Cartesian Meditation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Cartesian Meditation EUGEN FINK Sixth Cartesian Meditation THE IDEA OF A TRANSCENDENTAL THEORY OF METHOD WITH TEXTUAL NOTATIONS BY EDMUND HUSSERL TRANSLATED WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY Ronald Brutina EUGEN FINK Sixth Cartesian Meditation THE IDEA OF A TRANSCENDENTAL THEORY OF METHOD WITH NOTATIONS BY EDMUND HUSSERL TRANSLATED WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY Ronald Bruzina "... a thorough critique of Husserl's transcendental phenomenology . raises many new questions. a classic." — J. N. M ohanty Eugen Fink's Sixth Cartesian Medita­ tion, accompanied by Edmund Husserl's detailed and extensive notations, is a pivotal document in the development of one of the dominant philosophical directions of the twentieth century, Husserlian transcendental phe­ nomenology. Meant to follow a systematic revision of Husserl's first five Cartesian Meditations, (continued on back flap) Sixth Cartesian Meditation Studies in Continental Thought John Sallis, general editor Consulting Editors Robert Bernasconi W illia m L. M cBride Rudolf Bernet J. N. Mohanty John D. Caputo M ary Rawlinson David Carr Tom Rockmore Edward S. Casey Calvin O . Schrag Hubert L. Dreyfus f Reiner Schiirmann D o n Ih d e C h a rle s E. Scott David Farrell Krell Thomas Sheehan Lenore Langsdorf Robert Sokolowski Alphonso Lingis Bruce W . Wilshire D a v id W o o d Sixth Cartesian Meditation T H E ID EA OF A TRANSCENDENTAL THEORY OF M E T H O D WITH TEXTUAL NOTATIONS BY EDMUND HUSSERL TRANSLATED WITH AN INTRODUCTION BY Ronald Bruzina INDIANA UNIVERSITY PRESS BLOOMINGTON & INDIANAPOLIS Published in G erm an as Eugen Fink, Vi. Cartesianische Meditation.Teil 1. Die Idee Einer Transzendentalen Metbodenlebrr, edited by Hans Ebeling, Jann H o ll, and Guy van K.erckhoven. C opyright © 1988 by Kluwer -Academic Publishers B.V. English-language edition © 1?95 by Ronald Bruzina All rights re served N o part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher The Association of American University Presses' Resolution on Permissions constitutes the only exception to this prohibition. The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences— Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z 39.48 -1984. ® T“ M anufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Fink, Eugen. [Idee einer transzendentaler Methodenlehre. English] Sixth Cartesian meditation : the idea of a transcendental theory of method / Eugen Fink; with the complete textual notations by Edmund Husserl , translated with an introduction by Ronald Bruzina. p. cm. — (Studies in Continental thought) Translation of: VI. cartesianische Meditation. T. I. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-253-32273-1 (alk. paper) 1. Husserl, Edmund, 1859-1938 Cartesianische Meditationen. 2. Phenom enology. I. Husserl, Edmund, 1859-1938. II. Title. III. Title: 6th Cartesian meditation. IV. Title: Idea of a transcendental theory of method. V. Series. B3279.H94F4913 1995 193—dc20 94-34 1 2 3 4 5 00 9 9 98 97 96 95 L. Contents TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTION vii [DRAFT OF A FOREWORD] 1 PREFATORY NOTE [TO THE HABITATION TEXT], DECEMBER, 1945 2 SIXTH [CARTESIAN] MEDITATION The Idea of a Transcendental Theory of Method §1. The methodological limitation of the previous Meditations 3 §2. The theme of the transcendental theory of method 10 §3. The "self-reference" of phenomenology 13 §4. The problem and articulation of the transcendental theory of method 19 §5. Phenomenologizing as the action of reduction 29 §6. Phenomenologizing as a process of regressive analysis 48 § 7 . Phenomenologizing in "constructive" phenomenology 54 §8. Phenomenologizing as theoretical experience 66 §9. Phenomenologizing as an action of ideation 77 §10. Phenomenologizing as predication 84 §11. Phenomenologizing as "making into a science" 100 A) The problem of the scientificity of phenomenologizing 101 B) The enworlding of phenomenologizing 106 C) The concept of "science" 133 §12. "Phenomenology" as transcendental idealism 152 A PP E N D IC E S Texts by Edmund Husserl relating to Eugen Fink's D raft of a Sixth M editation A. Appended pages and insertions [from Summer 1933 to January 1934) 163 A ppendix I 163 Appendix II 163 Appendix III 165 Appendix IV 165 Appendix V 166 Appendix VI 167 Appendix VII 168 Appendix VIII 170 Appendix IX 171 B. Comments and research notes 174 A ppendix X 174 Appendix XI 178 Appendix XII 181 C. Unassigned pages 188 Appendix XIII 188 Appendix XIV 190 Appendix XV 191 TRANSLATOR'S NOTES 193 INDEX 201 TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTION Eugen Fink's "Sixth Cartesian Meditation" is one of those famous unknown works in philosophy that haunt the margins of established texts while seldom if ever coming to light themselves, at least in any form other than scant frag­ ments. Occasionally, however, one of these missing writings does become ac­ cessible in full and is at last itself known, and this is the case with the present publication. For a whole generation of philosophers in phenomenology— which is a long time in the modern age of rapid and extensive communication and scholarship— the Sixth Meditation was a work known to have been writ­ ten, yet one that very few had ever seen, one that could easily be presumed not to have survived the descent of fascism and war upon Europe. Those who had read the Sixth Meditation were individuals who had maintained a close connection with Edmund Husserl even as the times darkened after 1933, and as acknowledgment of Husserl's accomplishments and of his very name came to be suppressed in Germany. Published mention of the Sixth Meditation first occurred in 1941 in France, in Gaston Berger's Le cogito dans la philosophic de Husserl1 to be followed only after the end of the war by reference to it in M au­ rice Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenologie de la perception.2 It was most natural, then, that, when the editing of Husserl's Cartesian Meditations was under way for the first volume of the Husserliana edition, in­ terest would again turn to this text of Fink's. Stephan Strasser spoke of it in his editor's introduction to the Cartesianische Meditationen,3 expressing the hope that, while the Sixth Meditation did not figure into the edition he was prepar­ ing, it would nevertheless be itself published as part of the whole set of revi­ sion texts that Fink had produced for Husserl for the Cartesian Meditations in that earlier decade. The texts in question— the Sixth Meditation itself and these revision texts for Husserl's earlier five Cartesian Meditations— were and are not, however, part of the Husserl Nachlass in the Archives in Louvain.4 Apart from the period when Fink resided and lectured at Louvain (from the spring of 1939 to the autumn of 1940),5 these texts were not available even there,- and not until 1971 were copies finally provided for the Husserl Archives. Arrangements for their publication got under way only after Fink's death in 1975 and after the opening of the adjunct series, Husserliana Doku- mente, in 1977. It is in this series, now, that the texts have finally appeared in a two-volume edition, Eugen Fink, VI. Cartesianische Meditation, Part I: Die Idee einer Transzendentalen Metbodenlebre, ed. Hans Ebeling, Jann Holl, and Guy van Kerckhoven,- Part II: Ertjanzungsband, ed. Guy van Kerckhoven.6 It is the text of the first of these two volumes that is integrally translated here. The question of how and why these texts were preserved and yet kept pri­ vate is directly bound up with the history of their origin, which includes nat­ urally the nature of their content. They are the product of an intimate collaborative effort on the part of two philosophers, one an established and world-renowned master, the other a youthful scholar who had just finished his doctoral work. Each had an independent mind, each highly valued the other's work, and both were deeply involved in a shared project of philo­ sophic investigation and reflection. Yet they were different individuals in this common project,- and so the project acquired from the one differing emphases and a differing character than it did from the other. Both were beginners, but differently: one was a beginner in the final stage of a lifelong thinking,7 the other a beginner in the first realization of what would be a similar dedication. It will not be possible in this introduction to treat in any great detail the iden­ tities and differences between these two linked endeavors,- and yet som ething of this will have to be covered, for the nature of the documents given here in English is such that the primaiy thing is precisely the interplay of the two thinkings. W hen one considers what this final period of Husserl's thinking is taken to represent, namely, the culmination of an originally Cartesian impe­ tus that is being at the same time transcended, then the documented record of the direct interplay, the dialogue, of these two minds deep within tran­ scendental phenomenology takes on special importance. W hen we look at the title of the main text of the present translated vol­ ume, we should notice two things. First, we have here the sixth of a series of "Cartesian" meditations,- second, the subtitle of this sixth "Cartesian" medita­ tion, "The Idea of a Transcendental Theory of Method/' is frankly Kantian. W e must understand, then, what the fuller context and principal orientation of this piece are in order to interpret it properly. In the first place, it must be recognized that Fink's Sixth Meditation was meant to follow not upon Husserl's Cartesian Meditations as they have be­ come familiar to us up until now,8 but upon an extensively reworked version that was produced three years after Husserl's first full revision in 1929.
Recommended publications
  • On the Methodological Role of Marxism in Merleau-Ponty's
    On the Methodological Role of Marxism in Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology Abstract While contemporary scholarship on Merleau-Ponty virtually overlooks his postwar existential Marxism, this paper argues that the conception of history contained in the latter plays a signifi- cant methodological role in supporting the notion of truth that operates within Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological analyses of embodiment and the perceived world. This is because this con- ception regards the world as an unfinished task, such that the sense and rationality attributed to its historical emergence conditions the phenomenological evidence used by Merleau-Ponty. The result is that the content of Phenomenology of Perception should be seen as implicated in the normative framework of Humanism and Terror. Keywords: Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, Methodology, Marxism, History On the Methodological Role of Marxism in Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology In her 2007 book Merleau-Ponty and Modern Politics after Anti-Humanism, Diana Coole made the claim (among others) that Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology is “profoundly and intrinsically political,”1 and in particular that it would behoove readers of his work to return to the so-called ‘communist question’ as he posed it in the immediate postwar period.2 For reasons that basical- ly form the substance of this paper, I think that these claims are generally correct and well- taken. But this is in spite of the fact that they go very distinctly against the grain of virtually all contemporary scholarship on Merleau-Ponty. For it is the case that very few scholars today – and this is particularly true of philosophers – have any serious interest in the political dimen- sions of Merleau-Ponty’s work.
    [Show full text]
  • Husserl and Ricoeur the Influence of Phenomenology on the Formation of Ricoeur’S Hermeneutics of the ‘Capable Human’
    Husserl and Ricoeur The Influence of Phenomenology on the Formation of Ricoeur’s Hermeneutics of the ‘Capable Human’ Dermot Moran Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy - Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française, Vol XXV, No 1 (2017) pp 182-199. Vol XXV, No 1 (2017) ISSN 1936-6280 (print) ISSN 2155-1162 (online) DOI 10.5195/jffp.2017.800 www.jffp.org This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. This journal is operated by the University Library System of the University of Pittsburgh as part of its D-Scribe Digital Publishing Program, and is co-sponsored by the UniversityJournal of Pittsburgh of French and Press Francophone Philosophy | Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française Vol XXV, No 1 (2017) | www.jffp.org | DOI 10.5195/jffp.2017.800 Husserl and Ricoeur The Influence of Phenomenology on the Formation of Ricoeur’s Hermeneutics of the ‘Capable Human’ Dermot Moran University College Dublin & Wuhan University The phenomenology of Edmund Husserl had a permanent and profound impact on the philosophical formation of Paul Ricoeur. One could truly say, paraphrasing Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s brilliant 1959 essay “The Philosopher and his Shadow,”1 that Husserl is the philosopher in whose shadow Ricoeur, like Merleau-Ponty, also stands, the thinker to whom he constantly returns. Husserl is Ricoeur’s philosopher of reflection, par excellence. Indeed, Ricoeur always invokes Husserl when he is discussing a paradigmatic instance of contemporary philosophy of “reflection” and also of descriptive, “eidetic” phenomenology.2 Indeed, I shall argue in this chapter that Husserl’s influence on Ricoeur was decisive and provided a methodology which is permanently in play, even when it has to be concretized and mediated by hermeneutics, as Ricoeur proposes after 1960.
    [Show full text]
  • My Own Life[1]
    My Own Life[1] Dorion Cairns I was born July 4th, 1901, in the village of Contoocook, in the town of Hopkinton, New Hampshire. My father, James George Cairns, was the pastor of the Methodist Church in Contoocook, and I was the first child of my parents. During my first three and a half years of life, my father moved from one place to another as pastor of Methodist Churches in New Hampshire and Massachusetts. My brother, Stewart Scott Cairns, currently Professor of Mathematics at the University of Illinois, was born May 8th, 1904. My father felt that there was no future for a young minister in New England, and he decided to move his family—which consisted of my mother, my brother and me—to California. He shipped all of our family goods, all of our furniture and things, to California on the very day of the San Francisco Earthquake, or “Fire,” as they like to call it in San Francisco. The California Conference of the Methodist Episcopal Church at that time controlled what was called the “Utah Mission.” This was a mission to Mormon Territory, needless to say. My father, since there were so many people of longer standing in the California Conference who had no churches left owing to the earthquake, was given a church in Utah Mission, in Salt Lake City itself. It was there in 1907 that my sister Mary, who is the wife of James Wilkinson Miller, currently Professor of Philosophy at McGill University in Montreal, was born. When they wanted to transfer my father from this little church in Salt Lake City to a church or mission in Provo, Utah, my father went and looked at the set-up in Provo, and he came back, and it was the first time I had seen a grown man cry.
    [Show full text]
  • The Manifold Concept of the Lifeworld. Husserl and His Posterity
    Doctorado en Filosofía The Manifold Concept of the lifeworld. Husserl and his posterity Academic Term 2nd Semester 2021 Credits 6 Calendar Once-a-week sessions, Tuesdays, 15.30-18.30; September 28 – December 14 Office hours Fridays, 17.00-18.00 Profesor Ovidiu Stanciu Mail [email protected] DESCRIPTION The concept of the world has played a significant role in the phenomenological tradition. By redefining the meaning of the world and proposing a “natural concept of the world” (natürliche Weltbegriff) or a concept of the lifeworld (Lebenswelt), phenomenology was able to make clear the peculiarity of its own undertaking against competing philosophical directions such as Neo-Kantianism, logical positivism or neutral monism (Whitehead, W. James). The first major formulation of the concept of lifeworld can be traced back to Husserl’s last writings, namely the ‘‘Crisis’’-texts. This course aims at unpacking the various ramifications and levels of analysis entailed in this question and at proposing a critical discussion of the ambiguities the concept of “life-world” contains. The basic claim Husserl (and the subsequent phenomenological tradition) is issuing is that although the world is never an immediate object of experience, although it cannot be experienced in a straightforward way as we experience things in the world, it is yet a built-in structure and a necessary ingredient of every experience. In and through each of our particular perceptions and actions we experience not only particular things but also of the world as their ultimate horizon. The correlative thesis is that every experience has an intuitive core and a non-thematic background, which properly understood is that of the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 7-1-2018 Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology (07/18). DOI. © 2018 Oxford University Press. Used with permission. Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology Edited by Dan Zahavi Print Publication Date: Jun 2018 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, History of Western Philosophy (Post-Classical) Online Publication Date: Jul 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.5 Abstract and Keywords This chapter offers a reassessment of the relationship between Kant, the Kantian tradi­ tion, and phenomenology, here focusing mainly on Husserl and Heidegger. Part of this re­ assessment concerns those philosophers who, during the lives of Husserl and Heidegger, sought to defend an updated version of Kant’s philosophy, the neo-Kantians. The chapter shows where the phenomenologists were able to benefit from some of the insights on the part of Kant and the neo-Kantians, but also clearly points to the differences. The aim of this chapter is to offer a fair evaluation of the relation of the main phenomenologists to Kant and to what was at the time the most powerful philosophical movement in Europe. Keywords: Immanuel Kant, neo-Kantianism, Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Marburg School of neo-Kantian­ ism 3.1 Introduction THE relation between phenomenology, Kant, and Kantian philosophizing broadly con­ strued (historically and systematically), has been a mainstay in phenomenological re­ search.1 This mutual testing of both philosophies is hardly surprising given phenomenology’s promise to provide a wholly novel type of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Things: the Ontological Importance of Play According to Eugen Fink Jan Halák Published Online: 26 Aug 2015
    This article was downloaded by: [Jan Halák] On: 30 August 2015, At: 11:57 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: 5 Howick Place, London, SW1P 1WG Journal of the Philosophy of Sport Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjps20 Beyond Things: The Ontological Importance of Play According to Eugen Fink Jan Halák Published online: 26 Aug 2015. Click for updates To cite this article: Jan Halák (2015): Beyond Things: The Ontological Importance of Play According to Eugen Fink, Journal of the Philosophy of Sport, DOI: 10.1080/00948705.2015.1079133 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00948705.2015.1079133 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content.
    [Show full text]
  • Contributions to Phenomenology
    HANDBOOK OF PHENOMENOLOGICAL AESTHETICS CONTRIBUTIONS TO PHENOMENOLOGY IN COOPERATION WITH THE CENTER FOR ADVANCED RESEARCH IN PHENOMENOLOGY Vol ume 59 Series Editors: Nicolas de Warren, Wellesley College, MA, USA Dermot Moran, University College Dublin, Ireland. Editorial Board: Lilian Alweiss, Trinity College Dublin, Ireland Elizabeth Behnke, Ferndale, WA, USA Rudolf Bernet, Husserl-Archief, Katholieke Universiteit Leuven, Belgium David Carr, Emory University, GA, USA Chan-Fai Cheung, Chinese University Hong Kong, China James Dodd, New School University, NY, USA Lester Embree, Florida Atlantic University, FL, USA Alfredo Ferrarin, Università di Pisa, Italy Burt Hopkins, Seattle University, WA, USA Kwok-Ying Lau, Chinese University Hong Kong, China Nam-In Lee, Seoul National University, Korea Dieter Lohmar, Universität zu Köln, Germany William R. McKenna, Miami University, OH, USA Algis Mickunas, Ohio University, OH, USA J.N. Mohanty, Temple University, PA, USA Junichi Murata, University of Tokyo, Japan Thomas Nenon, The University of Memphis, TN, USA Thomas M. Seebohm, Johannes Gutenberg-Universität, Germany Gail Soffer, Rome, Italy Anthony Steinbock, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale, IL, USA Shigeru Taguchi, Yamagata University, Japan Dan Zahavi, University of Copenhagen, Denmark Richard M. Zaner, Vanderbilt University, TN, USA Scope The purpose of the series is to serve as a vehicle for the pursuit of phenomenological research across a broad spectrum, including cross-over developments with other fields of inquiry such as the social sciences and cognitive science. Since its establishment in 1987, Contributions to Phenomenology has published nearly 60 titles on diverse themes of phenomenological philosophy. In addition to welcoming monographs and collections of papers in established areas of scholarship, the series encourages original work in phenomenology.
    [Show full text]
  • 92 Necessitate Scrutiny Beyond the Scope of His Thesis, Schneider Reiterates His Long-Standing Argument Against the Utopian Expa
    92 BOOK REVIEWS necessitate scrutiny beyond the scope of his thesis, Schneider reiterates his long-standing argument against the utopian expansiveness of the "Wilbe- rians" as well as suggests an existential basis for religion. Finally, Schneider presents his contribution to existential therapy. Essentially, it consists of the attempt to help the patient integrate the contradictory, paradoxical extremes of everyday life. He summarizes: The key dictums here have been (1) address the client's desire and capacity for (constrictive or expansive) integration; (2) align the ther- apeutic approach with this desire and capacity; and (3) invite clients into increasingly anxious domains of their experience (keeping fully aware of the first dictum), so as to enhance their capacity to construc- tively transform those domains. (p. 204) Schneider's consideration of the paradoxical phenomena of constriction and expansion continues the existential tradition in psychotherapy. While one might wonder about the constrictive nature of the thesis itself as it reduces a vast array of descriptions (as well as psychoanalytic and psycho- logical nosology) to the polarity, it provides a means of understanding the fear and dread experienced by troubled people in the context of the contradictions of everyday existence. Furthermore, it offers both a philo- sophic and psychotherapeutic means of' understanding and being with individuals stymied or troubled by those contradictions. Michael W. Barclay Cotati, CA Eugen Fink, Cartesianische Meditation VI (Two-volume Set: Teil 1. Die Idee einer Transzendentalen Methodenlehre, edited by Hans Ebeling, Jann Holl, and Guy van Kerckhoven. Teil 2. Ergänzungsband, edited by Guy van Kerckhoven) . Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1988, vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Merleau-Ponty and the Myth of Human Incarnation Bryan Smyth
    Merleau-Ponty and the Myth of Human Incarnation Bryan Smyth The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, Volume 30, Number 3, 2016, pp. 382-394 (Article) Published by Penn State University Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/628668 Access provided by University Of South Florida Libraries (29 Apr 2017 04:33 GMT) jsp Merleau-Ponty and the Myth of Human Incarnation Bryan Smyth university of mississippi abstract: In this article I argue that Merleau-Ponty’s initial reinterpretation of Husserlian phenomenology is premised methodologically on a certain mythic under- standing of human embodiment—what I term “the myth of human incarnation.” This is not an objection but a clarification of how Merleau-Ponty resolved the problem of the external horizonality of phenomenological experience on an intuitional (rather than speculative) basis. This methodological priority of myth is implicated in the epis- temic status of phenomenological claims concerning prereflective phenomena such as “bodily” intentionality and thus has important consequences for questions concerning the “naturalization” of phenomenology. keywords: Merleau-Ponty, embodiment, bodily intentionality, myth, phenomenologi- cal methodology In this article I will argue that Merleau-Ponty’s reinterpretation of Husserlian phenomenology—in particular as this was initially worked out in Phenomenology of Perception1—is premised methodologically on a certain mythic view of nature and of human embodiment in particular. I will claim, in other words, that the corporeal turn that is central to the philosophical attractiveness of Merleau-Pontian phenomenology rests upon a myth. journal of speculative philosophy, vol. 30, no. 3 , 2016 Copyright © 2016 The Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA merleau-ponty and the myth of human incarnation 383 Within the constraints of this short article, I will explain how and why this is so and consider some of the consequences that result.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy, Literature, and Everyday Life in the Second Sex: the Current Beauvoir Revnal
    PHILOSOPHY, LITERATURE, AND EVERYDAY LIFE IN THE SECOND SEX: THE CURRENT BEAUVOIR REVNAL In her interviews with Sartre, published posthumously in La Ceremonie des Adieux (Adieux: A Farewell to Sartre), Simone de Beauvoir largely seems to share Sartre's belief that philosophy is one thing, literature another. In these conversations of 1974, Sartre enumerates some of the differences: for example, philosophy, he claims, can be written with ease, even under the influence of drugs-he himself had consumed great quantities of Corydrane while composing his mammoth Critique ofDialectical Reason; good literature, on the other hand, usually requires aseries of drafts. 1 Both Sartre and Beauvoir appear to accept here a conventional distinction that is based on an essentialist conception of genres of writing, but it is one which in practice they continually put in question. My first aim in this essay is to challenge the distinction itself, at least in the rigid form in which Sartre and Beauvoir understand it. My second aim is to explore the basis of Beauvoir's position in light of what she says about philosophy in her important autobiographical The Prime ofLife. My third and final aim is to discuss the current Beauvoir revival, or rather first awakening of interest in Beauvoir as a philosopher that is reflected in numerous recent books, articles, conferences, and symposia and largely centers on The Second Sex. The Philosophy-Literature Dichotomy In accepting the conventional philosophy-literature dichotomy, Sartre and Beauvoir were insufficiently reflective. I will offer some narrative rather than formal arguments to support this claim. But first let me insist on what I am not arguing.
    [Show full text]
  • Merleau-Ponty and Transcendental Philosophy
    MERLEAU-PONTY AND TRANSCENDENTAL PHILOSOPHY Douglas Low In this essay I will respond to a number of more primary sentience) to ground rational issues raised by Steven Crowell's excellent es­ discourse. I will begin with a brief exposition say "The Project of Ultimate Grounding and of Merleau-Ponty's philosophy as it relates to the Appeal to Intersubjectivity in Recent Tran­ these issues and will then proceed to scendental Philosophy."' I will do so by using specifically address the issues as they are Merleau-Ponty's philosophy. Crowell makes a raised by Crowell in his essay. useful distinction "between two important ver­ In his Phenomenology of Perception, when sions of transcendental philosophy-the neo­ addressing the nature of the subject of experi­ Kantian version oriented toward justification ence, including the untenable nature of a tran­ of principles and the phenomenological ver­ scendental ego, Merleau-Ponty says, "the sub­ sion oriented toward clarification of meaning" ject of sensation is neither a thinker who takes (Crowell 31). Using Merleau-Ponty's philoso­ note of a quality, nor an inert setting which is phy, I will support the latter ( with some qualifi­ affected or changed by it, it is a power which is cation) and criticize the former: the only way born into, and simultaneously with, a certain to ground knowledge about experience is to existential environment, or is synchronized use experience itself, and, even though propo­ with it."2 The subject of sensation is not an ab­ nents of the first version have moved away stract intellectual consciousness or an inert from Kant's belief in an isolated rational tran­ setting but an embodied existential subject, an scendental subject, by way of the so-called embodied subject that is already and always a "linguistic turn," I will argue that they still un­ part of the world upon which it opens.
    [Show full text]
  • Dreaming Consciousness in Phenomenology and Depth Psychology
    Journal of Experiential Psychotherapy, vol. 22, no 3 (87) September 2019 Dreaming Consciousness in Phenomenology and Depth Psychology Csaba Szummer*i, Attila Almási**ii, Iszáj Fruzsina*iii *Institute of Psychology, Faculty of Humanities, Károli Gáspár University of the Reformed Church in Hungary **Multidisciplinary for Psychedelic Studies, Hungary Abstract Introduction: Freud and Jung delve deep into the study of dreams and other phenomena occurring in altered states of consciousness. Edmund Husserl, the founding father of phenomenology, on the contrary, neglects mental activity in altered states of consciousness, and primarily describes mental functioning from the perspective of normal, waking consciousness. Objectives: The purpose of this comparative study is to show that a productive dialogue might be possible between phenomenology and Freudian and Jungian psychology, in their research in mental activities occurring in altered states of consciousness. Methods: First, the concepts of the unconscious of phenomenology and of depth psychology are compared. Then, the obstacles to the phenomenological analysis of dreams are enumerated. Afterwards, the Freudian and Jungian dream theories are contrasted. Finally, the Jungian active imagination is addressed from the vantage point of the phenomenological concept of phantasy. Results: Although mental processes form a continuum, until the last two decades, they were treated separately in phenomenology and depth psychology. Phenomenology specialized itself in normal awake state of consciousness, in which the various functional organizations of the human mind act in concert subordinated to and controlled by a virtual center. Freud, Jung and their disciples, on the other hand, focused on states in which consciousness is cut off from the outer world (hypnosis, dreaming, psychotic hallucinations), or the subject suspends – to a certain degree – its interest in the environment (day-dreaming and active imagination).
    [Show full text]