On the Possibility of a Privileged Class of Logical Terms

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On the Possibility of a Privileged Class of Logical Terms GREG RAY ON THE POSSIBILITYOF A PRIVILEGEDCLASS OF LOGICALTERMS* (Received 7 August 1995) INTRODUCTION Alfred Tarski's (1936) semantic account of the logical properties (logical consequence, logical truthand logical consistency) makes essential appeal to a distinction between logical and non-logical terms. John Etchemendy (1990) has recently argued that Tarski's accountis inadequatefor quite a numberof differentreasons. Among them is a brief argumentwhich purports to show thatTarski 's reliance on the distinctionbetween logical and non-logical terms is in prin- ciple mistaken.) According to Etchemendy,there are very simple (even first order) languages for which no such distinction can be made. This is a surprisingresult, and an importantone, if true. Since Tarski's account does indeed depend on such a distinction, Etchemendy'sargument, if correct, would rule out definitively the received view on logical truth(as well as logical consequence and logical consistency). But his argumentis not correct,and it is the job of this paperto show that. TARSKI'SACCOUNT Etchemendyargues for his claim by giving an exampleof a first-order languagethat is such that,no matterhow you divide up its termsinto "logical"and "non-logical",the applicationof Tarski'sdefinition of logical truth (or logical consequence) will give the wrong results. Before looking at this argumentin detail, it is importantto review how it is that Tarski'saccount of the logical propertiesdepends on making a distinctionbetween logical and non-logical terms. Philosophical Studies 81: 303-313, 1996. ? 1996 KluwerAcademic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. This content downloaded from 128.227.195.219 on Fri, 13 Dec 2013 12:06:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 304 GREGRAY (Dxy & Dyz )- Dxz s < .... ... > Figure 1. Relation between a formula'p and a sequence. Forease of exposition,we will focuson just logical truth. Tarski's definitionof logicaltruth is closelyrelated to his definitionof truth. In fact,Tarski's idea was thatdefinitions of all the logicalproperties can be obtainedsimply as an extendedapplication of the methods he usedin definingtruth. According to Tarski,a sentenceis truejust in case it is satisfiedby every sequence.For example,the formula '(Dxy & Dyz) -? Dxz' (read "If x is a descendent of y and y is a descendentof z, then x is a descendentof z") is satisfiedby the sequences justin case a certaintriplet of itemsin thatsequence have the rightsort of descendencyrelations. See Figure1. In particular, lettingf be a functionwhich tells us which variablesto associate with whichpositions in the sequence,we can give the satisfaction conditionof, say,just the subformula'Dxy' as follows. s satisfies 'Dxy' if andonly if thething in theposition f('x') of s is a descendent of the thingin positionf('y') of s. Notice thatthe satisfactioncondition I just gave presupposeda choice of a function,f, which assignsvariables of the languageto aninteger (representing a sequence position). We normally suppress thisparameter, and the reason it is alrightto do thatis thatit doesnot matterwhich such function we choose(so long as we stickwith it). Thereason any old suchfunction will do is thatthe functionhas no independentsignificance, it is purelyan artifact of therepresentation we have chosen, and representsnothing about the conceptbeing treated,in thiscase truth. The situationchanges, however, when we turnto a treatmentof logical truth.Again, Tarskiemploys the satisfactionrelation, but this time it is not the satisfactionbehavior of the targetsentence itselfthat matters. After all, if the targetsentence (call it ',o') is so muchas true,then its satisfactionbehavior will simplyconsist in its being satisfiedby all sequences.But it sharesthis distinctionwith This content downloaded from 128.227.195.219 on Fri, 13 Dec 2013 12:06:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LOGICALTERMS 305 (Dab & Dbc) - Dac F~~~~~~~~~ (Xxy & XYZ ) XXZ f <' f >1 Figure 2. Relationbetween a formulaF(p) and a sequence. all true sentences. So, the satisfactionbehavior of p by itself cannot be a distinguishingmark of p's logical truth. Instead, on Tarski's account, ,o'slogical truthis markedby the satisfactionbehavior of a formulawhich can be obtainedfrom o by substitution,namely that formulawhich resultsfrom applyinga special replacementfunction, F, which maps each term of the language either onto itself or onto an extra-linguisticvariable. See Figure 2. Forexample, the sentence '(Dab & Dbc) -? Dac' will be said to be logically truejust in case every sequencesatisfies this new hybridfor- mula '(xxy & Xyz) -- xxz'. Notice, then,that the treatmentof logical truthpresupposes a choice of two functions.We still have the func- tion, f, from variablesto positions in sequences,just as we did in the case of truth.But we also now have the functionF which determines what termsof the originalsentence get replacedby variablesprior to evaluation. While this additionalparameter is likewise suppressed in modem presentationsof the Tarskianor model-theoreticaccount of logical truth,this is not because the choice of function F doesn't matterto the outcome. It does matter,and, moreover,the functionF does representsomething about the notion(s) we are treating.F must divide the logical terms from the non-logical terms. In particular, F must slate all and only non-logical termsfor replacementwith extra-linguisticvariables. Call a replacementfunction which meets this condition, a logical termfunction. Why does Tarski'saccount, which relies crucially on a choice of replacementfunction, F, also requirethat F be a logical term function?Here is one way to moti- vate this requirement.The following argumentseeks to establish This content downloaded from 128.227.195.219 on Fri, 13 Dec 2013 12:06:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 306 GREG RAY an appropriatelyclose relationbetween Tarskianlogical truthand a certainintuitive characterization of logical truth. Let F (p) be the formulathat results from applyinga replacement function,F, to a sentence p. Now, it can be shown (thoughI will not do so here) that, if the formulaF(o) is satisfiedby every sequence, then the original sentence p is true. Put somewhat differently,the truthof o is determinedby the satisfactionbehavior of the formula F(p). Now, if F is also a logical term function, then it is also the case that the satisfaction behavior of F(o) can in no way depend on the non-logical terms of po,since, of course, these will have all been replaced by variables in F(o). In short, if F is a logical term function, and F(o) is satisfied by every sequence, then the truth of o is determinedby the logical form of o independentlyof the particular importof any of its non-logical terms.2This is one good thing to mean by the time-honoredphrase "truein virtue of logical form",which has been used as a characterizationof logical truth. I have just presented an argument to the effect that Tarski's definitioncaptures one good sense of 'logically true', i.e. if Tarski's definitionapplies to a given sentence, then that sentence is a logical truth.But this argumentmakes crucial appealto a logical termfunc- tion, F. So, there had betterbe such functions for the languages the accountis supposedto cover. Thatis ,therehad betterbe a distinction between logical and non-logical terms for such languages. Tarski's definitionsof the other logical properties,logical consequence and logical consistency, likewise depend on this distinction.3In 1936 when Tarski formulatedhis account of the logical properties,he did not have any account to offer of what made a term logical or non-logical. Of course, one can pointto examples, but this is no sub- stitutefor giving a principlefor distinction.Thus, Tarskiconsidered his account incomplete in 1936.4 Tarski'saccount of the logical propertiespresupposes that there is a logical termfunction F. Consequently,Tarski's account depends on an existence claim, unsubstantiatedin 1936, to the effect that there exist logical term functions (for some broadclass of languages, i). Etchemendy'sargument would show thatthis crucialexistence claim is false. Etchemendy'saim is to show thatthere are very simple languages for which the distinctionbetween logical and non-logical termscan- This content downloaded from 128.227.195.219 on Fri, 13 Dec 2013 12:06:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions LOGICALTERMS 307 notbe madesuccessfully. That is notjust to say thatwe arenot sure how to drawthe distinctionin suchlanguages, but that no division of termswill makeTarskian consequences in the languagecorre- spondto the logical consequences.5Thus, Etchemendy holds that philosophersand logicianswho have workedtoward identifying a privilegedclass of logicalterms have been pursuing a chimera. THE "BULLET"ARGUMENT Let us takea closerlook at the argumentEtchemendy offers for his claim.First, we will needtwo closely-relatedlanguages with which to work.Following Etchemendy, let L be a very simplelanguage with two names('George Washington'and 'Abe Lincoln'),two predicates('was president'and 'has a beard'),three truth-functional oper- ations ('V', 'A' and '-1'), where all these terms have their usualmeaning. LetL* be a languagejust like L, exceptthere is, in addition, a binaryconnective, '*', withthe following truth condition for any sentencesfo and b of L*, r(( * '0)- is trueiff Lincolnhad a beardand either p is trueor , is true. Etchemendymakes his case,using these languages, in thefollowing way. [L*is] a languagein whichevery sentence is logicallyequivalent
Recommended publications
  • Logical Consequence Philosophy of Logic and Language — HT 2017-18
    Lecture 7: Logical Consequence Philosophy of Logic and Language — HT 2017-18 Jonny McIntosh [email protected] Works by Tarski The main text by Tarski this week is ’On the Concept of Logical Consequence’; ’Truth and Proof’ is a very accessible presentation, written much later: Alfred Tarski (1936) ’On the Concept of Logical Consequence’ in his (1983) Logic, Se- mantics, Metamathematics, 2nd revised edition (Hackett). — (1969) ‘Truth and Proof’ in Scientific American 220, pp. 63-77. Secondary Reading Starred items (*) are more introductory, and good places to start. Coffa (1991) traces the historical roots of Tarski’s account of logical consequence (among other things). Quine attacks the analytic/synthetic distinction in his (1951) and defends a version of the sub- stitutional conception in his (1986). For more discussion of formality, see in particular Etchemendy (1983) and Macfarlane (2000). Etchemendy (2008) is the best place to start for his objections, though see his (1990/1999) for extended discussion. For responses, see McGee (1992), Sher (1996), Hanson (1997), Gomez-Torrente´ (1999), Soames (1999), and Paseau (2013). *JC Beall and Greg Restall (2005/2013) ’Logical Consequence’ in E. Zalta, ed. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-consequence/ *Patricia Blanchette (2001) ‘Logical Consequence’ in L. Goble, ed. The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic (Blackwell). J. Alberto Coffa (1991) The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap, ed. by Linda Wessels (CUP). John Etchemendy (1983) ‘The Doctrine of Logic as Form’ in Linguistics and Philosophy 6(3), 319334. John Etchemendy (1988) ‘Tarski on Truth and Logical Consequence’ in The Journal of Symbolic Logic 53(1), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Liar: an Essay in Truth and Circularity, by Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy, Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford, 1987, Xii + 185 Pp., $19.95
    216 BOOK REVIEWS BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 20, Number 2, April 1989 ©1989 American Mathematical Society 0273-0979/89 $1.00 + $.25 per page The Liar: An essay in truth and circularity, by Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy, Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford, 1987, xii + 185 pp., $19.95. ISBN 0-19-505072-x Consider the classic Liar sentence: "This sentence is false." It claims that it is false. So if we assume that a sentence is true if and only if what it claims is the case, then the Liar is true if and only if it is false. People have thought about this paradox for centuries. Despite this, there is no single standard "solution." An attempted resolution of the paradox would tell us which of our intuitions are sound and which need further clarification. It would point out where and why our naive reasoning leads us to a contradiction. Modern logic applies mathematical methods to the modeling and study of truth, proof, computation, and infinity. The paradoxes of semantics and set theory were important in the development of the field. The reason for working on the paradoxes of any field is not only to secure a foundation. The deeper reason is that by introducing, discarding, and clarifying the concepts that lead to paradox we are lead to the central ideas and questions of the field. We see from The Liar that the paradoxes are still a source of inspiration in logic. The book is a new, exciting contribution to the study of truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Course Description Textbook LANGUAGE, PROOF and LOGIC by Jon Barwise & John Etchemendy, Text/Software Package (Eit
    INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC Philosophy 201_Summer 2011 LeeSun Choi 730: 201:H1 (Course Index: 91390) Email: [email protected] Scott Hall 219 Office: 1 Seminary Pl. Room 003 MTWThu 10:10 – 12:05 pm Office Hours: Thu 1 pm – 2:30 pm & by Appt Course Description We can find our and others’ thoughts as rational or irrational. What makes us do this? We can point out a gap in our thoughts, discover an assumption in our claims and examine the legitimacy of our inference and reasoning. These activities belong to logic. Roughly speaking, logic is about valid inference and reasoning in our thoughts. In order to analyze our thoughts and inference procedures, we need to have a technical language to express the thoughts and the procedures with clarity and rigor. We will study this technical language called First‐Order Logic (FOL) that helps us to disambiguate our use of natural languages, e.g. English, and prevents us from making logical errors in our arguments. In addition, FOL will allow us to formulate accurately the concept of truth, proof, and valid inference. FOL has been foundational in mathematics, computer science, and cognitive science as well as philosophy. We will be encouraged to apply our learning to other academic disciplines. This course has requirements of daily homework assignments as well as midterm and final exams. Logic is immensely accumulative. If you deviate from the track at any point, you cannot proceed to the next step. It is very important to attend every class and do all the weekly assignments. You are highly encouraged to come to the office hours with any questions and problems you have in this class.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanford University, News and Publication Service, Audiovisual Recordings Creator: Stanford University
    http://oac.cdlib.org/findaid/ark:/13030/c8dn43sv Online items available Guide to the Stanford News Service Audiovisual Recordings SC1125 Daniel Hartwig &amp; Jenny Johnson Department of Special Collections and University Archives October 2012 Green Library 557 Escondido Mall Stanford 94305-6064 [email protected] URL: http://library.stanford.edu/spc Guide to the Stanford News SC1125 1 Service Audiovisual Recordings SC1125 Language of Material: English Contributing Institution: Department of Special Collections and University Archives Title: Stanford University, News and Publication Service, audiovisual recordings creator: Stanford University. News and Publications Service Identifier/Call Number: SC1125 Physical Description: 63 Linear Feetand 17.4 gigabytes Date (inclusive): 1936-2011 Information about Access The materials are open for research use. Audio-visual materials are not available in original format, and must be reformatted to a digital use copy. Ownership & Copyright All requests to reproduce, publish, quote from, or otherwise use collection materials must be submitted in writing to the Head of Special Collections and University Archives, Stanford University Libraries, Stanford, California 94305-6064. Consent is given on behalf of Special Collections as the owner of the physical items and is not intended to include or imply permission from the copyright owner. Such permission must be obtained from the copyright owner, heir(s) or assigns. See: http://library.stanford.edu/depts/spc/pubserv/permissions.html. Restrictions also apply to digital representations of the original materials. Use of digital files is restricted to research and educational purposes. Cite As [identification of item], Stanford University, News and Publication Service, Audiovisual Recordings (SC1125). Dept. of Special Collections and University Archives, Stanford University Libraries, Stanford, Calif.
    [Show full text]
  • Euler Diagrams As an Introduction to Set-Theoretical Models
    Euler diagrams as an introduction to set-theoretical models Ryo Takemura Nihon University 5-2-1 Kinuta, Setagaya-ku, Tokyo 157-8570, Japan [email protected] Abstract Understanding the notion of a model is not always easy in logic courses. Hence, tools such as Euler diagrams are frequently applied as informal illustrations of set-theoretical models. We formally investigate Euler diagrams as an introduction to set-theoretical models. We show that the model-theoretic notions of validity and invalidity are characterized by Euler diagrams, and, in particular, that model construction can be described as a manipulation of Euler diagrams. 1998 ACM Subject Classification I.2.0 Philosophical foundations Keywords and phrases Euler diagrams; Set-theoretical model; Counter-model 1 Introduction Logic is traditionally studied from the different viewpoints of syntax and semantics. From the syntactic viewpoint, formal proofs are investigated using proof systems such as natural deduction and sequent calculus. From the semantic viewpoint, set-theoretical models of sentences are usually investigated. In contrast to a proof, which shows the validity of a given inference, we usually disprove an inference by constructing a counter-model. A counter- model is one in which all premises of a given inference are true, but its conclusion is false. The notions of proofs and models are traditionally defined in the fundamentally different frameworks of syntax and semantics, respectively, and the completeness theorem, one of the most basic theorems of logic, provides a bridge between them. In university courses, logic is usually taught along such lines. As the notion of a proof appears naturally in mathematics courses, students are, to some extent, familiar with it.
    [Show full text]
  • 2007 a World at Risk Democracy Fellows the NEWSLETTER of FREEMAN SPOGLI INSTITUTE for INTERNATIONAL STUDIES
    THE NEWSLETTER OF THE FREEMAN SPOGLI INSTITUTE FOR INTERNATIONAL STUDIES inside: IMPROVING HEALTH AND GOVERNANCE P 2 winter issue INNOVATION IN CHINA P 6 KEEPING THE BOMB FROM IRAN P 7 OFFSHORE AQUACULTURE LEGISLATION P 10 2007 EU INTEGRATION AND INTERVENTION P 11 PEOPLE, BOOKS, PUBLICATIONS P 14 stanford university A WORLD AT RISK Freeman Spogli Institute’s Second Annual International Conference and Dinner “What has changed is not the risk, but the “As Stanford University’s primary forum number and complexity of problems that for the consideration of the major interna- face the world today. The challenges of tional issues of our time, we at FSI are the 21st century require that universities dedicated to interdisciplinary research and change. We must move beyond tradi- teaching on some of the most pressing tional academic boundaries and embrace and complex problems facing the global new ways of doing research.” – stanford community today.” – coit d. “chip” blacker, provost john w. etchemendy director, freeman spogli institute 1 On November 16, 2006, FSI convened its annual international conference, A World at Risk, devoted to systemic and human risk confronting the global community. Remarks by Stanford Provost John Etchemendy, FSI Director Coit Blacker, former Secretary of State Warren Christopher, former Secretary of Defense William Perry, and former Secretary of State George Shultz set the stage for stimulating discussions. Interactive panel sessions encouraged in-depth exploration of major issues with Stanford faculty, outside experts, and policymakers. HERE, AND ON PAGES 8 AND 9, ARE CONFERENCE HIGHLIGHTS “The Middle East has descended into hate, “We are facing new dangers and we must “The world has never been at a more violence, and chaos.
    [Show full text]
  • The University
    2009-10 STANFORD Men’S BASKETBALL THE UNIVERSITY WWW.GOSTANFORD.COM STanford men’S BASKETBALL 2009-10 MEDIA GUIDE 167 2009-10 STANFORD Men’S BASKETBALL THE UNIVERSITY For the Stanford’s on that day, the university was the ▼ Current Perspectives realization of a dream and a fitting tribute to the memory In other ways, the university has changed tremendously of their only son, who had died of typhoid fever weeks on its way to recognition as one of the world’s great before his sixteenth birthday. Far from the nation’s center universities. At the hub of a vital and diverse Bay Area, of culture and unencumbered by tradition or ivy, the new Stanford is less than hour’s drive south of San Francisco university drew students from all over the country: many and just a few minutes north of the Silicon Valley, an area from California; some who followed professors hired dotted with computer and high technology firms largely from other colleges and universities; and some simply spawned by the university’s faculty and graduates. seeking adventure in the West. Though there were On campus, students and faculty enjoy new libraries, Stanford University many difficulties during the first months – housing was modern laboratories, tremendous sports and recreation inadequate, microscopes and books were late in arriving facilities, and comfortable residences. Contemporary at a Glance from the East – the first year foretold of greatness. As sculpture, as well as pieces from the Stanford Museum’s Jane Stanford wrote in the summer of 1892, “Even our extensive collection of sculpture by Auguste Rodin, is On October 1, 1891, the 465 new students who were fondest hopes have been realized.” placed throughout the campus, providing unexpected pleasures at many turns.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stanford Senate Academic Council
    The Stanford Senate of the Academic Council Reflections on Fifty Years of Faculty Governance, 1968–2018 StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 1 3/4/18 11:54 AM StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 2 3/4/18 11:54 AM The Stanford Senate of the Academic Council Reflections on Fifty Years of Faculty Governance, 1968–2018 written, compiled, and edited by Peter Stansky Ethan W. Ris Susan W. Schofield Hans N. Weiler and Past Senate Chairs and Academic Secretaries with the assistance of the Stanford University News Service, Registrar’s Office, and University Archives published by the Stanford University Office of the Academic Secretary with the support of the Stanford Historical Society StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 3 3/4/18 11:54 AM StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 4 3/4/18 11:54 AM Robert W. Beyers. 1974 Dedicated to Robert W. Beyers, an intrepid newsman committed to the integrity of the press and to the effectiveness of faculty governance. Beyers served as the Information Officer for the Senate in its early years. This book was made possible through the generous support of the Robert & Charlotte Beyers Fund of the Stanford Historical Society. StanfordSenate4thpages.indd 5 3/4/18 11:54 AM Stanford University, Office of the Academic Secretary © 2018 by the Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or in any informa- tion storage or retrieval system without the prior written permission of the Stanford University Office of the Academic Secretary.
    [Show full text]
  • Computers, Visualization and the Nature of Reasoning
    Computers, visualization, and the nature of reasoning Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy1 The computer is bringing about a revolution in our understanding of inference, representation, and reasoning, some of the most fundamental no- tions of logic. The revolution is far from complete, but we think the direction is clear enough. In this article we describe how the computer led the two of us first to change the way we teach elementary logic, and eventually to re- think basic assumptions about the subject matter of our discipline. We think the story is a remarkable case study of the synergy between teaching, technol- ogy, and research. 1 Some autobiography Our story begins in 1983 when we both returned to Stanford from teaching at other universities. Elementary logic instruction is part of the bread-and-but- ter teaching in Stanford’s philosophy department, as it is in most philosophy departments. There is a difference, though, because Stanford has a long tradi- tion of using computers in logic instruction. This dates back to the late 1960’s, when Patrick Suppes introduced his program Valid into Philosophy 57, Stanford’s elementary logic course. This program ran on a mainframe com- puter devoted to nothing else, and provided students with an entire course of instruction in introductory logic. Like most logic courses offered from the 60’s through the 80’s, it focused on teaching the basic syntactic rules of proof in a formal calculus. Unlike most, it covered the subject in considerable depth, delving into axiomatic systems of some sophistication. 1The programs described in this paper were conceived by the authors, but would never have be- come realities without the design and programming talents of Gerry Allwein, Dave Barker- Plummer, Kalpana Bharadwaj, Alan Bush, Doug Felt, Dan Fish, Christopher Fuselier, Bill Graham, Mark Greaves, Adrian Klein, Mike Lenz, Steve Loving, Eric Ly, Atty Mullins, Pete Murray, Mark Ravaglia, Xin Wei Sha, Jason Strober, Rolf van Widenfelt, and Rick Wong.
    [Show full text]
  • Stanford Institute for Human-Centered Artificial Intelligence
    2019–2020 ANNUAL REPORT Stanford Institute for Human-Centered Artificial Intelligence Find out how HAI is advancing AI research, education, policy, and practice to improve the human condition. Contents 1 Letter from the Co-Directors 2 By the Numbers RESEARCH 6 HAI Research Focus 7 Featured Projects 8 Grant Programs for AI Research 11 Stanford Digital Economy Lab Y POLICY 14 National Research Cloud 15 Featured Policy Activities A EDUCATION 19 Featured Programs P PEOPLE 20 Denning Co-Directors 21 Associate Directors 23 Staff 24 Faculty and Fellows 25 HAI Commitment to Action 26 Fellows 27 Advisory Council 28 Research Centers and Partners 30 Corporate Members Program 30 Philanthropic Support 31 Events 32 Financials Act. To round out the institute’s first year of operations, Letter from we introduced a range of multidisciplinary education programs focused on helping high-impact decision the Denning makers as well as future leaders respond thoughtfully to Co-Directors the social and ethical implications of AI. Artificial Intelligence will change lives in profound ways. We feel a collective responsibility to help guide this technology in a positive direction. To this end, in 2019 we founded the Stanford Institute for Human-Centered Artificial Intelligence (HAI) to advance AI research, education, policy, and practice to improve the human condition. We want to thank the many faculty and advisors who joined us in conceiving and creating the institute and helping to define its charter and scope. Our growing community of researchers, scholars, fellows, students, and partners brings true diversity of thought to the critical question of how AI will affect our society.
    [Show full text]
  • Join Stanford Women's Basketball Boosters!
    Stanford University Stanford University at a Glance n October 1, 1891, the 465 new students who Owere on hand for opening day ceremonies at Leland Stanford Junior University greeted Leland and Jane For the Stanford’s on that day, the university was the Current Perspectives Stanford enthusiastically, with a chant they had made up realization of a dream and a fitting tribute to the memory In other ways, the university has changed tremendously of their only son, who had died of typhoid fever weeks on its way to recognition as one of the world’s great and rehearsed only that morning. Wah-hoo! Wah-hoo! before his sixteenth birthday. Far from the nation’s center universities. At the hub of a vital and diverse Bay Area, of culture and unencumbered by tradition or ivy, the Stanford is less than hour’s drive south of San Francisco L-S-J-U! Stanford! Its wild and spirited tone symbolized new university drew students from all over the country: and just a few minutes north of the Silicon Valley, an many from California; some who followed professors area dotted with computer and high technology firms the excitement of this bold adventure. As a pioneer faculty hired from other colleges and universities; and some largely spawned by the university’s faculty and graduates. simply seeking adventure in the West. Though there were On campus, students and faculty enjoy new libraries, member recalled, “Hope was in every heart, and the many difficulties during the first months – housing was modern laboratories, tremendous sports and recreation inadequate, microscopes and books were late in arriving facilities, and comfortable residences.
    [Show full text]
  • Tarski, Truth, and Semantics
    Tarski, Truth, and Semantics Richard G. Heck, Jr. 1 Opening No one denies that Tarski made a major contribution to one particular problem about truth, namely, the resolution of the semantic paradoxes—although, of course, there is disagreement about whether he provided the correct solution. But some philosophers have suggested that Tarski also made a significant contribution to an- other project, that of providing semantic theories for natural languages. Hartry Field (2001), for example, credits Tarski with transforming the problem of reduc- ing truth to physicalistically acceptable notions into that of reducing “primitive denotation”. And Donald Davidson (1984c) founded an entire approach to seman- tics by arguing that a theory of meaning for a language may take the form of a Tarskian definition of truth. But, according to John Etchemendy Etchemendy (1988),1 in so far as Tarski’s work does contribute to empirical semantics, this “is little more than a fortuitous accident”. There are both conceptual and historical issues here. The conceptual question is whether reading Tarski’s work on truth as it must be read, if it is to have any relevance to semantics, requires misunderstanding the character of his mathematical work. The historical question is whether Tarski intended his work to be so read. Etchemendy’s view is that Tarski was primarily concerned to resolve the semantic paradoxes. Yet the form his solution takes appears. to serve equally as a characteri- zation of the semantic properties of the language whose truth predicate is defined. However the appearance is actually quite misleading. In particular, it would be a mistake to construe Tarski as taking part in this latter, semantic project, since the two goals turn out to be in quite direct opposition to one another.
    [Show full text]