55 Fateful Images ALPHONSO LINGIS the Pennsylvania State University

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

55 Fateful Images ALPHONSO LINGIS the Pennsylvania State University Fateful Images ALPHONSO LINGIS The Pennsylvania State University Reality and its Appearances Phenomenology, Jean-Paul Sartre wrote, reduced the reality of things to the totality of their appearances. It is because something appears that we can assert that it exists. It belongs to the essence of a real thing to generate appearances. And the appearances are appearances of things. Appearances do not flow by, a drifting fog of tones and hues; they separate into identifiable units, gestalten. To be outside our minds belongs to the things, and their appearances are outside. We do not see patterns suspended in the inner space of the mind, but the colors, sizes, shapes of outside things. The real thing itself-the chair or the building caught sight of in its fragmentary appearances- is not something invisible, or conceptual, not an identity-term posited by the mind; it is the totality as sketched out in any of its appear- ances. Any of its appearances implicate further appearances: we see how the surface exposed in front of us implicates and is continued by a back side, an underside. The chair or a building exists in a wave of duration across which it evolves perspectival profiles of itself. Yet not all the appearances a thing generates show it as it really is. Natural perception itself, Maurice Merleau-Ponty pointed out, distin- guishes between the real properties of things and their perspectival deformations, appearances distorted by the intervening medium or obscured by the distance, colors seen in dim or colored light, shapes 55 56 set askew. The real properties appear in the thing when the thing itself is within reach, set at the right distance and position, accessible to our multiple sensory and motor powers. Other appearances appear not as false or illusory (or mentally fabricated) but as transitional: they lead to the real thing and its real characteristics, and disappear when they appear. The flattened oval shape of the dinner plate seen on the shelf leads to and merges into the circular form which spreads out all the patterns of the plate equally before our view, as monocular images fade out before the integral appearance of an object set at explorable distance from our eyes. Formal and Substantial Appearances of Real Things The apprehension of the real features and natures of things is an ac- tion. It is when we position ourselves before a thing, and position it before us, such that its surfaces are visible throughout and their colors and textures observable, and its overall structure is surveyable that the thing appears to be a unit that holds together. This positioning, this manipulation is a primary form of understanding. The construction of a scientific representation of the universe proceeds out of an action of isolating substances and discovering their properties by putting them in reaction with other substances; and it is predictive; it issues in tech- nological transformations. Since we uncover and discover things by manipulation, are the things anything but manipulanda? Things are not only forms but also forces- their forms are dynamic forms. The hammer's form is the ways its force of resistance or drive fits in with other things-with the grip of the hand of the user and with the other things movable, breakable, or assemblable with its force. A thing thus reduces to the unity of its "properties"-which are in fact modes of appropriateness; and phenomenological ontology establishes a relational conception in place of the ancient substantive definition of things, taken, since Hume, to be metaphysical. But, Emmanuel Levinas points out, things do not momentarily take form in the unarticulated elements, in the flow of light and shadow, heat and damp, along the ground, with the specific function the ma- nipulating hand simultaneously outlines and makes use of. It is be- cause they are already there, detachable substances, in themselves and at our disposal, that we can envision uses for them. Use presupposes possession. The clearly delimited contours that constitute a piece of reality as a thing mark out the way it is separate from or detachable from other things. Because a thing's form, its closed surfaces, makes .
Recommended publications
  • Maurice Merleau-Ponty,The Visible and the Invisible
    Northwestern University s t u d i e s i n Phenomenology $ Existential Philosophy GENERAL EDITOR John Wild. ASSOCIATE EDITOR James M. Edie CONSULTING EDITORS Herbert Spiegelberg William Earle George A. Schrader Maurice Natanson Paul Ricoeur Aron Gurwitsch Calvin O. Schrag The Visible and the Invisible Maurice Merleau-Ponty Edited by Claude Lefort Translated by Alphonso Lingis The Visible and the Invisible FOLLOWED BY WORKING NOTES N orthwestern U n i v e r s i t y P r e s s 1968 EVANSTON Northwestern University Press www.nupress.northwestern.edu Originally published in French under the title Le Visible et l'invisible. Copyright © 1964 by Editions Gallimard, Paris. English translation copyright © 1968 by Northwestern University Press. First printing 1968. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America 15 14 13 12 11 ISBN-13: 978-0-8101-0457-0 isbn-io: 0-8101-0457-1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication data are available from the Library of Congress Permission has been granted to quote from Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes (New York: The Philosophical Library, 1956). @ The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences— Permanence o f Paper for Printed Library Materials, ansi Z39.48-1992. Contents Editor’s Foreword / xi Editorial Note / xxxiv T ranslatofs Preface / xl T h e Visib l e a n d t h e In v is ib l e : Philosophical Interrogation i Reflection and Interrogation / 3 a Interrogation and Dialectic / 50 3 Interrogation and Intuition / 105 4 The Intertwining—The Chiasm / 130 5 [a ppen d ix ] Preobjective Being: The Solipsist World / 156 W orking N otes / 165 Index / 377 Chronological Index to Working Notes / 279 Editor's Foreword How eve r e x p e c t e d it may sometimes be, the death of a relative or a friend opens an abyss before us.
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Illusions Alphonso Lingis Pennsylvania State University - State College, [email protected]
    Fordham University Masthead Logo DigitalResearch@Fordham Hermeneutic and Phenomenological Philosophies Research Resources of Science 2005 Divine Illusions Alphonso Lingis Pennsylvania State University - State College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_research Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Lingis, Alphonso, "Divine Illusions" (2005). Research Resources. 29. https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_research/29 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Hermeneutic and Phenomenological Philosophies of Science at DigitalResearch@Fordham. It has been accepted for inclusion in Research Resources by an authorized administrator of DigitalResearch@Fordham. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DIVINE ILLUSIONS ALPHONSO LINGIS David Allison says to his readers that Nietzsche writes for you — you and him and me. In his book he tells of what of Nietzsche’s thoughts he has, with long years of research and penetrating and generous reflection, made his own. The lucidity of this book enables us to see if these thoughts can also become ours. Nietzsche’s thoughts are not only extremely complex but hard thoughts which we cannot make our own without a struggle. The finest virtue of a philosophical book on Nietzsche is that it provokes this struggle. Here I am only going to recount a little of my struggle with a couple of those thoughts, in the expectation that David Allison will shed more light on them. Nietzsche’s insists on the illusory nature of art. Apollonian art — plastic art, poetry, sculpture, and architecture — is the art of forms, perfect, self- contained, radiant forms.
    [Show full text]
  • The Horizons of Continental Philosophy Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library Volume 30
    THE HORIZONS OF CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY MARTINUS NIJHOFF PHILOSOPHY LIBRARY VOLUME 30 For a complete list of volumes in this series see final page of this volume. The Horizons of Continental Philosophy Essays on Husser!, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty edited by Hugh J. Silverman State University of New York at Stony Brook Algis Mickunas Ohio University Theodore Kisiel Northern Illinois University Alphonso Lingis The Pennsylvania State University 1988 SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data The Horizons Qf continental phllosophy essays on Husserl, Heidegger, and Merleau-Ponty I editors, Hugh J. Silverman ... [et al. 1. p. cm. -- (Martinus Nljhoff phi losophy l ibrary ; v. 30) Inc ludes index. ISBN 978-90-481-8308-1 ISBN 978-94-017-3350-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-017-3350-2 1. Philosophy, Modern--20th century . 2. Husserl, Edmund. 1859-1938. 3. Heidegger, Martin, 1889-1976. 4. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 1908-1961. 1. Silverman, Hugh J. II. Series. B804.H726 1988 190--dc19 87-33798 CIP ISBN 978-90-481-8308-1 Copyright © 1988 by Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Origina11y published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1988 An rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written permis sion of the publishers, Springer-Science+Business Media, B.V. PUBLICATIONS BOARD General Editor Hugh J. Silverman Volume Editors Algis Mickunas (Husserl Circle) Theodore Kisiel (Heidegger Conference) Alphonso Lingis (~lerleau-Ponty Circle) Publications Committee Members Theodore Ki s i e1 Alphonso Lingis Al gi s Mi ckunas John Sallis Hugh J.
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL 475 – Topics in Contemporary European Philosophy Mon & Wed 2:35-3:55 SH688 295
    PHIL 475 – Topics in Contemporary European Philosophy Mon & Wed 2:35-3:55 SH688 295 Dr. Erica Harris ([email protected]) Office hours: LEA 923, Wed 1:00 – 2:00 p.m. (or by appointment) Course topic and objectives Topic Fall 2017: Other Bodies A major concern of phenomenologists of the early twentieth century was the so-called ‘problem of the other’. These philosophers were concerned with questions like: how do I know that the object standing in front of me is another subject like myself (Husserl)? How does the freedom of others limit my own (Sartre and Beauvoir)? What, if anything, do I owe this strange person (Levinas)? How does encountering another person change the way I see myself? The existential philosophers – especially Sartre and Beauvoir – often described the encounter with the other as one filled with shame, and antagonism. In his play, No Exit, Sartre famously said “Hell is other people.” Merleau-Ponty, a phenomenologist who studied and worked alongside the existentialists, took a different approach to the encounter with others. His approach is grounded in the larger framework of his embodied phenomenology. In this course, we will consider how highlighting the importance of embodiment has changed the way that continental philosophy has approached the ‘problem’ of otherness. This course will be divided into two parts. In the first half of the course, we will juxtapose Merleau- Ponty’s embodied account of empathy with Sartre’s existentialist view. Students will read Sartre’s No Exit, followed by selections from Merleau-Ponty’s seminal work from the first part of his career, The Phenomenology of Perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Writing 'With'
    There are three related points I want to make about tact. First, through the limit marked by the touch of bodies my body is open and unfinished such that it owes its life to the blood of others it may now reject as foreign. I have a responsibility (to the life and value of my own body and those of others) to extend my hand to the other and welcome, with tact, that difference and the signification it brings. For, to paraphrase Nietzsche, the blood of another and the signs it gives can only survive if it is re-animated by the touch that it provokes: ‘it is only our blood that constrains them to speak to us’ and we honour the expressions of other bodies ‘less by that barren timidity that allows every word … to remain intact than by energetic endeavours to aid them continually to new life’.38 The body, singular and communal, signifies and lives through the ‘interlacing, the mixing of bodies with bodies’39 and what this relies on being, thinking, is treating the other’s uniqueness with tact. Yet, and second, this welcome of the other’s difference is always conditional in two senses. The welcome is conditional in the sense that, writing ‘with’ as the sharing of meaning is two-way or reversible, so is the responsibility for maintaining NIKKI SULLIVAN the limit and hence the difference between bodies. There is no obligation here to welcome a body that lacks tact, that already negates my expression of existence, that presents as a hand that grasps or as a clenched fist.
    [Show full text]
  • Totality and Infinity Tot Ality and Infinity an Essa Y on Exteriority
    TOTALITY AND INFINITY TOT ALITY AND INFINITY AN ESSA Y ON EXTERIORITY by EMMANUEL LEVINAS translated hy ALPHONSO LINGIS .. KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS DORDRECHT I BOSTON I LONDON Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data ISBN-13: 978-94-009-9344-0 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-9342-6 DOI: 10.1007/978-94-009-9342-6 Published by Kluwer Academic Publishers, P.O. Box 17,3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Kluwer Academic Publishers incorporates the publishing programmes of D. Reidel, Martinus Nijhoff, Dr W. Junk and MTP Press. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In aII other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Originally published in French: Emmanuel Levinas, Tota/ite et infini: essai sur [' exteriorite, Martinus Nijhoff, La Haye, 1961, 5th ed. 1988, xviii + 284 pp, ISBN 90-247-5105-5 PHAENOMENOLOGICA 8. First printing 1969, Martinus NijhoffPublishers and Duquesne University Press. Second printing 1979, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and Duquesne University Press. Third printing 1991, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed on acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 1991 Kluwer Academic Publishers Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover 4th edition 1991 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, includ ing photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permis sion from the copyright owner. To Marcelle and Jean Wahl TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION 11 PREFACB • 21 SECTION 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Vital Powers: Cultivating a Critter Community
    Phenomenology & Practice, Volume 12 (2018), No. 2, pp. 15-27. Vital Powers: Cultivating a Critter Community Dr. Stephen J. Smith, Professor, Faculty of Education, Associate Dean, Faculty of Health Sciences, Simon Fraser University Email: [email protected] Abstract This paper is based on the eco-pedagogical aspiration to live with domesticated animals in accordance with Alphonso Lingis's Community of those who have nothing in common. I draw upon this remarkable text as well as Lingis's animal writings in describing moments and movements of pathic community. Such a community in affective affiliation with one another, where symbiotic relations are possible and bodily kinships are exercised, exemplifies what is possible in more rational human communities where domesticating impulses seek to harness the vital powers of co- constitutive life. Of telling significance are predatory threats, the manner in which they appear, and the protectionist responses they occasion. By recasting these threats and responses in terms of motional affordances, it may well be possible to move with non-human creatures, both literally and figuratively, beyond the anthropocentric confines of domestication. Animals with whom we appear to have nothing specifically, or in species terms, in common can show us how to cultivate more pathic communities of our own kind. Introduction Alphonso Lingis's animal writings inspire an ecological imagination of how we as a human species of metamorphic proportions have taken on the multiplicity of the flock, the school, the herd, and the pack. Our communal lives may at times appear of a mob mentality bound by animal drives, however there is contagious enthusiasm generated in particular group affiliations, feelings of solidarity that come with compelling community engagements, and a sense of belonging engendered when working alongside others for a common cause.
    [Show full text]
  • LEVINAS and the TRIPLE CRITIQUE of HEIDEGGER Graham Harman
    LEVINAS AND THE TRIPLE CRITIQUE OF HEIDEGGER Graham Harman As twentieth century philosophy fades into of purposes, but close off in themselves, with a the distance, Martin Heidegger seems to be sort of inviolable integrity apart from all net- standing the test of time. His stature in conti- worksorfunctions.Humansalwaysstand nental philosophy is beyond question, and somewhere in particular, bathing in the mate- those French thinkers who avoid his influence rial reality of wind, water, and stars, not to most noticeably (such as Alain Badiou and mention hammers and cigarettes, none of them Gilles Deleuze) are often difficult for precisely entirely used up by their assignment to wider this reason, since it is Heidegger who has purposes. It is often forgotten that this second shaped our vision of philosophy more than criticism of Heidegger is the basis for the first: anyone else. Even analytic philosophers have for in Totality and Infinity, it is “separation” begun to find useful insights in Heidegger’s that paves the way for exteriority and transcen- works, while no analytic thinker has a compa- dence.1 rable influence in the other direction—not In this article, I will claim that there is also a even Wittgenstein. As the dust settles on the third critique of Heidegger to be found in past hundred years of philosophy, it is Levinas, one more closely related to the sec- Heidegger who looms as the ancestor whose ond than to the first. As Alphonso Lingis has influence we most need to absorb and resist. lucidly observed,2 Levinas gives us a new defi- No one has seen this more clearly than Em- nition of individual substance without relaps- manuel Levinas.
    [Show full text]
  • Gilles Deleuze and Alphonso Lingis
    Filosofija ir menas ISSN 1392-8600 E-ISSN 1822-7805 Žmogus ir žodis / Filosofija Man and the Word / Philosophy 2017, t. 19, Nr. 4, p. 44–66 / Vol. 19, No. 4, pp. 44–66, 2017 Two Notions of Vulnerable and Intensely Affected Body: Gilles Deleuze and Alphonso Lingis Laura Galvanauskienė Lithuanian University of Educational Sciences, Department of Education and Philosophy, Studentų St. 39, Vilnius, [email protected] Summary. Two different approaches towards Francis Bacon’s painting are analysed in the article: postmodern and phenomenological. The problematic and multiple status of such con- cepts as sensitive body, intensive sensation and the affect common for both Gilles Deleuze’s and Alphonso Lingis’ philosophy become most visible in regard to Bacon’s painting that displays the reality of the vulnerable and intensely affected body as his main subject. The article follows the main intrigue which inspires their studies, i.e. the article aims to explain what determines the suggestibility of Bacon’s canvas: is there the violence of line and colour, which negates the role of figuration (Deleuze) or the violence of life, that on the contrary, affirms representation (Lingis)? The author maintains that such different interpretations are determined by different notions of experience. Lingis emphasizes actual experience which allows to find the link between creation, lived body and life world, while Deleuze stresses virtual experience, impersonal life, body without organs and creation of new perspectives. Keywords: Bacon, body, figure, sensation, phenomenology, experience, violence. 44 Žmogus ir žodis / Filosofija / 2017, t. 19, Nr. 4 DOI: http://dx�doi�org/10�15823/zz�2017�16 ISSN 1392–8600 E-ISSN 1822–7805 Philosophy and Art Alphonso Lingis: from Embodied Subjectivity towards the Plastic or Transgressive Body The challenge to Deleuze’s experimental study of Bacon’s painting1 was posed by the Lithuanian-American phenomenologist Alphonso Lingis (b.
    [Show full text]
  • The Plastic Subject of Alphonso Lingis
    Janus Head 99 Bodies in Transit: The Plastic Subject of Alphonso Lingis Tom Sparrow Duquesne University Alphonso Lingis is the author of many books and renowned for his translations of Levinas, Merleau-Ponty, and Klossowski. By combining a rich philosophical training with an ex- tensive travel itinerary, Lingis has developed a distinctive brand of phenomenology that is only now beginning to gain critical attention. Lingis inhabits a ready-made language and conceptuality, but cultivates a style of thinking which disrupts and transforms the work of his predecessors, setting him apart from the rest of his field. This essay sketches Lingis’ phenomenology of sensation in order to give expression to some dimensions of Lingisian travel. As we see, Lingis deploys a theory of the subject which features the plasticity of the body, the materiality of affect, and the alimentary nature of sensation. One is born with forces that one did not contrive. One lives by giving form to these forces. The forms one gets from the others. — Alphonso Lingis, “We Mortals” A Synthetic Phenomenologist Alphonso Lingis is well-known in the Anglophone world for his transla- tions. We continental philosophers have all read his renderings of Levinas’ Totality and Infinity and Merleau-Ponty’s The Visible and the Invisible. He has also gained an admirable following with his philosophical travelogues, books like Excesses, Abuses, and Trust. In a way, even these texts offer us translations: of unfamiliar customs and peoples, of technical concepts and slippery philosophical jargon. In the travelogues, readers witness phenom- enological descriptions of individuals and cultures which are laced with the thinking of alterity familiar to Levinas’ readers, and the phenomenology of the lived body that Merleau-Ponty has handed down to the continental tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Visage, Figure: Reading Levinas's Totality and Infinity Author(S): Jill Robbins Source: Yale French Studies, No
    Visage, Figure: Reading Levinas's Totality and Infinity Author(s): Jill Robbins Source: Yale French Studies, No. 79, Literature and the Ethical Question (1991), pp. 135-149 Published by: Yale University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2930249 Accessed: 29-09-2015 09:34 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Yale University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Yale French Studies. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 193.108.160.146 on Tue, 29 Sep 2015 09:34:58 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions JILL ROBBINS Visage,Figure: Reading Levinas's Totalityand Infinity* What would it mean to facewhat Derridahas called "the ethics ofethics"? That is to say,to confrontthe veryopening of the question of ethics-the groundsof both its possibilityand impossibility-priorto the production and elaboration of all moral rules or precepts?According to Emmanuel Levinas,the face of the other[le visage dAutrui]is the verysite and privi- legedfigure for such an opening.In theface-to-face encounter, responsibility in its most originalform of response, or language-response, arises.
    [Show full text]
  • Martin Heidegger & a Politics of Care
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2016 The aP th Not Taken: Martin Heidegger & a Politics of Care Andrea Danielle Conque Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Conque, Andrea Danielle, "The aP th Not Taken: Martin Heidegger & a Politics of Care" (2016). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 1097. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/1097 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. THE PATH NOT TAKEN: MARTIN HEIDEGGER & A POLITICS OF CARE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Andrea Danielle Conque B.A., Louisiana Scholars’ College, 1999 M.A.L.A., Louisiana State University, 2001 M.A., Louisiana State University, 2002 May 2016 © 2016 Copyright Andrea D. Conque All rights reserved ii Acknowledgements There are many people without whom this dissertation would not have come to fruition. It has been a long, rewarding journey. I thank, first and foremost, my parents Judge Durwood and Rusti Conque for their continuing support over the years and in so many ways. For their intellectual guidance and friendship, I thank Drs.
    [Show full text]