The Critique of Power
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Critical Theory and Authoritarian Populism.Pp
CHAPTER 3 Understanding Right and Left Populism 1 Samir Gandesha We appear to be living in an age of populism. Over the past two decades, we have witnessed the rise of right-wing populist parties throughout Europe such as Haider’s Freedom Party in Austria, Victor Orban’s Fidesz Party in Hungary, and the Polish Law and Justice Party. Such an emergence hasn’t been confined to Europe but is a global phenomenon as evinced, for example, by the elec- toral triumphs of Narendra Modi in India in 2014 and that of Recep Tayyip Erdogan in Turkey as early as 2003. But no phenomena more clearly supports- this thesis than the stunning victory of Donald J. Trump in the 2016 American presidential election and the triumph of the Leave Campaign led by the United Kingdom Independence Party (UKIP). But there has also been a populism of the Left. The Arab Spring was widely regarded as a broad-based, if short-lived, popular revolt and therefore as a kind of populism in the streets in 2011. The events of Tahrir Square profoundly in- spired the Occupy Movement – sparked by the editor of the Vancouver-based magazine Ad Busters’ exhortation – to ‘Occupy Wall Street!’ Radiating out be- yond Zuccotti Park, the movement spread through much of the Western world. Arguably, the Occupy Movement’s most significant and enduring effect was to be felt five years later in the dramatic grassroots support for Vermont Senator Bernie Sanders’ bid for the Democratic Party’s Presidential nomination, which was – as recent juridical proceedings have revealed – undermined by the actions of the DNC. -
Theory by Overcoming the So-Called Pessimism of the Dialecticof Enlightenment
Propriety of the Erich Fromm Document Center. For personal use only. Citation or publication of material prohibited without express written permission of the copyright holder. Eigentum des Erich Fromm Dokumentationszentrums. Nutzung nur für persönliche Zwecke. Veröffentlichungen – auch von Teilen – bedürfen der schriftlichen Erlaubnis des Rechteinhabers. From Honneth to Fromm Seiki Okazaki I Introduction As is well known, Jiirgen Habermas opens up the frontiers of "radical democracy" in the history of critical theory by overcoming the so-called pessimism of The Dialecticof Enlightenment. It is Axel Honneth who takes over the political orientation from Habermas, who nevertheless criticizes Habermas's language-theoretic version of communication paradigm and advocates his own recognition-theoretic version of communication paradigm. In The Fragmented World of the Social (1995), Honneth refers to "four thematic domains" of his post-Habermasian critical theory (Honneth 1995, pp. xiii-xxv): (A) "everydaymoral experience" connected with a "struggle for recognition"; (B) relation between "work" and "recognition"; (C) "pathologies of modern society" having nothing to do with the problem of "rationality"; and (D) "psychoanalytic concept of the subject." I find potentialities in Honneth's critical theory in that it will contribute to elucidatemany problems on which Habermas fails to shed light. However, in spite of its attractiveness, there exists a crucial difficulty in Honneth's critical theory. In this article I would like to attempt to overcome the difficulty of Honneth's critical theory through the dialogue with one of the most important critical theorists, Erich Fromm (1900-1980). While he had been "a member of staff who had for a considerable time been the most significant one for its theoretical work" (1), Fromm was excluded from the Institute for Social Research, partly because of the opposition to Adorno. -
Curriculum Vitae
Curriculum Vitae SANTIAGO ZABALA ICREA Research Professor at the Pompeu Fabra University Director of UPF Center for Vattimo’s Archives and Philosophy Prof. Dr. Santiago Zabala ICREA Research Professor Pompeu Fabra University Department of Humanities Ramon Trias Fargas, 25-27 (office 20.238) 08005 Barcelona Catalonia (Spain) [Tel.] +34 93 542 1636 [Fax.] +34 93 542 16 20 Web Page: www.santiagozabala.com Email: [email protected] Date of Birth, 27th June 1975. Passport (Italian): YA0042314 ICREA Research Professor | ORCID-ID | ScopusID | ResearcherID (Web of Science) | Google Scholar Profile | UPF Scientific output AREA OF SPECIALIZATION Aesthetics, Continental Philosophy, Hermeneutics, Political Philosophy. Butler, Derrida, Gadamer, Heidegger, Rorty, Tugendhat, Vattimo. AREAS OF COMPETENCE Analytic Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion, Phenomenology, Pragmatism, Arendt, Marx, Latour, Lévinas, Ricoeur, Wittgenstein, Žižek. EDUCATION Pontifical Lateran University of Rome, Ph.D., Philosophy (summa cum laude), 2006 Dissertation: The Remains of Being: Hermeneutic Ontology after Metaphysics Dissertation Committee: Antonio Livi (Chair), Philip Larrey, Leonardo Messinese. University of Turin, Laurea, Philosophy, 2002 Dissertation: The Hermeneutic Nature of Analytic Philosophy. A study of Ernst Tugendhat Dissertation Committee: Gianni Vattimo (Chair), Giuseppe Riconda, Ugo Ugazio. International Schools of Vienna - Geneva, International Baccalaureate, 1995 Languages, English, German, Italian, Spanish, French, Catalan. AWARDS AND HONORS - Accreditation of Advanced Research – issued by AQU Catalunya, 2019. - Alexander von Humboldt Post-Doctoral Fellowship in Philosophy at the University of Potsdam, 2008-9. PUBLICATIONS A. Authored Books - Being at Large: Freedom in the Age of Alternative Facts, Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2020. Santiago Zabala Vitae 2 - Spanish translation by Belen Nasini, El ser anda suelto. -
Ethics of Recognition: Axel Honneth's Normative Critique of Modern Society
Journal of Critical Reviews ISSN- 2394-5125 Vol 7, Issue 11, 2020 ETHICS OF RECOGNITION: AXEL HONNETH’S NORMATIVE CRITIQUE OF MODERN SOCIETY John Paul J. Petrola University of San Agustin, Iloilo City, Philippines [email protected] Received: 11.03.2020 Revised: 18.04.2020 Accepted: 12.05.2020 Abstract This paper is an expose of Axel Honneth’s theory of recognition. Using document analysis and hermeneutics of Axel Honneth’s seminal works and other resources on social pathology and struggle for recognition, this paper attempts to provide a deeper interpretation of Honneth 's theory of recognition as it tries to address the context of Honneth's critical theory, its three spheres of recognition, namely affection, rights and unity, which are required in order to gain concrete self-relationship, and its principle of disrespect as the spiritual grammar of the disenfranchised in the struggle for recognition. Furthermore, it offers a new alternative in doing critical analysis of the society. Keywords: Axel Honneth, Critical theory, Love, Rights, Solidarity, Modern Society © 2020 by Advance Scientific Research. This is an open-access article under the CC BY license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/) DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.31838/jcr.07.11.30 INTRODUCTION These are requisites in synthesizing a background on Honneths ethical life and recognition are two key concepts of Hegel critical social theory and his concepts of the spheres of borrowed by Honneth in developing the theory of the struggle for recognition. recognition. As elucidated by Hegel, according to Deranty, the term ‘absolute ethical life’ entails the full development of the Lastly, I will present Honneths concept of disrespect or denial of individual’s theoretical and practical capacities, as well as the full recognition, and how it becomes the moral grammar of the development of social interactions [3]. -
Appeal Signed by 50 European Intellectuals, July 2018
Appeal signed by 50 European intellectuals, July 2018 Published in French Newspaper Liberation Reconciliation in the Balkans: A Call to Support the Prespes Agreement The historic Agreement of June 17 2018 signed in the Prespes lakes between Greece and the (Former Yugoslav Republic of Macedonia (FYROM) brings to an end an international dispute which had been festering for the last 25 years. It defines the political, historical and cultural boundaries between classical Greek Macedonia and as of now, North Macedonia, by making it clear that the Macedonian identity can be shared between people who endow it with different meanings. It respects the dignity and the right to self-determination of the two peoples and confirms the desire of both countries for peaceful coexistence. To achieve this, each side has had to address the concerns of the other side. North Macedonia obtained the recognition of the existence of a Macedonian language as part of the Slavic family of languages (a fact long recognized by the UN and Greece) the designation of the nationality as Macedonian/Citizens of North Macedonia, and crucially, the promise of starting accession negotiations to NATO and the EU in the very near future. Greece obtained the geographical designation in the compound new name, its application both domestically and internationally (erga omnes), and the requirement that the constitution of FYROM be amended accordingly. When completed, this legally binding international agreement will have resolved an issue of contested political identity, so common in multicultural societies, and will offer a model for future resolution of other protracted conflicts. But the agreement still faces major hurdles in both countries where the hard liners and extremists are mobilizing against it. -
On the Consistency of Axel Honneth's Critical Theory
[The published version of this paper is available in Philosophical Forum, 49 (4), 2018, p. 483-509. Online at: https://doi.org/10.1111/phil.12203] On the consistency of Axel Honneth’s critical theory: Methodology, critique, and current struggles for recognition. Marco Angella. Introduction Drawing upon the tradition of the Frankfurt School critical social theory, over the decades Axel Honneth (2009a) has been developing one of the most fully-structured paradigms of recognition in the field of social philosophy, whose methodology he accurately reconstructs. In the first part of the paper, I will examine Honneth’s recognition paradigm insofar as it enables him to renovate this methodological framework. My examination has the specific objective to support a twofold hypothesis. On the one hand, I aim to outline a defense of Honneth’s consistent methodology against growing criticisms – especially, but not exclusively, related to recent appraisal of Freedom’s Right – which tend to see depletion of critical insights in the recent developments of his theory as compared with the results obtained in his early works1. Unlike these critics, I contend that Honneth’s work is (methodologically) compatible with the Frankfurt school’s tradition and retains (and to a certain extent extends) its critical insights 1 See the recent special issue of Critical Horizons dedicated to Freedom’s Right, especially Freyenhagen (2015) and Schaub (2015). (Deranty 2009, pp. 449-456). On the other hand, I aim to propose a critical appraisal of interpretations of Honneth’s theory that, while more sympathetic towards it (or at least toward a specific period of its development), attempts to indicate the ways in which he could have strengthened his critique of contemporary society. -
On the “Post-Religious” Political Theology of Walter Benjamin
Messianism without Delay: On the “Post-religious” Political Theology of Walter Benjamin Giacomo Marramao 1. The interpretive key to Walter Benjamin’s “Theses On the Philosophy of History” which I intend to bring to light, can be deliberately and provocatively expressed in the title: “Mes- sianism without Delay.” This is literally a para-doxical title which seemingly contrasts with commonsense or current opinion with regard to those characteristics traditionally attributed to the “messianic.” How is it possible, in a literal sense, to have a messianism without “hori- zon of delay?” And does not the lack of a ‘wait’ constitute sufficient reason for dissolving the very tension implied in the concept of a “messiah” itself? It is my firm conviction that one finds hidden here the secret cipher of a text – at once translucent and enigmatic – which can only be thoroughly grasped by reconstructing the multi-polar constellations of its con- ceptual and symbolic referents. That is, one cannot interpret its radical political-theological core simply as a “secularized” version of messianism (as occurs in the philosophies of history criticized by Karl Lowith¨ 1): Benjamin’s brand of messianism is in equal measure post-secular and post-religious. In short, the paradox of Benjamin’s message of redemption lies in its position on the other side of the ambiguous Janus profile of western Futurism. It is symbolized, on the one hand, by the promise of salvation in monotheistic religions and, on the other, by the modern philosophy of history’s faith in progress. Hence, I will try to illustrate how the singular figure of a “messianism without delay” is tied to the proposal of a “concept of history” not after the end of history, but rather, after the end of the faith in history. -
PHIL 452/652, EP&E 231 Recognition
PHIL 452/652, EP&E 231 Recognition: Intersubjectivity in Moral and Political Philosophy Fall 2011 Class Hours: Wednesdays 3:30 PM – 5:20 PM Class Location: Bass Library L73 Course Website: On the ClassesV2 server Instructors: Stephen Darwall ([email protected]) CT Hall 306 Office Hours – Thursday 12:00 Noon – 2:00 pm (and by appt) Matthew Noah Smith ([email protected]) CT Hall 106 Office Hours – Tuesday 1:00 pm – 3:00 pm (and by appt) Mailboxes: Connecticut Hall 101 Course Description: This course explores a central issue in moral philosophy: the normative structure of the relationship between moral equals. Following a practice of post-Kantian German idealists, we call this relationship recognition. Recognition is the relationship manifested when two moral equals see and relate to each other as having the standing to make reciprocal moral claims on one another. While we explore questions about the psychological structure of this stance – is it cognitive or conative, for example – our main focus will be on the moral structure of the relationship between moral equals. This course begins with a study of the emergence of philosophical attention to recognition, which occurred at the headwaters of early modern moral and political theory in sixteenth and seventeenth Centuries. Much of this philosophical work focused on property rights. We will likely read works by Francisco Suarez, Samuel Pufendorf, and Hugo Grotius, to name a few important figures. We will then turn to close examination of the role of recognition in the work of Adam Smith, Kant, and post-Kantian German idealists. -
Texas A&M University Department of Hispanic Studies
Texas A&M University Department of Hispanic Studies Academic Program Review Self-Study Document October 2017 Texas A&M University Academic Program Review (APR) Table of Contents Peer Review Team Charge ........................................................................................................... 3 Overview of the Program ............................................................................................................. 4 EXECUTIVE SUMMARY OF THE SELF-STUDY REPORT ............................................... 5 INTRODUCTION TO THE DEPARTMENT ........................................................................... 9 Program History and Background ............................................................................................ 10 Administrative Structure ........................................................................................................... 15 Department Staff ......................................................................................................................... 17 Department Resources................................................................................................................ 18 ANALYSIS .................................................................................................................................. 23 Mission, Strategic Plan, Goals, Objectives ............................................................................... 23 FACULTY PROFILE ............................................................................................................... -
Is There an Emancipatory Interest? an Attempt to Answer Critical Theory's Most Fundamental Question
DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12321 2016 MARK SACKS ANNUAL LECTURE Is there an emancipatory interest? An attempt to answer critical theory's most fundamental question Axel Honneth 1 | INTRODUCTION The idea that human beings have a deep‐seated interest in overcoming dependencies and heteronomy has always been a hallmark of the tradition of critical social theory deriving from Marx. Some of the Left Hegelians already held that in the absence of such an emancipatory interest on the part of the entire species, the demand for social progress would remain a merely moral “ought,” lacking any support in historical reality. Marx was convinced that under capitalism, this interest was represented by the proletariat, forced by its particular situation to fight on behalf of all of humanity for fully noncoercive and nondominating social relations.1 When Georg Lukács took up this thought in the early 1920s, even surpassing its original ambitions through a bold appropriation of Fichtean ideas, the revolution- ary ethos of the working class had already been in decline to such an extent that his construction received little acclaim even from those sympathetic to it.2 Max Horkheimer was therefore cautious enough to rely in his develop- ment of a critical social theory only on the claim that such an emancipatory interest was revealed in the ineradicable human tendency to revolt against structures of domination. Without attempting to provide a more detailed argument for this assumption, he thereby reiterated on a more abstract level the Marxian thesis that the epistemological foun- dation of his theory would have to lie in its connection with “critical conduct.”3 It was only with Jürgen Habermas's path‐breaking monograph Knowledge and Human Interests that new life was breathed into this century‐old idea. -
O Ser Humano Na Era Da Técnica the Human Being in the Age of Technique
O Ser Humano na Era da Técnica The human being in the age of technique Umberto Galimberti Resumo A técnica, comumente considerada uma “ferramenta” à disposição do ser humano, tornou-se, hoje, o verdadeiro “sujeito” da história; o ser humano executa o papel de “funcionário” de seus equipamentos, cumpre aquelas ações descritas e prescritas no rol de “tarefas” das ferramentas e coloca sua personalidade entre parênteses em favor da funcionalidade. Se, então, a técnica passou a ser o sujeito da história e o ser humano seu servo obediente, o humanismo pode ser dado por concluído, e as categorias hu- manísticas, que até agora nós adotamos para ler a história, se tornam insuficientes para interpretar a época iniciada com a era da técnica. Palavras-chave: técnica, humanismo, natureza. Abstract Often we have considered the technique as a “tool” available to the human being, when, instead, the technique has now become the true “subject” of history; the man was reduced to the role of “employee” of their equipment. Within them must fulfill the described and prescribed actions that make up the list of “tasks”, while his personality is bracketed in favor of its functionality. If, then, the technique has become the subject of history and the human being his obedient servant, humanism can be terminated, and the humanistic categories, which until now we have adopted to read the story became insufficient to interpret the period that began at the age of technique. Keywords: technique, humanism, nature. O Ser Humano na Era da Técnica Umberto Galimberti ano 13 • nº 218 • vol. 13 • 2015 • ISSN 1679-0316 Tradução: Sandra Dall’Onder Revisão: Ramiro Mincato Cadernos IHU ideias é uma publicação quinzenal impressa e digital do Instituto Humanitas Unisinos – IHU que apresenta artigos produzidos por palestrantes e convidados(as) dos eventos promovidos pelo Instituto, além de artigos inéditos de pesquisadores em diversas universidades e instituições de pesquisa. -
Situating Axel Honneth in the Frankfurt School Tradition
CHAPTER ONE SITUATING AXEL HONNETH IN THE FRANKFURT SCHOOL TRADITION Joel Anderson I have never had the intention of continuing the tradition of a school … e line of thought that gets attributed, in retrospect, to the Frankfurt School was a response to historically specic experiences with fascism and Stalinism, but above all to the incomprehensible Holocaust. A tradition of thought remains vital by proving its essential intuitions in the light of new experiences; that doesn’t happen without giving up those parts of theories that are no longer adequate. Jürgen Habermas1 Historical mantles are rarely worn comfortably. e associated expec- tations can be quite a burden. So it is not surprising that, like Jürgen Habermas, Axel Honneth refrains from identifying himself as a ‘Frankfurt School’ theorist. In his case, however, there is really no denying the lineage. Not only is he the successor to Habermas’ chair in social philosophy at the University of Frankfurt, but as research direc- tor of the Institute for Social Research there, he sits in the oce that was once eodor Adorno’s. At Honneth’s insistence, however, the old furniture has all been replaced. Insofar as the Frankfurt School tradition represents a contempo- rary phenomenon at all, it is a diverse approach that has been con- stantly developing and changing over its eighty-year history. My aim here is not to provide a denitive account of this lineage – nor to sort out which members of subsequent generations have ‘betrayed’ the tradition – but rather to situate Honneth’s own work historically, so as to highlight certain distinctive features of his approach and provide 1 J.