Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Evan Wm. Cameron Professor Emeritus Senior Scholar in Screenwriting Graduate Programmes, Film & Video and Philosophy York University [Presented on 13 February 1985 to the 'Media, Mind and Society' Seminar of David R. Olson, Co-Director of the McLuhan Program in Culture and Technology, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ontario. (Original notes in outline form, amended only as needed to permit comprehension by readers.) Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique1 1. Opening remarks: 2. Novel status of Goodman among philosophical peers: A. Philosophers are specialists (philosophers of science, for example, or logicians, aestheticians, philosophers of language, philosophers of mathematics and so on); yet Goodman has published in journals ranging from the Journal of Symbolic Logic to the Journal of Aesthetics; has had reviews of his work in specialized journals of science, mathematics, art and critical studies; and has been invited to give the John Locke lectures at Oxford and the 1st Kant lectures at Stanford. B. Peers are specialists; proceed as if Goodman had not lived, thought or written; yet the best of them admit that their only genuine antagonist is Goodman. How so? During the early part of his career, Goodman managed to construct within many parts of philosophy contradictions and paradoxes that not only rendered all current work suspect but seemed to promise that all future work would be suspect as well. The only choice, in many of these fields, was to plow ahead as if he didn't exist, or to stop working! 3. Examples of prior (and devastating) critical work: A. Inductive Logic (and therewith all of confirmation and falsification theory and hence all of the philosophy of science): the 'grue' paradox; B. Philosophy of Language: 1. Absence of synonymy twixt any two terms ('On Likeness of Meaning'; 'On difference of Meaning'); hence neither analyticity nor necessity, and hence little chance for a philosophy of language; 1 "An Approach to a Theory of Symbols" is the subtitle of Nelson Goodman's Languages of Art (Indianapolis, Indiana: Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1968). The book was based upon his John Locke lectures of 1960-61 at Oxford University. When citing passages below, I shall give page references to the second edition (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, 1976). [referred to hereafter as LA.] Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Page 2 of 26 (Synonymy: Two terms, A and B, are synonymous, Goodman believes, if and only if they are: (a) co extensive; and (b) no word compound exists whose A extension is different from its B extension but for which at least one C extension and D extension are different. But then no two words are synonymous, for adequately different word compounds may always be constructed.) 2. absence of the 'given'; hence no language independent criterion for truth possible; hence no useful criterion for truth possible either; 3. demolition of Chomsky's epistemological pretensions concerning innate grammatical structures (and therewith the epistemological import of 'transformational linguistics') (Chomsky holds that a second language need not be innately constrained (it need not, that is, be tied to 'deep' innate ideas). But a child, as Goodman pointed out, is already adept at deciphering and creating non spoken 'signals' by the time 'language', in Chomsky's perverted sense, commences: the child simply learns to generate spoken signals itself as a second language! C. Philosophy of Science: 1. no criterion of 'simplicity' for rival theories possible, for all extralogical postulates of every theory can be eliminated nontrivially. (Paper co-authored with Quine.) 2. paradoxes of contrafactual conditionals ('If Caesar were Napoleon, he would both wear a toga and not wear a toga': contradiction!) D. Philosophy of Mathematics: no paradox but the persistent claim that the word 'set' has neither extension nor meaning; that nominalism is the only proper technique; and hence that the axioms of set theory are ultimately ineffectual (and Cohen's proof seems right on target!) Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Page 3 of 26 All of the above positions are essentially critical achievements advanced within the standard traditions and tools of philosophical inquiry. Goodman then began the constructive work that culminated in the "theory of Symbols" of Languages of Art – an endeavour that, in contradistinction to the above, has failed to receive either general approval or even admitted relevance. Why not? More of that anon. 4. Introduction to Goodman's overall philosophical position: there are many, incompatible, equally right (or true) world descriptions; hence we have no more reason to deny the existence of many worlds corresponding to them then we have to affirm the existence of any world at all. A. Contrast Goodman's position with single world proponents (materialists or idealists, for example, or even most possible world theorists). Why does Goodman believe they are incorrect? B: There are many equally consistent but incompatible world descriptions couched in incompatible languages: for example, physicalist; phenomenalist; mentalist; various artistic symbol systems. Were there only one world and were it knowable to be the only one, we should be able to determine which of the world descriptions as couched in its language is true. But one cannot define 'is true' within a language, for contradiction ensues, nor can one define 'is true' for a language within another language without either begging the question or regressing infinitely. Hence, the predicate 'is true' is useless for distinguishing between world descriptions. (As is the predicate 'is a world', for we cannot within a language predicate it of anything. But that renders the predicate useless within a world description. But then how could we ever know that a world existed, since we cannot say it?) C: Why, then, does Goodman persist in speaking of 'truth', if not useless, as being often only of secondary importance to 'rightness', 'fit', etc.? 1. Because although the predicate 'is true' may have little use, the two place predicate 'is truer than' is useful indeed! (Compare: to know that 'A is faster than B', I need not know what 'A is fast' or 'B is fast' might mean. Indeed, to say 'A is fast' would be to say that 'A is faster than most comparable things'. Similarly with 'A is greater than B' with the positive and negative integers. But 'is truer than' is, in Goodman's view, in an identical position. Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Page 4 of 26 Goodman's goal, in a sense, is to construct world descriptions in which useless predicates like 'is true', 'is simple', 'is confirmed', 'represents', 'is aesthetically good', etc., are replaced with useful comparative two place predicates such as 'is truer than', 'is simpler than', 'is better confirmed than', 'better represents than', 'is aesthetically better than', etc. 2. A world, then, becomes a system for progressive testing of what is truer than what, what is righter than what or what fits better than what and hence for the remaking of that world itself. Goodman even speaks favorably of Peirce's dictum that 'rightness' (and hence truth) is 'ultimate acceptability', but we have no guarantee that anything satisfies the predicate. "The many stuffs ... that worlds are made of are made along with the worlds. But made from what? Not from nothing, but from other worlds. Worldmaking as we know it always starts from worlds already on hand; the making is a remaking."2 Hence, not only is truth relative to a world description but relative within it as well (WWM, page 123): truth is what our tests within a world relatively measure (WWM, page 122), an 'operational' account of truth. In general, all 'stable properties' such as 'is true', 'is aesthetic', 'is fast', 'is large' and so forth must be defined in terms of 'ephemeral function', not the reverse. (WWM, page 70) (We are never faced, for example, with a choice twixt using 'green' or 'grue'. Rather, we are habituated to using 'green' and should have to have a good reason within our world to switch to 'grue', but we shan't have one.) 3. "Knowing cannot be exclusively or even primarily a matter of determining what is true. Discovery often amounts, as when I place a piece in a jigsaw puzzle, not to arrival at a proposition for declaration or defense, but to finding a fit." (WWM, page 121) 2 Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, 1978), page 129. [Referred to hereafter as WWM] Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Page 5 of 26 "The distinction between true and false falls far short of marking the general distinction twixt right and wrong versions." (WWM, page 109): compare with Heidegger.) "...truth cannot be the only consideration in choosing among statements or versions ... even where there is no conflict, truth is far from sufficient. Some truths are trivial, irrelevant, unintelligible, or redundant; to broad, too narrow, too boring, too bizarre, too complicated ..." (WWM, pages 120 and 121) 5. Introduction to Goodman's comparative position in history of philosophy since Kant: A. Kant: the important presuppositions of judging truly: (a) are themselves judgments; (b) are synthetic a priori; (c) are unchangeable; and (d) can be known by considering the constraints on how we may and may not judge; B. Heidegger: agrees with Kant that judging truly entails a prior presuppositions but insists that the constraints on judging truly are only one among the many constraints that constrain us, for we do many things other than judge (we build things, for example, use tools, engage in political activities and so forth). Hence, the presuppositions of human being (Dasein): Nelson Goodman's 'Theory of Symbols': an Exposition and Critique Page 6 of 26 (a) are broader than judgments (including all presuppositions of authentic being, whether judging, hammering, campaigning, etc.); (b) are thus called 'existentials'; (c) are knowable a priori; and (d) are unchangeable; C.
Recommended publications
  • On the Epistemological Significance of Aesthetic Values in Architectural Theory
    On the Epistemological Significance of Aesthetic Values in Architectural Theory by Ritu Bhatt Master of Architecture (1993) Kansas State University Bachelor of Architecture (1990) University of Roorkee, India Submitted to the Department of Architecture in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Architecture: History and Theory of Architecture at the T yTT Massachusetts Institute of Technology January, 2000 @ 2000 Ritu Bhatt. All rights reserved The author hereby grants to MIT permission to reproduce and to distribute publicly paper and electronic copies of this thesis document in whole or in part. Signature of Author...................................................................... Department of Architecture January 7, 2000 C ertified b . ... .................... .. tanrord A son ark Jarzo Professor of History and Assoc. Pro essor of History and Architecture Architecture Thesis Co- Supervisor Thesis Co- Supervisor Accepted by................................. V ... - ........ Stanford Anderson Chairman, Department Committee on Graduate Students Thesis Readers Professor Stanford Anderson Professor of History and Architecture Head, Department of Architecture, MIT Professor Mark Jarzombek Associate Professor of History and Architecture, MIT Professor Sibel Bozdogan Adjunct Professor, Graduate School of Design, Harvard University Professor Diane Ghirardo Professor of Architecture, University of Southern California Professor Satya P. Mohanty Professor of English, Cornell University Professor Catherine
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of Nelson Goodman's Aesthetics: Music As Process
    PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research & Ideas Volume 1 Number 1 Article 6 2020 A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process William S. Gilbert University of North Florida, [email protected] Faculty Mentor: Sarah Mattice, PhD, Associate Professor Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies This paper was a co-winner of the Philosophy Program's 2019-2020 Paper Prize. Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/pandion_unf Part of the Comparative Philosophy Commons, and the Esthetics Commons Recommended Citation Gilbert, William S. (2020) "A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process," PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research and Ideas: Vol. 1 : No. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/pandion_unf/vol1/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Scholarship at UNF Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in PANDION: The Osprey Journal of Research & Ideas by an authorized administrator of UNF Digital Commons. For more information, please contact Digital Projects. © 2020 All Rights Reserved A Critique of Nelson Goodman’s Aesthetics: Music As Process Cover Page Footnote The advice and mentorship offered by Dr. Sarah Mattice was absolutely critical in not only the essays development but also my development as a student and thinker. Her feedback and generosity with time in meetings is something I am deeply grateful for. Dr. Jean Miller of Virginia Tech is also responsible for highly valuable suggestions for a much needed revision. I am very grateful for her advice. Finally I would like to thank Jason Simpson of the UNF Writing Center.
    [Show full text]
  • Nelson Goodman's Arguments Against Perspective: a Geometrical
    Branko Mitroviü Research Department of Architecture Nelson Goodman’s Arguments Against Unitec Institute of Technology Carrington Rd., Mt Albert Perspective: A Geometrical Analysis Auckland, NEW ZEALAND Presented at Nexus 2012: Relationships Between Architecture [email protected] and Mathematics, Milan, 11-14 June 2012 Keywords: Nelson Goodman, Abstract. Nelson Goodman’s highly influential book perspective theory, geometry of Languages of Art argued that that all visual experience is perspective, Ernst Gombrich, merely a cultural construct. In presenting his thesis Goodman Erwin Panofsky relied on a series of geometrical arguments intended to show that the geometrical construction of perspective does not rely on the geometry of light rays. In this article I analyze the geometrical validity of Goodman's arguments. Introduction For the past fifty years few books by English-speaking philosophers have exercised a greater influence on art- and architectural history than Nelson Goodman’s Languages of Art [1968]. This book was an important contribution to the rise of cultural relativism that subsequently came to dominate the English-speaking humanities for decades. Goodman adopted the view (previously advocated by Ernst Gombrich in his book Art and Illusion [1960]) that “there is no innocent eye” and that the totality of an individual’s perception is predetermined by and a result of that person’s conceptual framework.1 Unlike Gombrich, however, Goodman inferred that, since our conceptual frameworks derive from the cultures we live in, all we can know and perceive is a result of our cultural background; he consequently argued that reality itself was but a cultural construct.2 According to this view, there are no facts that constitute the world independent of human cognitive apparatus.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Benacerraf a Goodman-Lewis
    How to Benacerraf a Goodman-Lewis This paper offers a limited defense of the thesis Nelson Goodman labels “nominalism,” according to which there are no distinct entities constructed from the same basic entities. Goodmanian nominalism-- “gnominalism,” for short—bears an uncertain relation to more familiar nominalist theses, but, according to Goodman, anti-gnominalism is simply “incomprehensible.” Unfortunately, as many commentators have noted, Goodman offers frustratingly little in the way of arguments for gnominalism. The present reassessment of gnominalism argues that Goodman is right to claim that theories violating gnominalism incur a distinctive theoretical vice. At the same time, the glaring lack of arguments for gnominalism indicate that something has gone badly wrong. Roughly speaking, Goodman’s support for gnominalism mistakes the symptom for the disease. This is because the vice of anti-gnominalist theories is that they are uniformly susceptible to variations on the Non-Uniqueness Problem that Paul Benacerraf presents for set- theoretic reductions. Gnominalism can therefore be motivated as a response to the Non-Uniqueness Problem. For this reason, would-be gnominalists like David Lewis are best served to argue against contested posits by showing these posits to yield Non-Uniqueness Problems given the existence of distinct entities constructed from the basic entities. To this end, after explaining gnominalism and its connection to the Non-Uniqueness Problem, I discuss how Lewis’ version of gnominalism departs from Goodman’s own. I then argue that a Non-Uniqueness Problem arises for those who posit structural universals—the leading target of Lewis’ gnominalism. (Word Count: 4284) §1. Introduction Two conceptions of nominalism are commonly distinguished when discussing debates between nominalists and platonists.1 The first kind of nominalism denies the existence of universals and holds, instead, that all entities are particulars rather than general entities like universals.
    [Show full text]
  • Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-1999 Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Aesthetics On-Line (1999). Permalink. © 1999 Curtis Carter. Used with permission. Nelson Goodman Remembered Curtis Carter The American philosopher Nelson Goodman died on November 25, 1998, in Needham, Massachusetts, at the age of 92. He was buried in a family grave site in Everett, Massachusetts. His wife, Katharine Sturgis Goodman, preceded him in death in 1996. Born on August 7, 1906 in Sommerville, Massachusetts, Goodman became a leading proponent of analytic philosophy in the United States and his theories are now studied throughout the world. Goodman was a Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University from 1968-1977. Previously he served as Harry Austryn Wolfson Professor of Philosophy at Brandeis University from 1964-67, Professor of Philosophy from 1951-1964 and Associate Professor from 1946- 1951 at the University of Pennsylvania, and Instructor in Philosophy at Tufts College, 1944- 1945. Prior to these appointments Goodman was Director of the Walker-Goodman Art Gallery in Boston from 1929 to 1941. From 1942 to 1945 he performed military service in the United States Army. He received his B.S. in 1928 (Phi Beta Kappa, Magna cum laude) and his Ph.D. in 1941, both from Harvard University. Goodman’s interests ranged from philosophy to collecting art. Within philosophy, Goodman’s writing and teaching were
    [Show full text]
  • John Cage, Gilles Deleuze, and the Idea of Sound Iain
    John Cage, Gilles Deleuze, and the Idea of Sound Iain Campbell [draft only, final version published in parallax, 23:3, 361-378, DOI:10.1080/13534645.2017.1343785] Across John Cage’s writings there is one moment to which he would often return, posing it as a turning point, a kind of singular epiphany in his thought and work. This is his famous visit to an anechoic chamber, and the consequent ‘discovery’ of his concept of silence. Describing his visit to the chamber, an environment designed to have as little acoustic resonance as possible and as such to be as silent as possible, Cage recounts hearing two sounds, one low and one high. Asking the engineer what these sounds were, Cage was told that the former was the sound of his blood in circulation, the latter his nervous system in operation. What Cage takes from this is that there can be no genuine silence, that ‘until I die there will be sounds’.1 This in turn entails a conception of sound wherein it is not defined simply by its analytical characteristics, but also by how it necessarily exceeds intentionality, of both composer and of listener. This is the basis for Cage’s often-repeated but obscure claim that the function of art is to ‘imitate Nature in her manner of operation’,2 and by extension the other oft-repeated Cagean mantra of ‘let[ting] sounds be themselves’3 – two cornerstones of an understanding of art in which the certainty of a creative or observational standpoint cannot serve as its foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ontology of Technique As Explored Through the Early Work of Peter Eisenman
    On the (im)Possibility of Reading: The Ontology of Technique as Explored through the Early Work of Peter Eisenman The significance of the final form resides in its capacity to reveal its own origins. — Peter Eisenman ‘’The Futility of Objects” CHARLES CRAWFORD INTRODUCTION NewSchool of Architecture + Design Can a form in some manner “communicate” to a viewer the “intent” of its cre- ator? In the 1970’s and 1980’s many notable figures explored this question, the question Jorge Silvetti once referred to as “the problem of communication.” Aldo Rossi proposed a language of reductivist purity; Michael Graves a return to the familiar language of classicism; Robert Venturi and Denise Scott Brown a version of Populism; and Peter Eisenman proposed an experiment in pure syntax, devoid of cultural reference. This paper explores issues of ontology and technique and, hopefully, in that pro- cess, suggests a path by which we might connect both to tectonics. With his early work, most notably the houses, the CSULB Student Center and the Wexner Center, Peter Eisenman conducted an experiment in communication, attempting to produce architecture of linguistic structuralism. This attempt to incorporate Chomsky’s theory of syntax into a language of art possessed an inter- nal codification, which it was hoped would aide the viewer in “deconstructing” the process of composition. As Jeffery Kipnis writes, however, in “An Architecture Unbound:” Rather than ‘exposing’ an essential structure of (all) architectural possibility in an unambiguously accessible announcement of purely formal intentions, the suc- cess of the work, its architectural potency, seemed, paradoxically, to depend on ambiguity, on a deflection of readable intent.
    [Show full text]
  • Print This Article
    Aesthetic Experience, Mimesis and Testimony Roger W. H. Savage University of California Los Angeles Abstract In this article, I relate the demand that Paul Ricœur suggests mimesis places on the way we think about truth to the idea that the work of art is a model for thinking about testimony. By attributing a work’s epoché of reality to the work of imagination, I resolve the impasse that arises from attributing music, literature, and art’s distance from the real to their social emancipation. Examining the conjunction, in aesthetic experience, of the communicability and the exemplarity of a work reveals how Ricœur’s definition of mimesis as refiguration relates to the “rule” that the work summons. This “rule” constitutes the solution to a problem or question for which the work is the answer. In conclusion, as a model for thinking about testimony, the claims that works make have a counterpart in the injunctions that issue from exemplary moral and political acts. Keywords: Aesthetic experience, Mimesis, Judgment, Testimony Résumé Dans cet article, j’établis un lien entre l’exigence que, selon Paul Ricœur,la mimèsis place dans notre façon de penser la vérité, et l’idée que l’œuvre d’art est un modèle pour penser le témoignage. Appliquant l’époché de la réalité à l’oeuvre d’imagination, j’évite l’impasse qui se dresse lorsqu’on attribue la musique, la littérature et la distance artistique du réel à leur émancipation sociale. L’étude de la conjonction du caractère communicable et exemplaire d’une œuvre – dans l’expérience esthétique - met en lumière la relation que la définition par Ricœur de la mimésis comme refiguration établit avec la “règle” que l’œuvre convoque.
    [Show full text]
  • On Freeing Aesthetic Emotions
    Inside-Out or Outside-In? On Freeing Aesthetic Emotions Gerald Moshammer and Barbara Ekamp Introduction In their seminal Dialectic of Enlightenment, Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno drastically portray the scientific usurpation of the human sphere: That they [the behaviorists] apply to human beings the same formulae and results which they wring without restraint from defenseless animals in their abominable physiological laboratories, proclaims the difference in an especially subtle way. The conclusion they draw from the mutilated animal bodies applies, not to animals in freedom, but to human beings today. By mistreating animals they announce that they, and only they in the whole of creation, function voluntarily in the same mechanical blind, automatic way as the twitching movements of the bound victims made use of by the expert.1 Immanuel Kant famously defined the Enlightenment as emancipation from superstition. He argued in the name of science, that is, natural laws. Yet, against the backdrop of his diagnosis, Kant equally undertook an immense dialectic effort to expose ethical reasoning and aesthetic experience as autonomous islands in the sea of blind natural forces. The Neo-Marxists Adorno and Horkheimer do not subscribe to such a sharp contrast between nature and deontic rationality or aesthetic imagination. They, however, follow Kant in not selling out to science every gram of the human soul. They note, “art, morality, and sublime love are masks of nature, in which nature reappears transformed and becomes expressive as its own antithesis. Through its masks it acquires the gift of speech; in its distortion it manifests its essence; beauty is the serpent which displays the wound where once the fang was implanted.”2 The behaviorists, on the contrary, are Gerald Moshammer is an Assistant Professor and Barbara Ekamp a Lecturer at Mahidol University International College, Thailand.
    [Show full text]
  • British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, and the Origins of Analytic Aesthetics
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 4 200 YEARS OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY Article 12 2008 British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, And The Origins Of Analytic Aesthetics Chinatsu Kobayashi Université du Québec à Montréal Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Kobayashi, Chinatsu (2008) "British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, And The Origins Of Analytic Aesthetics," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 4. https://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.136 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. British Idealist Aesthetics 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of two, Bernard Bosanquet and Robin Collingwood appear, therefore, to Cognition, Logic and Communication be the only idealist aestheticians of significance in the first half of the twentieth century.4 Of the two, Collingwood knew more about art5 and August 2009 Volume 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy was by far more original, as he produced a philosophy of art that truly pages 1-40 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.136 engaged with the artistic preoccupations of his days in The Principles of Art (Collingwood 1938). Among the ‘realists’, the topic was hardly more popular: only Samuel Alexander and E.
    [Show full text]
  • The Closure of Experience Kant, Goodman, and the Aesthetic Approach Hanno Birken-Bertsch
    The closure of experience Kant, Goodman, and the aesthetic approach Hanno Birken-Bertsch ant ends traditional epistemology and founds the aesthetic approach. - K One can say that epistemology is supposed to investigate how an appearance comes about. »Appearance« is one of the key words in Kant. A table, for example, is an appearance for you and me. Epistemology asks how it comes about that we see this table. The point is that one cannot explain the table by something that is not, like the table, an appearance. This insight is the end of epistemology and the beginning of aesthetics. Or, to avoid confusion, it is better to speak of »the aesthetic approach«, although I am not altogether satisfied with this phrase. For the aesthetic approach, our world consists of experience. Our task is to find out what follows from this starting point. 1. K ant’s aesthetics We are focusing on the first critique, the Critique o f Pure Reason, in the first edition, which was published in 1781. This book is - among other things - an intersection of two approaches, the epistemological and the aesthetic. Two ways of theorizing cross in the book, and their models of thought are intertwined. Kant inherits epistemology and founds the aesthetic approach. The relevant text for both is a chapter in the Critique o f Pure Reason, entitled »Transcendental Aesthetics«. Why is it called »Aesthetics«? In ancient Greek aisthesis means perception, and »Aesthetics« is thus concerned with what relates to aisthesis. Following the idea of the word Kant deals with perception and sensibility. In a footnote he even complains about those who use the word »aesthetics« to refer to a philosophy of art or the beautiful.
    [Show full text]
  • Demystification of the “Innocent Eye”: Nelson Goodman, Ernst H
    / 71 Demystification of the “Innocent Eye”: Nelson Goodman, Ernst H. Gombrich, and the Limitation of Conventionalism BOWEN WANG Abstract oth literary and artistic historiography has been devoted to exploring the basic Brelationship between the real world and the work of art, from the mimetic theories of Plato and Aristotle to the contemporary theorists, i.e. Nelson Goodman and Ernst H. Gombrich. Their attempts to probe into the nature of pictorial representation mainly respond to two questions: What is the relationship between representation and that it is to represent (between picture and reality)? What is the mechanism of, or in an ontological sense, what is representation? Guided by these two questions, my article will critically investigate the models of Goodman’s and Gombrich’s representation theory on account of convention rather than resemblance, expression, or imitation. Keywords: representation; conventionalism; Goodman; Gombrich; innocent eye The mimetic theory of representation presupposes a fundamental distinction between the visual/pictorial and the verbal/linguistic representation. The former, as formulated by Plato in his Republic at the beginning of western philosophy, is determined by the resemblance of the perceptible world through the copying or imitating act of the absolute Form in the Ideal world (63), whereas the mechanism of language operates in the Saussurean sort of “semantically significant structures” (Hyman and Bantinaki) based on a system of socio-cultural conventions. In the latter part of the twentieth century, however, Nelson Goodman and Ernest H. Gombrich have substantially challenged this division and the Platonic theory of representation behind it. They argue for a conventionalist view that all pictorial representation is conventional, which implies that the art itself like philosophy and science can be viewed as a cognitive way of understanding and a creative process of shaping the reality, rather than a mode of mimesis or imitation.
    [Show full text]