking philosophers have exercised a greater influence on art- and architectural history than Nelson Goodman’s Languages of Art [1968]. This book was an important contribution to the rise of cultural relativism that subsequently came to dominate the English-speaking humanities for decades. Goodman adopted the view (previously advocated by Ernst Gombrich in his book Art and Illusion [1960]) that “there is no innocent eye” and that the totality of an individual’s perception is predetermined by and a result of that person’s conceptual framework.1 Unlike Gombrich, however, Goodman inferred that, since our conceptual frameworks derive from the cultures we live in, all we can know and perceive is a result of our cultural background; he consequently argued that reality itself was but a cultural construct.2 According to this view, there are no facts that constitute the world independent of human cognitive apparatus.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Benacerraf a Goodman-Lewis
    How to Benacerraf a Goodman-Lewis This paper offers a limited defense of the thesis Nelson Goodman labels “nominalism,” according to which there are no distinct entities constructed from the same basic entities. Goodmanian nominalism-- “gnominalism,” for short—bears an uncertain relation to more familiar nominalist theses, but, according to Goodman, anti-gnominalism is simply “incomprehensible.” Unfortunately, as many commentators have noted, Goodman offers frustratingly little in the way of arguments for gnominalism. The present reassessment of gnominalism argues that Goodman is right to claim that theories violating gnominalism incur a distinctive theoretical vice. At the same time, the glaring lack of arguments for gnominalism indicate that something has gone badly wrong. Roughly speaking, Goodman’s support for gnominalism mistakes the symptom for the disease. This is because the vice of anti-gnominalist theories is that they are uniformly susceptible to variations on the Non-Uniqueness Problem that Paul Benacerraf presents for set- theoretic reductions. Gnominalism can therefore be motivated as a response to the Non-Uniqueness Problem. For this reason, would-be gnominalists like David Lewis are best served to argue against contested posits by showing these posits to yield Non-Uniqueness Problems given the existence of distinct entities constructed from the basic entities. To this end, after explaining gnominalism and its connection to the Non-Uniqueness Problem, I discuss how Lewis’ version of gnominalism departs from Goodman’s own. I then argue that a Non-Uniqueness Problem arises for those who posit structural universals—the leading target of Lewis’ gnominalism. (Word Count: 4284) §1. Introduction Two conceptions of nominalism are commonly distinguished when discussing debates between nominalists and platonists.1 The first kind of nominalism denies the existence of universals and holds, instead, that all entities are particulars rather than general entities like universals.
    [Show full text]
  • Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-1999 Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Aesthetics On-Line (1999). Permalink. © 1999 Curtis Carter. Used with permission. Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter The American philosopher Nelson Goodman died on November 25, 1998, in Needham, Massachusetts, at the age of 92. He was buried in a family grave site in Everett, Massachusetts. His wife, Katharine Sturgis Goodman, preceded him in death in 1996. Born on August 7, 1906 in Sommerville, Massachusetts, Goodman became a leading proponent of analytic philosophy in the United States and his theories are now studied throughout the world. Goodman was a Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University from 1968-1977. Previously he served as Harry Austryn Wolfson Professor of Philosophy at Brandeis University from 1964-67, Professor of Philosophy from 1951-1964 and Associate Professor from 1946- 1951 at the University of Pennsylvania, and Instructor in Philosophy at Tufts College, 1944- 1945. Prior to these appointments Goodman was Director of the Walker-Goodman Art Gallery in Boston from 1929 to 1941. From 1942 to 1945 he performed military service in the United States Army. He received his B.S. in 1928 (Phi Beta Kappa, Magna cum laude) and his Ph.D. in 1941, both from Harvard University. Goodman’s interests ranged from philosophy to collecting art. Within philosophy, Goodman’s writing and teaching were
    [Show full text]
  • John Cage, Gilles Deleuze, and the Idea of Sound Iain
    John Cage, Gilles Deleuze, and the Idea of Sound Iain Campbell [draft only, final version published in parallax, 23:3, 361-378, DOI:10.1080/13534645.2017.1343785] Across John Cage’s writings there is one moment to which he would often return, posing it as a turning point, a kind of singular epiphany in his thought and work. This is his famous visit to an anechoic chamber, and the consequent ‘discovery’ of his concept of silence. Describing his visit to the chamber, an environment designed to have as little acoustic resonance as possible and as such to be as silent as possible, Cage recounts hearing two sounds, one low and one high. Asking the engineer what these sounds were, Cage was told that the former was the sound of his blood in circulation, the latter his nervous system in operation. What Cage takes from this is that there can be no genuine silence, that ‘until I die there will be sounds’.1 This in turn entails a conception of sound wherein it is not defined simply by its analytical characteristics, but also by how it necessarily exceeds intentionality, of both composer and of listener. This is the basis for Cage’s often-repeated but obscure claim that the function of art is to ‘imitate Nature in her manner of operation’,2 and by extension the other oft-repeated Cagean mantra of ‘let[ting] sounds be themselves’3 – two cornerstones of an understanding of art in which the certainty of a creative or observational standpoint cannot serve as its foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • DICTIONARY of PHILOSOPHY This Page Intentionally Left Blank
    A DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY This page intentionally left blank. A Dictionary of Philosophy Third edition A.R.Lacey Department of Philosophy, King’s College, University of London First published in 1976 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd Second edition 1986 Third edition 1996 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © A.R.Lacey 1976, 1986, 1996 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Lacey, A.R. A dictionary of philosophy.—3rd edn. 1. Philosophy—Dictionaries I. Title 190′.3′21 B41 ISBN 0-203-19819-0 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-19822-0 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0-415-13332-7 (Print Edition) Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available on request Preface to the first edition This book aims to give the layman or intending student a pocket encyclopaedia of philosophy, one with a bias towards explaining terminology. The latter task is not an easy one since philosophy is regularly concerned with concepts which are unclear.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ontology of Technique As Explored Through the Early Work of Peter Eisenman
    On the (im)Possibility of Reading: The Ontology of Technique as Explored through the Early Work of Peter Eisenman The significance of the final form resides in its capacity to reveal its own origins. — Peter Eisenman ‘’The Futility of Objects” CHARLES CRAWFORD INTRODUCTION NewSchool of Architecture + Design Can a form in some manner “communicate” to a viewer the “intent” of its cre- ator? In the 1970’s and 1980’s many notable figures explored this question, the question Jorge Silvetti once referred to as “the problem of communication.” Aldo Rossi proposed a language of reductivist purity; Michael Graves a return to the familiar language of classicism; Robert Venturi and Denise Scott Brown a version of Populism; and Peter Eisenman proposed an experiment in pure syntax, devoid of cultural reference. This paper explores issues of ontology and technique and, hopefully, in that pro- cess, suggests a path by which we might connect both to tectonics. With his early work, most notably the houses, the CSULB Student Center and the Wexner Center, Peter Eisenman conducted an experiment in communication, attempting to produce architecture of linguistic structuralism. This attempt to incorporate Chomsky’s theory of syntax into a language of art possessed an inter- nal codification, which it was hoped would aide the viewer in “deconstructing” the process of composition. As Jeffery Kipnis writes, however, in “An Architecture Unbound:” Rather than ‘exposing’ an essential structure of (all) architectural possibility in an unambiguously accessible announcement of purely formal intentions, the suc- cess of the work, its architectural potency, seemed, paradoxically, to depend on ambiguity, on a deflection of readable intent.
    [Show full text]
  • Print This Article
    Aesthetic Experience, Mimesis and Testimony Roger W. H. Savage University of California Los Angeles Abstract In this article, I relate the demand that Paul Ricœur suggests mimesis places on the way we think about truth to the idea that the work of art is a model for thinking about testimony. By attributing a work’s epoché of reality to the work of imagination, I resolve the impasse that arises from attributing music, literature, and art’s distance from the real to their social emancipation. Examining the conjunction, in aesthetic experience, of the communicability and the exemplarity of a work reveals how Ricœur’s definition of mimesis as refiguration relates to the “rule” that the work summons. This “rule” constitutes the solution to a problem or question for which the work is the answer. In conclusion, as a model for thinking about testimony, the claims that works make have a counterpart in the injunctions that issue from exemplary moral and political acts. Keywords: Aesthetic experience, Mimesis, Judgment, Testimony Résumé Dans cet article, j’établis un lien entre l’exigence que, selon Paul Ricœur,la mimèsis place dans notre façon de penser la vérité, et l’idée que l’œuvre d’art est un modèle pour penser le témoignage. Appliquant l’époché de la réalité à l’oeuvre d’imagination, j’évite l’impasse qui se dresse lorsqu’on attribue la musique, la littérature et la distance artistique du réel à leur émancipation sociale. L’étude de la conjonction du caractère communicable et exemplaire d’une œuvre – dans l’expérience esthétique - met en lumière la relation que la définition par Ricœur de la mimésis comme refiguration établit avec la “règle” que l’œuvre convoque.
    [Show full text]
  • Phenomenalism in Epistemology and Physicalism in Aesthetics 441 Belonging to a Subject and Representing an Object
    doi: 10.5007/1808-1711.2011v15n3p439 PHENOMENALISMIN EPISTEMOLOGY AND PHYSICALISM IN AESTHETICS JACQUES MORIZOT Université de Provence Abstract. The starting point of this paper is the intriguing observation that Goodman has defended a phenomenalist point of view in his epistemological works and a physicalist one in aesthetics. In fact, it would certainly be more accurate to say that his focus was anti physicalist in epistemology and anti phenomenalist in aesthetics. In any case a majority of interpreters would spontaneously have waited for a diametrically opposite choice, more con- sistent indeed with the positions taken by the representatives in these fields. Yet Goodman’s strategy is not arbitrary, it has deep roots in the general context of the philosophy in the twentieth century and in return contributes to clarify some of its features and motivation. Keywords: Phenomenalism; physicalism; epistemology; aesthetics. The starting point of this paper is the intriguing observation that Goodman has de- fended a phenomenalist point of view in his epistemological works and a physicalist one in aesthetics. In fact, it would certainly be more accurate to say that his focus was anti physicalist in epistemology and anti phenomenalist in aesthetics. In any case a majority of interpreters would spontaneously have waited for a diametrically opposite choice, more consistent indeed with the positions taken by the representa- tives in these fields. Yet Goodman’s strategy is not arbitrary, it has deep roots in the general context of the philosophy in the twentieth century and in return contributes to clarify some of its features and motivation. First it is worth mentioning that to state the problem in these terms may already seem questionable because the concept of ‘phenomenalism’ no longer occupies a prominent place in our contemporary philosophical horizon.
    [Show full text]
  • On Freeing Aesthetic Emotions
    Inside-Out or Outside-In? On Freeing Aesthetic Emotions Gerald Moshammer and Barbara Ekamp Introduction In their seminal Dialectic of Enlightenment, Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno drastically portray the scientific usurpation of the human sphere: That they [the behaviorists] apply to human beings the same formulae and results which they wring without restraint from defenseless animals in their abominable physiological laboratories, proclaims the difference in an especially subtle way. The conclusion they draw from the mutilated animal bodies applies, not to animals in freedom, but to human beings today. By mistreating animals they announce that they, and only they in the whole of creation, function voluntarily in the same mechanical blind, automatic way as the twitching movements of the bound victims made use of by the expert.1 Immanuel Kant famously defined the Enlightenment as emancipation from superstition. He argued in the name of science, that is, natural laws. Yet, against the backdrop of his diagnosis, Kant equally undertook an immense dialectic effort to expose ethical reasoning and aesthetic experience as autonomous islands in the sea of blind natural forces. The Neo-Marxists Adorno and Horkheimer do not subscribe to such a sharp contrast between nature and deontic rationality or aesthetic imagination. They, however, follow Kant in not selling out to science every gram of the human soul. They note, “art, morality, and sublime love are masks of nature, in which nature reappears transformed and becomes expressive as its own antithesis. Through its masks it acquires the gift of speech; in its distortion it manifests its essence; beauty is the serpent which displays the wound where once the fang was implanted.”2 The behaviorists, on the contrary, are Gerald Moshammer is an Assistant Professor and Barbara Ekamp a Lecturer at Mahidol University International College, Thailand.
    [Show full text]