Computers, Visualization and the Nature of Reasoning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Computers, Visualization and the Nature of Reasoning Computers, visualization, and the nature of reasoning Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy1 The computer is bringing about a revolution in our understanding of inference, representation, and reasoning, some of the most fundamental no- tions of logic. The revolution is far from complete, but we think the direction is clear enough. In this article we describe how the computer led the two of us first to change the way we teach elementary logic, and eventually to re- think basic assumptions about the subject matter of our discipline. We think the story is a remarkable case study of the synergy between teaching, technol- ogy, and research. 1 Some autobiography Our story begins in 1983 when we both returned to Stanford from teaching at other universities. Elementary logic instruction is part of the bread-and-but- ter teaching in Stanford’s philosophy department, as it is in most philosophy departments. There is a difference, though, because Stanford has a long tradi- tion of using computers in logic instruction. This dates back to the late 1960’s, when Patrick Suppes introduced his program Valid into Philosophy 57, Stanford’s elementary logic course. This program ran on a mainframe com- puter devoted to nothing else, and provided students with an entire course of instruction in introductory logic. Like most logic courses offered from the 60’s through the 80’s, it focused on teaching the basic syntactic rules of proof in a formal calculus. Unlike most, it covered the subject in considerable depth, delving into axiomatic systems of some sophistication. 1The programs described in this paper were conceived by the authors, but would never have be- come realities without the design and programming talents of Gerry Allwein, Dave Barker- Plummer, Kalpana Bharadwaj, Alan Bush, Doug Felt, Dan Fish, Christopher Fuselier, Bill Graham, Mark Greaves, Adrian Klein, Mike Lenz, Steve Loving, Eric Ly, Atty Mullins, Pete Murray, Mark Ravaglia, Xin Wei Sha, Jason Strober, Rolf van Widenfelt, and Rick Wong. Financial support was received from Stanford University’s Faculty Author Development Program and Center for the Study of Language and Information, and from Indiana University’s Visual Inference Laboratory. 1 Over the years, thousands of Stanford students learned logic from Valid. While one section of Philosophy 57 was always “person taught”—for computer-phobic students—the bulk of elementary logic instruction was shouldered by Suppes’ pioneering program. This freed most of the Stanford philosophy faculty from the burden of teaching elementary logic. In particu- lar, the two of us could teach more advanced and interesting logic courses. That first year we taught courses in computability (Turing machines, recur- sive functions, undecidablity) and mathematical logic (truth, models, sound- ness, completeness). In the winter of 1984, the same year we returned to Stanford, Apple Computer introduced its Macintosh. The graphical capabilities of the Macintosh immediately captured our imagination as a way to solve some ba- sic pedagogical problems we had encountered in these logic courses. One problem in teaching computability had to do with Turing machines, a model of computation developed in the thirties by the famous logician Alan Turing, and a fundamental notion in theoretical computer science. The problem was the difficulty of giving students a real sense of the power of Turing machines. Since Turing machines get extremely complicated extremely fast, the only ex- ercises we could assign (and have any hope of grading) were toy problems that called for the construction of very simple machines. And even with these simple machines students often failed to get them right, due to the difficulty of verifying that a particular machine did what it was supposed to do. For many students the gap between the problems they could hope to solve with pencil and paper and the evident power of the modern computer made many claims in the course seem far-fetched. For example, students were led to ac- cept Church’s Thesis, the claim that Turing machines can compute any func- tion that can be calculated by mechanical or algorithmic means, more on the basis of our authority than on the basis of their own appreciation of the in- credible power of these machines. The problem in mathematical logic was of a very different sort. In our classes many students who had been quite successful in constructing proofs using Valid, students who should have understood the symbolic language in which those proofs were couched, in fact had great difficulty grasping the very intuitive notion of truth in a structure. This lack of understanding evidenced itself repeatedly. For example, students would make egregious errors in translating between sentences of English and sentences of first-order logic, er- rors that would have been inconceivable had they really understood the meanings of both sentences. The Macintosh’s graphical capabilities inspired us to tackle these prob- lems in a new way. We envisioned tools that would facilitate the student’s ability to visualize the abstract subject matter of logic, and thereby work more effectively with it. Over the next four years, funded by Stanford’s Faculty 2 Author Development project, we worked with teams of student program- mers to develop programs we called Turing’s World [2] and Tarski’s World [3]. As hoped, these programs have been extremely successful in addressing the pedagogical problems at which they were aimed. What we did not expect, however, was that they would lead us to rethink the conceptual foundations of our subject. In order to explain this second result, we need to briefly de- scribe the programs. Turing’s World Introduced by Alan Turing in 1936, Turing machines are one of the key ab- stractions used in modern computability theory, the study of what computers can and cannot do. A Turing machine is a particularly simple model of the digital computer, one whose operations are limited to reading and writing symbols on a linear tape, or moving along the tape to the left or right. The tape is marked off into squares, each of which can be filled with at most one symbol. At any given point in its operation, the Turing machine can read or write on only one of these squares, the square located directly below its “read/write” head. In Turing’s World the tape is represented by a narrow window that sits at the bottom of the screen. Figure 1 shows the tape with a series of A’s and B’s written on it, and with the read/write head located on the leftmost of these symbols. Figure 1: A tape from Turing’s World. A Turing machine has a finite number of states and is in exactly one of these states at any given time. Associated with these states are instructions telling the machine what action to perform if it is currently scanning a partic- ular symbol, and what state to go into after performing this action. The states of a Turing machine are generally represented by a “flow” or “state” diagram, using circles for the states and labeled arcs for the instructions associated with those states. For example, Figure 2 shows the state diagram of a Turing machine with just two states. 3 Figure 2: A simple Turing machine. The linguistic description of this same machine would be given as fol- lows: In state 0: if you see an A, move right and go into state 0. In state 0: if you see a B, move right and go into state 1. In state 1: if you see a B, move right and go into state 1. or, in abbreviated “4-tuple” notation: 0, A, R, 0 0, B, R, 1 1, B, R, 1 This machine will run down a string of A’s and B’s, stopping at the first A it sees after a B. For example, if run on the sample tape above, it would stop when it got to the fourth symbol from the left, because it would then be in state 1 with no instructions about what to do next. In Turing’s World, a collection of graphical tools lets you design Turing machines by directly drawing their state diagrams. When you run a Turing machine in Turing’s World, the operation of the machine is displayed graph- ically, both on the tape and in the state diagram window. On the tape, the read/write head moves, making the changes required by the machine you’ve designed. In the state diagram, the nodes and arcs highlight to show the changing state of the computation. Turing’s World also allows students to display the text-based “4-tuple” description of their machines, though we have found that they rarely do. Despite their simplicity, Turing machines can be designed to compute remarkably complex functions. In fact, they are generally thought to be as 4 powerful (in theory) as any possible computer. Finding out what they can do is half the fun of studying computability. Figure 3 shows part of the detail of a Turing machine that adds two numbers expressed in decimal notation. Figure 3: A Turing machine for adding in base 10. The ability to design a Turing machine by simply drawing its state dia- gram, combined with the ability to run the machine and watch it go through its transitions, is a powerful aid in the student’s understanding of the intu- itive idea of a Turing machine. By allowing students to introduce subma- chines (as illustrated in Figure 3), the program lets them quickly build up a powerful arsenal of Turing machines and to combine them in important ways. In our classes we now routinely ask students to design a Universal Turing machine, a machine that acts as a fully programmable computer.
Recommended publications
  • Logical Consequence Philosophy of Logic and Language — HT 2017-18
    Lecture 7: Logical Consequence Philosophy of Logic and Language — HT 2017-18 Jonny McIntosh [email protected] Works by Tarski The main text by Tarski this week is ’On the Concept of Logical Consequence’; ’Truth and Proof’ is a very accessible presentation, written much later: Alfred Tarski (1936) ’On the Concept of Logical Consequence’ in his (1983) Logic, Se- mantics, Metamathematics, 2nd revised edition (Hackett). — (1969) ‘Truth and Proof’ in Scientific American 220, pp. 63-77. Secondary Reading Starred items (*) are more introductory, and good places to start. Coffa (1991) traces the historical roots of Tarski’s account of logical consequence (among other things). Quine attacks the analytic/synthetic distinction in his (1951) and defends a version of the sub- stitutional conception in his (1986). For more discussion of formality, see in particular Etchemendy (1983) and Macfarlane (2000). Etchemendy (2008) is the best place to start for his objections, though see his (1990/1999) for extended discussion. For responses, see McGee (1992), Sher (1996), Hanson (1997), Gomez-Torrente´ (1999), Soames (1999), and Paseau (2013). *JC Beall and Greg Restall (2005/2013) ’Logical Consequence’ in E. Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-consequence/ *Patricia Blanchette (2001) ‘Logical Consequence’ in L. Goble, ed. The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic (Blackwell). J. Alberto Coffa (1991) The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap, ed. by Linda Wessels (CUP). John Etchemendy (1983) ‘The Doctrine of Logic as Form’ in Linguistics and Philosophy 6(3), 319334. John Etchemendy (1988) ‘Tarski on Truth and Logical Consequence’ in The Journal of Symbolic Logic 53(1), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Liar: an Essay in Truth and Circularity, by Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy, Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford, 1987, Xii + 185 Pp., $19.95
    216 BOOK REVIEWS BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 20, Number 2, April 1989 ©1989 American Mathematical Society 0273-0979/89 $1.00 + $.25 per page The Liar: An essay in truth and circularity, by Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy, Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford, 1987, xii + 185 pp., $19.95. ISBN 0-19-505072-x Consider the classic Liar sentence: "This sentence is false." It claims that it is false. So if we assume that a sentence is true if and only if what it claims is the case, then the Liar is true if and only if it is false. People have thought about this paradox for centuries. Despite this, there is no single standard "solution." An attempted resolution of the paradox would tell us which of our intuitions are sound and which need further clarification. It would point out where and why our naive reasoning leads us to a contradiction. Modern logic applies mathematical methods to the modeling and study of truth, proof, computation, and infinity. The paradoxes of semantics and set theory were important in the development of the field. The reason for working on the paradoxes of any field is not only to secure a foundation. The deeper reason is that by introducing, discarding, and clarifying the concepts that lead to paradox we are lead to the central ideas and questions of the field. We see from The Liar that the paradoxes are still a source of inspiration in logic. The book is a new, exciting contribution to the study of truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Course Description Textbook LANGUAGE, PROOF and LOGIC by Jon Barwise & John Etchemendy, Text/Software Package (Eit
    INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC Philosophy 201_Summer 2011 LeeSun Choi 730: 201:H1 (Course Index: 91390) Email: [email protected] Scott Hall 219 Office: 1 Seminary Pl. Room 003 MTWThu 10:10 – 12:05 pm Office Hours: Thu 1 pm – 2:30 pm & by Appt Course Description We can find our and others’ thoughts as rational or irrational. What makes us do this? We can point out a gap in our thoughts, discover an assumption in our claims and examine the legitimacy of our inference and reasoning. These activities belong to logic. Roughly speaking, logic is about valid inference and reasoning in our thoughts. In order to analyze our thoughts and inference procedures, we need to have a technical language to express the thoughts and the procedures with clarity and rigor. We will study this technical language called First‐Order Logic (FOL) that helps us to disambiguate our use of natural languages, e.g. English, and prevents us from making logical errors in our arguments. In addition, FOL will allow us to formulate accurately the concept of truth, proof, and valid inference. FOL has been foundational in mathematics, computer science, and cognitive science as well as philosophy. We will be encouraged to apply our learning to other academic disciplines. This course has requirements of daily homework assignments as well as midterm and final exams. Logic is immensely accumulative. If you deviate from the track at any point, you cannot proceed to the next step. It is very important to attend every class and do all the weekly assignments. You are highly encouraged to come to the office hours with any questions and problems you have in this class.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanford University, News and Publication Service, Audiovisual Recordings Creator: Stanford University
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/c8dn43sv Online items available Guide to the Stanford News Service Audiovisual Recordings SC1125 Daniel Hartwig & Jenny Johnson Department of Special Collections and University Archives October 2012 Green Library 557 Escondido Mall Stanford 94305-6064 [email protected] URL: http://library.stanford.edu/spc Guide to the Stanford News SC1125 1 Service Audiovisual Recordings SC1125 Language of Material: English Contributing Institution: Department of Special Collections and University Archives Title: Stanford University, News and Publication Service, audiovisual recordings creator: Stanford University. News and Publications Service Identifier/Call Number: SC1125 Physical Description: 63 Linear Feetand 17.4 gigabytes Date (inclusive): 1936-2011 Information about Access The materials are open for research use. Audio-visual materials are not available in original format, and must be reformatted to a digital use copy. Ownership & Copyright All requests to reproduce, publish, quote from, or otherwise use collection materials must be submitted in writing to the Head of Special Collections and University Archives, Stanford University Libraries, Stanford, California 94305-6064. Consent is given on behalf of Special Collections as the owner of the physical items and is not intended to include or imply permission from the copyright owner. Such permission must be obtained from the copyright owner, heir(s) or assigns. See: http://library.stanford.edu/depts/spc/pubserv/permissions.html. Restrictions also apply to digital representations of the original materials. Use of digital files is restricted to research and educational purposes. Cite As [identification of item], Stanford University, News and Publication Service, Audiovisual Recordings (SC1125). Dept. of Special Collections and University Archives, Stanford University Libraries, Stanford, Calif.
    [Show full text]
  • Euler Diagrams As an Introduction to Set-Theoretical Models
    Euler diagrams as an introduction to set-theoretical models Ryo Takemura Nihon University 5-2-1 Kinuta, Setagaya-ku, Tokyo 157-8570, Japan [email protected] Abstract Understanding the notion of a model is not always easy in logic courses. Hence, tools such as Euler diagrams are frequently applied as informal illustrations of set-theoretical models. We formally investigate Euler diagrams as an introduction to set-theoretical models. We show that the model-theoretic notions of validity and invalidity are characterized by Euler diagrams, and, in particular, that model construction can be described as a manipulation of Euler diagrams. 1998 ACM Subject Classification I.2.0 Philosophical foundations Keywords and phrases Euler diagrams; Set-theoretical model; Counter-model 1 Introduction Logic is traditionally studied from the different viewpoints of syntax and semantics. From the syntactic viewpoint, formal proofs are investigated using proof systems such as natural deduction and sequent calculus. From the semantic viewpoint, set-theoretical models of sentences are usually investigated. In contrast to a proof, which shows the validity of a given inference, we usually disprove an inference by constructing a counter-model. A counter- model is one in which all premises of a given inference are true, but its conclusion is false. The notions of proofs and models are traditionally defined in the fundamentally different frameworks of syntax and semantics, respectively, and the completeness theorem, one of the most basic theorems of logic, provides a bridge between them. In university courses, logic is usually taught along such lines. As the notion of a proof appears naturally in mathematics courses, students are, to some extent, familiar with it.
    [Show full text]
  • 2007 a World at Risk Democracy Fellows the NEWSLETTER of FREEMAN SPOGLI INSTITUTE for INTERNATIONAL STUDIES
    THE NEWSLETTER OF THE FREEMAN SPOGLI INSTITUTE FOR INTERNATIONAL STUDIES inside: IMPROVING HEALTH AND GOVERNANCE P 2 winter issue INNOVATION IN CHINA P 6 KEEPING THE BOMB FROM IRAN P 7 OFFSHORE AQUACULTURE LEGISLATION P 10 2007 EU INTEGRATION AND INTERVENTION P 11 PEOPLE, BOOKS, PUBLICATIONS P 14 stanford university A WORLD AT RISK Freeman Spogli Institute’s Second Annual International Conference and Dinner “What has changed is not the risk, but the “As Stanford University’s primary forum number and complexity of problems that for the consideration of the major interna- face the world today. The challenges of tional issues of our time, we at FSI are the 21st century require that universities dedicated to interdisciplinary research and change. We must move beyond tradi- teaching on some of the most pressing tional academic boundaries and embrace and complex problems facing the global new ways of doing research.” – stanford community today.” – coit d. “chip” blacker, provost john w. etchemendy director, freeman spogli institute 1 On November 16, 2006, FSI convened its annual international conference, A World at Risk, devoted to systemic and human risk confronting the global community. Remarks by Stanford Provost John Etchemendy, FSI Director Coit Blacker, former Secretary of State Warren Christopher, former Secretary of Defense William Perry, and former Secretary of State George Shultz set the stage for stimulating discussions. Interactive panel sessions encouraged in-depth exploration of major issues with Stanford faculty, outside experts, and policymakers. HERE, AND ON PAGES 8 AND 9, ARE CONFERENCE HIGHLIGHTS “The Middle East has descended into hate, “We are facing new dangers and we must “The world has never been at a more violence, and chaos.
    [Show full text]
  • The University
    2009-10 STANFORD Men’S BASKETBALL THE UNIVERSITY WWW.GOSTANFORD.COM STanford men’S BASKETBALL 2009-10 MEDIA GUIDE 167 2009-10 STANFORD Men’S BASKETBALL THE UNIVERSITY For the Stanford’s on that day, the university was the ▼ Current Perspectives realization of a dream and a fitting tribute to the memory In other ways, the university has changed tremendously of their only son, who had died of typhoid fever weeks on its way to recognition as one of the world’s great before his sixteenth birthday. Far from the nation’s center universities. At the hub of a vital and diverse Bay Area, of culture and unencumbered by tradition or ivy, the new Stanford is less than hour’s drive south of San Francisco university drew students from all over the country: many and just a few minutes north of the Silicon Valley, an area from California; some who followed professors hired dotted with computer and high technology firms largely from other colleges and universities; and some simply spawned by the university’s faculty and graduates. seeking adventure in the West. Though there were On campus, students and faculty enjoy new libraries, Stanford University many difficulties during the first months – housing was modern laboratories, tremendous sports and recreation inadequate, microscopes and books were late in arriving facilities, and comfortable residences. Contemporary at a Glance from the East – the first year foretold of greatness. As sculpture, as well as pieces from the Stanford Museum’s Jane Stanford wrote in the summer of 1892, “Even our extensive collection of sculpture by Auguste Rodin, is On October 1, 1891, the 465 new students who were fondest hopes have been realized.” placed throughout the campus, providing unexpected pleasures at many turns.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stanford Senate Academic Council
    The Stanford Senate of the Academic Council Reflections on Fifty Years of Faculty Governance, 1968–2018 StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 1 3/4/18 11:54 AM StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 2 3/4/18 11:54 AM The Stanford Senate of the Academic Council Reflections on Fifty Years of Faculty Governance, 1968–2018 written, compiled, and edited by Peter Stansky Ethan W. Ris Susan W. Schofield Hans N. Weiler and Past Senate Chairs and Academic Secretaries with the assistance of the Stanford University News Service, Registrar’s Office, and University Archives published by the Stanford University Office of the Academic Secretary with the support of the Stanford Historical Society StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 3 3/4/18 11:54 AM StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 4 3/4/18 11:54 AM Robert W. Beyers. 1974 Dedicated to Robert W. Beyers, an intrepid newsman committed to the integrity of the press and to the effectiveness of faculty governance. Beyers served as the Information Officer for the Senate in its early years. This book was made possible through the generous support of the Robert & Charlotte Beyers Fund of the Stanford Historical Society. StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 5 3/4/18 11:54 AM Stanford University, Office of the Academic Secretary © 2018 by the Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or in any informa- tion storage or retrieval system without the prior written permission of the Stanford University Office of the Academic Secretary.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanford Institute for Human-Centered Artificial Intelligence
    2019–2020 ANNUAL REPORT Stanford Institute for Human-Centered Artificial Intelligence Find out how HAI is advancing AI research, education, policy, and practice to improve the human condition. Contents 1 Letter from the Co-Directors 2 By the Numbers RESEARCH 6 HAI Research Focus 7 Featured Projects 8 Grant Programs for AI Research 11 Stanford Digital Economy Lab Y POLICY 14 National Research Cloud 15 Featured Policy Activities A EDUCATION 19 Featured Programs P PEOPLE 20 Denning Co-Directors 21 Associate Directors 23 Staff 24 Faculty and Fellows 25 HAI Commitment to Action 26 Fellows 27 Advisory Council 28 Research Centers and Partners 30 Corporate Members Program 30 Philanthropic Support 31 Events 32 Financials Act. To round out the institute’s first year of operations, Letter from we introduced a range of multidisciplinary education programs focused on helping high-impact decision the Denning makers as well as future leaders respond thoughtfully to Co-Directors the social and ethical implications of AI. Artificial Intelligence will change lives in profound ways. We feel a collective responsibility to help guide this technology in a positive direction. To this end, in 2019 we founded the Stanford Institute for Human-Centered Artificial Intelligence (HAI) to advance AI research, education, policy, and practice to improve the human condition. We want to thank the many faculty and advisors who joined us in conceiving and creating the institute and helping to define its charter and scope. Our growing community of researchers, scholars, fellows, students, and partners brings true diversity of thought to the critical question of how AI will affect our society.
    [Show full text]
  • Join Stanford Women's Basketball Boosters!
    Stanford University Stanford University at a Glance n October 1, 1891, the 465 new students who Owere on hand for opening day ceremonies at Leland Stanford Junior University greeted Leland and Jane For the Stanford’s on that day, the university was the Current Perspectives Stanford enthusiastically, with a chant they had made up realization of a dream and a fitting tribute to the memory In other ways, the university has changed tremendously of their only son, who had died of typhoid fever weeks on its way to recognition as one of the world’s great and rehearsed only that morning. Wah-hoo! Wah-hoo! before his sixteenth birthday. Far from the nation’s center universities. At the hub of a vital and diverse Bay Area, of culture and unencumbered by tradition or ivy, the Stanford is less than hour’s drive south of San Francisco L-S-J-U! Stanford! Its wild and spirited tone symbolized new university drew students from all over the country: and just a few minutes north of the Silicon Valley, an many from California; some who followed professors area dotted with computer and high technology firms the excitement of this bold adventure. As a pioneer faculty hired from other colleges and universities; and some largely spawned by the university’s faculty and graduates. simply seeking adventure in the West. Though there were On campus, students and faculty enjoy new libraries, member recalled, “Hope was in every heart, and the many difficulties during the first months – housing was modern laboratories, tremendous sports and recreation inadequate, microscopes and books were late in arriving facilities, and comfortable residences.
    [Show full text]
  • Tarski, Truth, and Semantics
    Tarski, Truth, and Semantics Richard G. Heck, Jr. 1 Opening No one denies that Tarski made a major contribution to one particular problem about truth, namely, the resolution of the semantic paradoxes—although, of course, there is disagreement about whether he provided the correct solution. But some philosophers have suggested that Tarski also made a significant contribution to an- other project, that of providing semantic theories for natural languages. Hartry Field (2001), for example, credits Tarski with transforming the problem of reduc- ing truth to physicalistically acceptable notions into that of reducing “primitive denotation”. And Donald Davidson (1984c) founded an entire approach to seman- tics by arguing that a theory of meaning for a language may take the form of a Tarskian definition of truth. But, according to John Etchemendy Etchemendy (1988),1 in so far as Tarski’s work does contribute to empirical semantics, this “is little more than a fortuitous accident”. There are both conceptual and historical issues here. The conceptual question is whether reading Tarski’s work on truth as it must be read, if it is to have any relevance to semantics, requires misunderstanding the character of his mathematical work. The historical question is whether Tarski intended his work to be so read. Etchemendy’s view is that Tarski was primarily concerned to resolve the semantic paradoxes. Yet the form his solution takes appears. to serve equally as a characteri- zation of the semantic properties of the language whose truth predicate is defined. However the appearance is actually quite misleading. In particular, it would be a mistake to construe Tarski as taking part in this latter, semantic project, since the two goals turn out to be in quite direct opposition to one another.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Modeled by Truth in All Models?∗
    What is Modeled by Truth in All Models?∗ John MacFarlane† March 23, 2000 Abstract John Etchemendy has argued that the model-theoretic definition of log- ical truth fails as a conceptual analysis of that notion. I will argue that Etchemendy’s criticism cuts deeper than recent critics have conceded. Prop- erly understood, it is directed against the underlying analysis of logical truth as truth on all possible semantic interpretations of a language’s nonlogical vocabulary, not against any particular mathematical realization of that anal- ysis. The only way to block Etchemendy’s argument is to reject his assump- tion that the possible semantic values for singular terms in an extensional language are the actually existing objects. In fact, a version of his argument goes through even if we retreat to the weaker assumption that the possible semantic values for singular terms are the possibly existing objects. I defend the model-theoretic analysis by arguing that there is a sense of “possible se- mantic value” for which both these assumptions are false. 1 Logical truth and truth in all models It is commonly thought that the best precise account of logical truth we have is the one given in model theory: a sentence S is logically true just in case it is true in every model.1 A model (for a first-order extensional language) consists in a nonempty set of objects—the domain—and an interpretation function that assigns ∗Talk delivered at the Pacific APA, Albuquerque, NM, April 8, 2000. †Department of Philosophy, University of California at Berkeley. E-mail: [email protected].
    [Show full text]