The Missing Pieces of the Debate Over Federal Property Rights Legislation, 27 Hastings Const

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Missing Pieces of the Debate Over Federal Property Rights Legislation, 27 Hastings Const Hastings Constitutional Law Quarterly Volume 27 Article 1 Number 1 Fall 1999 1-1-1999 The iM ssing Pieces of the Debate over Federal Property Rights Legislation Max Kidalov Richard H. Seamon Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/ hastings_constitutional_law_quaterly Part of the Constitutional Law Commons Recommended Citation Max Kidalov and Richard H. Seamon, The Missing Pieces of the Debate over Federal Property Rights Legislation, 27 Hastings Const. L.Q. 1 (1999). Available at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_constitutional_law_quaterly/vol27/iss1/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hastings Constitutional Law Quarterly by an authorized editor of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ARTICLES The Missing Pieces of the Debate Over Federal Property Rights Legislation by MAx KIDALov* AND RicHARD H. SEAMON** I. Introduction The 105t" Congress came very close to passing property-rights leg- islation that reflected a "new breed" of federal property-rights pro- posals.' Property-rights bills in earlier Congresses would have changed the substance of the Just Compensation Clause by making it easier to prove that government action had "taken" private property.2 In contrast, last year's proposed legislation ostensibly changed, not the substance of takings law, but the process for asserting takings claims in federal court. Opponents of these process-oriented takings bills as- serted, however, that the bills did change the substance of takings law, and for that reason were unconstitutional. The debate over the consti- tutionality of the bills has continuing importance in the 106th Con- gress, where new process-oriented takings bills have been introduced.3 The debate has broader importance as well, for it raises fundamental, unsettled questions about the power of the federal courts and Con- * Clerk to the Honorable Loren A. Smith, Chief Judge, United States Court of Fed- eral Claims; J.D., University of South Carolina. Nothing in this article should be construed as expressing the views of the Court of Federal Claims or as an attempt to advance or hinder the passage of any legislation before the Congress. ** Assistant Professor of Law, University of South Carolina; J.D., Duke University. We thank Michael M. Berger, Steven J. Eagle, John D. Echeverria, Gideon Kanner, Daniel R. Mandelker, Thomas E. Roberts, and Gregory M. Stein for their helpful comments on drafts of this article. 1. S. REP. NO. 105-242, at 37 (1998); Robert Meltz, Congressional Research Service, "PropertyRights" Bills Take a Process Approach: H.R. 992 and H.R. 1534, No. 97-877A, Summary [hereinafter cited as "CRS Report"]; see also infra notes 80-96 and accompany- ing text (discussing proposed legislation). 2. U.S. CONsT. amend. V ("Nor shall private property be taken for public use with- out just compensation."). 3. S. 1028, 106th Cong. (1999); H.R. 2372, 106' Cong. (1999). HASTINGS CONSTITUTIONAL LAW QUARTERLY [Vol. 27:1 gress to enforce the Just Compensation Clause against state and local governments. Unfortunately, the legislative debate so far has not ade- quately explored those questions. This article attempts to provide the missing pieces. The process-oriented takings bills that are the subject of this arti- cle respond to a line of U.S. Supreme Court decisions, the best-known of which is Williamson County Reg'l Planning Comm'n v. Hamilton Bank.4 Those decisions all involved suits in federal courts against lo- cal land-use agencies in which a land owner asserted a "regulatory takings" claim-i.e., a claim that the local agency had "taken" the owner's land by severely restricting the owner's use of it. The Court in the Williamson line of cases developed two "ripeness" requirements that a land owner must meet before bringing a regulatory taking claim against a local agency in federal court. First, the owner must get a "final decision" from the local agency on what land uses are permissi- ble. Second, the owner must exhaust all available and adequate state procedures, including state-court procedures, in his or her attempt to obtain just compensation. Although there are exceptions to William- son's "final decision" and "exhaustion" requirements for ripeness, the exceptions are narrow. In a case that does not fall within an excep- tion, Williamson's ripeness requirements make the litigation of a regu- latory takings claim against a local agency in federal court an arduous and usually futile process. The main process-oriented takings bill considered in the 105th Congress sought to streamline the current process by altering William- son's ripeness requirements. Specifically, House Bill 1534 ("H.R. 1534") would have modified Williamson's "final decision" require- ment to limit the time and effort that a property owner must spend trying to resolve matters with the local agency.5 In addition, H.R. 1534 would have eliminated Williamson's "exhaustion" requirement so that a property owner could assert a regulatory taking claim against a local agency in federal court without seeking just compensation in state court. This article focuses primarily on the second feature of H.R. 1534, the provision eliminating Williamson's exhaustion require- ment, because H.R. 1534's exhaustion provision raises constitutional questions that neither Congress nor the courts have yet answered. The opponents of H.R. 1534 challenged the constitutionality of the bill's exhaustion provision on two grounds, to which the support- 4. 473 U.S. 172 (1985); see also S. REP. NO. 105-242, at 8 (1998) (describing William- son as "a key decision" on takings-ripeness doctrine); H.R. REP. NO. 105-323, at 4 (1997). 5. H.R. 1534, 105th Cong. (1997). Fall 19991 FEDERAL PROPERTY RIGHTS LEGISLATION ers had one main response. First, opponents suggested that the ex- haustion provision would violate Article III of the United States Constitution because the exhaustion requirement is mandated by Ar- ticle M's "case or controversy" requirement.6 They also argued that the exhaustion requirement would make a substantive change in the law of takings by eliminating a necessary element of a cause of action for a violation of the Just Compensation Clause. In their view, such a "substantive" change exceeded Congress' power. Supporters of H.R. 1534 countered both arguments by asserting that the exhaustion re- quirement is a "prudential" requirement, not a constitutional require- ment.7 In their view, its prudential nature made it dispensable by Congress at will. This debate over H.R. 1534's exhaustion provision raises three questions about the power of federal courts and Congress to enforce the Just Compensation Clause against local agencies. First, does Arti- cle III bar a federal court from adjudicating a takings claim against a local agency until the claimant has satisfied Williamson's exhaustion requirement? Second, even assuming that Article III does not bar such a claim, can the claimant establish a cause of action for a viola- tion of the Just Compensation Clause if the claimant has not satisfied the exhaustion requirement? Third, assuming that Article III does not bar the claim of a plaintiff who has not met the exhaustion re- quirement, but that such a plaintiff cannot state a cause of action under the Just Compensation Clause, does Congress have power to authorize the federal courts to award just compensation to the plain- tiff anyway, if the plaintiff can prove that his or her property has been taken? The supporters and opponents of H.R. 1534 explored only the first two questions, and even as to these, their analysis was incom- plete. In terms of their bottom lines, though, each side was half-right. The supporters of H.R. 1534 correctly contended that Article III does not mandate the exhaustion requirement, and Congress can therefore eliminate it without violating Article III. On the other hand, the op- ponents of H.R. 1534 correctly contended that the exhaustion require- 6. See U.S. CONST. art. HI, § 2, cl. 1 (providing that the judicial power of the United States shall extend to certain "Cases" and "Controversies"). 7. The term "prudential" is used to describe rules of justiciability that have been developed by the U.S. Supreme Court and that prevent federal courts from hearing cases that, in the Court's view, are more appropriately resolved in another forum. See Erwin Chemerinsky, Federal Jurisdiction, §2.1, at 42 (2d ed. 1994). Prudential rules are not dic- tated by the Constitution. Rather, they reflect discretionary principles of judicial "self- governance." Flast v. Cohen, 392 U.S. 83, 95 (1968); See also infra note 127. HASTINGS CONSTITUTIONAL LAW QUARTERLY [Vol. 27:1 ment is an element of a cause of action for a violation of the Just Compensation Clause. The elimination of that requirement would change the substance of takings law in the sense that it would create a new right to monetary relief in federal court. Neither the supporters of H.R. 1534 nor its opponents, however, explored the third question posed above: What enumerated power, if any, enabled Congress to make such a substantive change? The supporters asserted that Con- gress has the power to eliminate the exhaustion requirement because it is merely prudential. The opponents asserted that Congress lacks the power to eliminate the requirement because doing so would change the substance of takings law. These assertions mask a difficult question. If the exhaustion re- quirement were only prudential, Congress plainly could eliminate it under current precedent. The U.S. Supreme Court has indicated that Congress has plenary power to eliminate prudential rules of jus- ticiability. The Court appears to consider that authority is encom- passed within Congress' power to make rules for the federal courts.
Recommended publications
  • WALKER V. GEORGIA
    Cite as: 555 U. S. ____ (2008) 1 THOMAS, J., concurring SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES ARTEMUS RICK WALKER v. GEORGIA ON PETITION FOR WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE SUPREME COURT OF GEORGIA No. 08–5385. Decided October 20, 2008 JUSTICE THOMAS, concurring in the denial of the peti- tion of certiorari. Petitioner brutally murdered Lynwood Ray Gresham, and was sentenced to death for his crime. JUSTICE STEVENS objects to the proportionality review undertaken by the Georgia Supreme Court on direct review of peti- tioner’s capital sentence. The Georgia Supreme Court, however, afforded petitioner’s sentence precisely the same proportionality review endorsed by this Court in McCleskey v. Kemp, 481 U. S. 279 (1987); Pulley v. Harris, 465 U. S. 37 (1984); Zant v. Stephens, 462 U. S. 862 (1983); and Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U. S. 153 (1976), and described in Pulley as a “safeguard against arbitrary or capricious sentencing” additional to that which is constitu- tionally required, Pulley, supra, at 45. Because the Geor- gia Supreme Court made no error in applying its statuto- rily required proportionality review in this case, I concur in the denial of certiorari. In May 1999, petitioner recruited Gary Lee Griffin to help him “rob and kill a rich white man” and “take the money, take the jewels.” Pet. for Cert. 5 (internal quota- tion marks omitted); 282 Ga. 774, 774–775, 653 S. E. 2d 439, 443, (2007). Petitioner and Griffin packed two bicy- cles in a borrowed car, dressed in black, and took a knife and stun gun to Gresham’s house.
    [Show full text]
  • Proportionality As a Principle of Limited Government!
    032006 02_RISTROPH.DOC 4/24/2006 12:27 PM PROPORTIONALITY AS A PRINCIPLE ! OF LIMITED GOVERNMENT ALICE RISTROPH† ABSTRACT This Article examines proportionality as a constitutional limitation on the power to punish. In the criminal context, proportionality is often mischaracterized as a specifically penological theory—an ideal linked to specific accounts of the purpose of punishment. In fact, a constitutional proportionality requirement is better understood as an external limitation on the state’s penal power that is independent of the goals of punishment. Proportionality limitations on the penal power arise not from the purposes of punishment, but from the fact that punishing is not the only purpose that the state must pursue. Other considerations, especially the protection of individual interests in liberty and equality, restrict the pursuit of penological goals. Principles of proportionality put the limits into any theory of limited government, and proportionality in the sentencing context is just one instance of these limitations on state power. This understanding of proportionality gives reason to doubt the assertion that determinations of proportionality are necessarily best left to legislatures. In doctrinal contexts other than criminal sentencing, proportionality is frequently used as a mechanism of judicial review to prevent legislative encroachments on individual rights and other exercises of excessive power. In the criminal sentencing context, a constitutional proportionality requirement should serve as a limit on penal power. Copyright © 2005 by Alice Ristroph. † Associate Professor, University of Utah, S.J. Quinney College of Law. A.B., Harvard College; J.D., Harvard Law School; Ph.D., Harvard University; L.L.M., Columbia Law School.
    [Show full text]
  • „When Am I?“ – Zeitlichkeit in Der US-Serie LOST, Teil 2
    GABRIELE SCHABACHER „When Am I?“ – Zeitlichkeit in der US-Serie LOST, Teil 2 Previously on … An der US-Serie LOST lässt sich eine systematische Nutzung der temporalen Di- mension beobachten: Auf den Ebenen von Erzählzeit und erzählter Zeit – das konnte der erste Teil dieses Beitrags zeigen – ist der Einsatz von story arcs überspan- nenden Flashbacks bzw. Flashforwards sowie eine handlungsseitig ausgeführte Thematisierung und Problematisierung von Zeitreisen und Teleportation für das Seriennarrativ zentral. Schon diese zeitlichen Relationen ermöglichen der Narra- tion entscheidende Inversionen und paradoxe Konstruktionen, die für die Serie LOST charakteristisch geworden sind. 1. Die dritte Zeit Eine dritte Dimension der Narration, um die es dem zweiten Teil dieses Beitrags geht, lässt sich nun keiner der beiden bisher thematisierten Gruppen eindeutig zuordnen, weder also der Erzählzeit und damit den stilistischen Mitteln im engeren Sinne, noch der erzählten Zeit, d. h. der inhaltlichen Ebene der Geschichte. Es handelt sich vielmehr um eine Gruppe von Phänomen, die sich durch eine spezifi - sche Übergängigkeit zwischen diesen beiden Kategorien auszeichnen. Daher wird im Folgenden auf die in der Serie geäußerten Vorahnungen, Time Loops, Bewusst- seinsreisen und Zeitsprünge einzugehen sein, um die Hybridisierung von Stilistik und Inhaltsmomenten der Narration zu verdeutlichen. Das Vorhandensein solcher hybrider Elemente ist es, das eine mögliche Erklärung für die besondere Faszinati- on an LOST und eine spezifi sch temporal motivierte Komplexität
    [Show full text]
  • Practical Guide on Admissibility Criteria
    Practical Guide on Admissibility Criteria Updated on 1 August 2021 This Guide has been prepared by the Registry and does not bind the Court. Practical guide on admissibility criteria Publishers or organisations wishing to translate and/or reproduce all or part of this report in the form of a printed or electronic publication are invited to contact [email protected] for information on the authorisation procedure. If you wish to know which translations of the Case-Law Guides are currently under way, please see Pending translations. This Guide was originally drafted in English. It is updated regularly and, most recently, on 1 August 2021. It may be subject to editorial revision. The Admissibility Guide and the Case-Law Guides are available for downloading at www.echr.coe.int (Case-law – Case-law analysis – Admissibility guides). For publication updates please follow the Court’s Twitter account at https://twitter.com/ECHR_CEDH. © Council of Europe/European Court of Human Rights, 2021 European Court of Human Rights 2/109 Last update: 01.08.2021 Practical guide on admissibility criteria Table of contents Note to readers ........................................................................................... 6 Introduction ................................................................................................ 7 A. Individual application ............................................................................................................. 9 1. Purpose of the provision ..................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Judicial Review Scope and Grounds
    JUDICIAL REVIEW SCOPE AND GROUNDS By Scott Blair, Advocate THE TRIGONOMETRY OF JUDICIAL REVIEW In Scotland, unlike England and Wales, the judicial review jurisdiction is not limited to cases which have an element of public law. As explained by Lord President Hope in West v. Secretary of State for Scotland 1992 SC 385 at 413 the scope of judicial review is as follows: “ The following propositions are intended therefore to define the principles by reference to which the competency of all applications to the supervisory jurisdiction under Rule of Court 260B is to be determined: 1. The Court of Session has power, in the exercise of its supervisory jurisdiction, to regulate the process by which decisions are taken by any person or body to whom a jurisdiction, power or authority has been delegated or entrusted by statute, agreement or any other instrument. 2. The sole purpose for which the supervisory jurisdiction may be exercised is to ensure that the person or body does not exceed or abuse that jurisdiction, power or authority or fail to do what the jurisdiction, power or authority requires. 3. The competency of the application does not depend upon any distinction between public law and private law, nor is it confined to those cases which English law has accepted as amenable to judicial review, nor is it correct in regard to issues about competency to describe judicial review under Rule of Court 260B as a public law remedy. By way of explanation we would emphasise these important points: (a) Judicial review is available, not to provide machinery for an appeal, but to ensure that the decision-maker does not exceed or abuse his powers or fail to perform the duty which has been delegated or entrusted to him.
    [Show full text]
  • The Quest for Proportionality in the Discovery Rules of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Duke Law Scholarship Repository Are We Insane? The Quest for Proportionality in the Discovery Rules of the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure Paul W. Grimm Albert Einstein defined insanity as “doing the same thing over and over again, and expecting different results.”1 For over thirty years, the federal rules of civil procedure have been serially amended to require federal trial judges to control pretrial discovery in civil cases to ensure that it is “proportional”—meaning that the costs to the parties are not unduly great given what is at stake in the litigation. And, for thirty years, lawyers, bar associations, clients and commentators have complained loudly that the federal judges have not done so. The Supreme Court has approved yet another series of civil rules changes, which took effect on December 1, 2015, that once more direct judges to ensure that discovery is proportional. But if the proportionality requirement already has been in the rules for over thirty years without inducing judges to fulfill their obligation to manage discovery, what makes this latest amendment requiring the exact same thing any more likely to achieve success? In short, why has achieving proportionality been such an elusive goal? Is it possible for judges to manage discovery so that it is proportional? If so, how are they to do so? And, if achieving proportionality is possible, why have judges failed to do so? Is it because they are resistant to doing what the rules require? Or are they willing to try, but they lack the knowledge or training to succeed in the task? These questions, and their answers, are the focus of this thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Memorial Book 2020
    5781 CONGREGATION KOL AMI VIRTUAL CEMETERY It is a long standing Jewish tradition to visit the gravesites of loved ones in the period surrounding the High Holidays. While a personal visit to the cemetery is the preferred way to fulfill this mitzvah, circumstances may prevent such a trip. Thanks to the internet and a website called FindaGrave, those buried in Congregation Kol Ami plots, family members interred at other cemeteries anywhere in the world and those whose only memorial is in our minds and hearts, may be visited virtually. One feature of FindaGrave is the ability to create a virtual cemetery. A virtual cemetery gathers memorials of people who are interred in various physical cemeteries into one place. The Congregation Kol Ami Virtual Cemetery lists all interments in Kol Ami plots at Mount Hope and Mount Pleasant cemeteries. In addition, memorials for people who are buried around the globe, or whose ashes may have been scattered in the winds and waters of the planet, may be included in our virtual Kol Ami cemetery. The site may be visited by going to: http://tinyurl.com/KolAmiVirtualCemetery By clicking the name of an individual, you will be taken to his or her memorial page. There, you will find a photograph of the gravestone or other memorial (e.g. a plaque on a bench), as well as information taken from the stone, such as dates of birth and death. A few of the listings include biographical information entered by the creator of the memorial page. For questions about the virtual cemetery or to have a name added, please contact our temple office.
    [Show full text]
  • Judges and Discrimination: Assessing the Theory and Practice of Criminal Sentencing
    The author(s) shown below used Federal funds provided by the U.S. Department of Justice and prepared the following final report: Document Title: Judges and Discrimination: Assessing the Theory and Practice of Criminal Sentencing Author(s): Charles W. Ostrom ; Brian J. Ostrom ; Matthew Kleiman Document No.: 204024 Date Received: February 2004 Award Number: 98-CE-VX-0008 This report has not been published by the U.S. Department of Justice. To provide better customer service, NCJRS has made this Federally- funded grant final report available electronically in addition to traditional paper copies. Opinions or points of view expressed are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the official position or policies of the U.S. Department of Justice. Judges and Discrimination Assessing the Theory and Practice of Criminal Sentencing Apprwed By: m Authored by: Charles W. Ostrom Michigan State University Brian J. Ostrom National Center for State Courts Matthew Kleiman National Center for State Courts With the cooperation of the Michigan Sentencing Commission and the Michigan Department of Corrections This report was developed under a grant from the National Institute of Justice (Grant 98-CE-VX-0008). The opinions andpoints of view in this report are those of the authors and do not necessarily represent the official position or policies of the National Institute or the Michigan Sentencing Commission. 1 The sentencing decision is the symbolic keystone of the c~minaljustice system: in it, the conflicts between the goals of equal justice under the law and indvidualzedjustice with punishment tailored to the offender are played out, and sociely5s moral principles and highest vaiues-life and libedy-are interpreted and appled.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard S. Frase* the Supreme Court's Disappointing Holdings in the California Three Strikes Cases Have Probably Led Many Obse
    LIMITING EXCESSIVE PRISON SENTENCES UNDER FEDERAL AND STATE CONSTITUTIONS * Richard S. Frase INTRODUCTION The Supreme Court’s disappointing holdings in the California Three Strikes cases have probably led many observers to conclude that there are no effective constitutional limits on excessively long prison sentences. This Article argues the contrary, and makes three main points. First, any judgment of excessiveness (or disproportionality) re- quires a normative framework—“excessive” relative to what? The Court’s opinions have been very unhelpful in this regard, but three distinct proportionality principles are implicit in Eighth Amendment cases (and in many other areas of American, foreign, and interna- tional law). Litigators, courts, and scholars need to clearly state and make explicit use of these principles. As summarized below, and more fully discussed in my previous writings,1 three of the most im- portant and widespread examples of such principles are what I have called the limiting retributive, ends-benefits, and alternative-means proportionality principles. The second and third principles are grounded in utilitarian philosophy; thus, they apply even if a jurisdic- tion (with the Court’s apparent blessing) rejects retributive limits on lengthy prison terms designed to achieve crime control and other practical goals. Second, excessiveness, in one or more of the three senses dis- cussed in Part I, is the common theme which underlies all three clauses of the Eighth Amendment.2 Litigators, courts, and scholars should explicitly recognize and apply this theme in prison-duration cases applying the Cruel and Unusual Punishments Clause, drawing * Benjamin N. Berger Professor of Criminal Law, University of Minnesota.
    [Show full text]
  • The Reasonableness and Proportionality Principle in Labour Law
    THE REASONABLENESS AND PROPORTIONALITY PRINCIPLE IN LABOUR LAW Piera Loi Law Department, University of Cagliari, Italy The reasonableness and proportionality principle in labour law Piera Loi Law Department, University of Cagliari, Italy [email protected] Draft- not to be quoted Introduction The reasonableness and proportionality principle seems to have a growing importance in labour law. One of the first questions we should ask is what are the relations between these concepts. In the Italian constitutional tradition proportionality and reasonableness are strictly related, since the proportionality principle has always been considered as instrumental to the reasonableness principle- and the proportionality test is seen as part of the reasonableness test- whereas in the other EU legal systems and also in European case law the reasonableness principle is autonomous. The proportionality principle is in use in different areas of law, especially in constitutional and administrative law, and it’s aiming at controlling the exercise of public powers towards individuals. This unwritten constitutional principle developed by the German Constitutional Courts, finds its origins in the tradition of German public law. It was precisely the Prussian Supreme Court that established the principle in the field of police law1 and Georg Jellinek’s comment was that “the police may not kill a swallow with a cannon”. The principle requires that any restriction of individual freedom must be appropriate to the attainment of the objectives to be achieved. Any restrictive measures should not impose excessive limits on the freedom of the individual and must therefore be based on the principle of 1 Decision 9 of 14 June 1882, PROVG 353 reasonableness.
    [Show full text]
  • In the Supreme Court of the United States
    No. In the Supreme Court of the United States STEPHEN M. SHAPIRO, O. JOHN BENISEK, AND MARIA B. PYCHA Petitioners, v. BOBBIE S. MACK AND LINDA H. LAMONE, Respondents. On Petition for a Writ of Certiorari to the United States Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit PETITION FOR A WRIT OF CERTIORARI MICHAEL B. KIMBERLY Counsel of Record PAUL W. HUGHES JEFFREY S. REDFERN Mayer Brown LLP 1999 K Street, NW Washington, DC 20006 (202) 263-3127 [email protected] Counsel for Petitioners QUESTION PRESENTED The Three-Judge Court Act requires the conven- ing of three-judge district courts to hear a wide range of particularly important lawsuits, including consti- tutional challenges to the apportionment of congres- sional districts and certain actions under the Voting Rights Act, Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act, Prison Litigation Reform Act, and Communications Act. The Three-Judge Court Act provides that a three-judge court shall be convened to hear such cases unless the single judge to whom the case is initially referred “determines that three judges are not required.” 28 U.S.C. § 2284(a), (b)(1). In Goosby v. Osser, 409 U.S. 512 (1973), this Court held that the Three-Judge Court Act “does not require the convening of a three-judge court when the [claim] is insubstantial.” Id. at 518. A claim is in- substantial “for this purpose” if it is “‘obviously friv- olous,’” “‘essentially fictitious,’” or “inescapably * * * foreclose[d]” by this Court’s precedents. Ibid. The question presented, which has divided the lower courts, is as follows: May a single-judge district court determine that a complaint covered by 28 U.S.C.
    [Show full text]
  • Overview of Judicial Review
    Overview of Judicial Review Richards Harwood & Wald 9 September 2010 Overview of Judicial Review 1. A general overview of judicial review can be divided into the following topics, of which the second (Grounds of Review) forms the focus of today’s presentation: (1) Procedural issues. (a) Introduction. (b) Pre-action conduct. (c) Protective Costs Orders. (d) Commencing a Claim. (e) The Acknowledgment of Service. (f) Permission. (g) Costs at the Permission stage. (h) Standing. (i) Alternative Remedies. (j) Time Limits. (k) Discretion to Refuse a Remedy. (2) Grounds of Review (a) Illegality (i) Doing an act with no legal authority (simple illegality). (ii) Misinterpreting the law governing the decision. (iii) Failure to retain a discretion by: (1) Improper delegation. (2) Fettering of discretion by adoption of over-rigid policy. (iv) Abuse of discretion: (1) Using a power for an improper purpose. 2 (2) Taking into account irrelevant considerations or failing to take into account relevant considerations. (b) Irrationality. (c) Procedural Impropriety. (3) Remedies (a) Prerogative Remedies: (i) Quashing Order (ii) Mandatory Order (iii) Prohibiting Order (b) Common Law Remedies: (i) Injunction (ii) Declaration (c) Pecuniary Remedies: (i) Damages (ii) Restitution. 3 Procedural Issues Introduction 2. A claim for judicial review is defined widely by CPR 54.1(2)(a) as “a claim to review the lawfulness of – (i) an enactment; or (ii) a decision, action or failure to act in relation to the exercise of a public function.” 3. The judicial review procedure must be used in a claim for judicial review when the Claimant is seeking a prerogative order (mandatory order, prohibiting order, or quashing order) or an injunction under s30 Supreme Court Act 1981 (restraining a person from acting in any office in which he is not entitled to act): CPR 54.2.
    [Show full text]