Writing Duty: Religion, Obligation and Autonomy in George Eliot and Kant

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Writing Duty: Religion, Obligation and Autonomy in George Eliot and Kant University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Masters Theses Graduate School 8-2011 Writing Duty: Religion, Obligation and Autonomy in George Eliot and Kant Andrew Ragsdale Lallier [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_gradthes Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, and the English Language and Literature Commons Recommended Citation Lallier, Andrew Ragsdale, "Writing Duty: Religion, Obligation and Autonomy in George Eliot and Kant. " Master's Thesis, University of Tennessee, 2011. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_gradthes/993 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Masters Theses by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a thesis written by Andrew Ragsdale Lallier entitled "Writing Duty: Religion, Obligation and Autonomy in George Eliot and Kant." I have examined the final electronic copy of this thesis for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, with a major in English. Allen Dunn, Major Professor We have read this thesis and recommend its acceptance: Nancy Henry, Amy Billone Accepted for the Council: Carolyn R. Hodges Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) Writing Duty: Religion, Obligation and Autonomy in George Eliot and Kant A Thesis Presented for the Master of Arts Degree The University of Tennessee, Knoxville Andrew Ragsdale Lallier August 2011 Copyright © 2011 by Andrew R. Lallier. All rights reserved. ii I dedicate this thesis to my wife, Allison Miller, whose love and sympathy possess for me an incalculable value, and to my parents, Charles Wesley Lallier and Rebecca Anne Ragsdale Lallier, whose support and encouragement have always been there for me. iii Acknowledgments I would like to thank my thesis committee for their support and indulgence for this project. I owe a particular debt to Nancy Henry for reintroducing me to the works of George Eliot, for supporting me in preparing an article that provided some of the groundwork for this thesis, and for taking me on as a research assistant for her forthcoming biography, The Life of George Eliot. Allen Dunn‟s ready assistance and patient guidance have been essential in shaping and executing project, and are also greatly appreciated in pursuing a plurality of problems, critical and philosophical. I would also like to thank Amy Billone, whose interests and encouragement have been of great help in mapping out sites of engagement in nineteenth-century literature. iv ABSTRACT Connections between George Eliot and Immanuel Kant have been, for the most part, neglected. However, we have good reason to believe that Eliot not only read Kant (as well as many who were directly influenced by Kant), but substantially agreed with him on critical and moral issues. This thesis investigates one of the issues on which Kant and Eliot were most closely aligned, the need for duty in morality. Both the English novelist and the German philosopher upheld a vision of duty that could command absolutely while remaining consonant with human freedom and grounding a sense of moral dignity. This vision runs throughout the works of both writers, but is first developed and takes on a particular urgency in the works examined in this thesis, ranging from some of their early publications to Kant‟s Critique of Practical Reason and Eliot‟s Romola. The first chapter discusses duty in the wider context of debates about Divine Command Morality, in which the good is defined by its accord with the will or command of God, and which both Kant and Eliot resisted in formulating their own moral visions (while maintaining the language of law and command). This chapter also discusses evidence we have for Eliot‟s familiarity with Kant and establishes critical context for this paper. The second chapter discusses religion – in particular, religious enthusiasm – as a necessary background for duty, which exists in the absence of theological certitude, even as it seeks to preserve something of religion‟s capacity to command and its popular scope. Kant‟s path to the first Critique led through works foundational for, but also sometimes at odds with, the priorities and conclusions of critical science, and Eliot‟s first novel was preceded by a critical career that paints a quite different picture of religion than the sympathetic portrait of Dinah Morris. The third chapter deals with three dimensions of duty in Kant and Eliot, autonomy, reflection and respect, primarily through the second Critique and The Mill on the Floss. In the conclusion, I turn to Romola to illustrate the conflict and indeterminative power inherent in this conception of duty. v TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter I: Command and Context ...................................................................................... 1 Chapter II: Religion and Criticism .................................................................................... 28 Chapter III: Autonomy, Reflection and Respect ............................................................... 79 Conclusion ...................................................................................................................... 115 Works Cited .................................................................................................................... 121 Vita .................................................................................................................................. 129 vi Chapter 1: Command and Context Duty and Divine Command Morality Late into the Critique of Pure Reason, Immanuel Kant declares “All of my reason‟s interest (speculative as well as practical) is united the following three questions: 1. What can I know? 2. What ought I to do? 3. What may I hope?” (735). The focus of this thesis falls primarily on the second question, which is as much a statement about duty as a question concerning duty; i.e., both George Eliot and Kant presume that we do possess compelling moral obligations (there is something which I ought to do). The mentality which seeks after what one ought to do, knowing that such responsibility exists, already manifests a consciousness of duty, provided such a mentality neither submerges choice in submission to inclination, nor assumes the answer to be given in an arbitrary and external code. Kant‟s interrogative formulation and union of his three questions in a common interest should not be overlooked – duty, for both Eliot and Kant, is something requiring investigation (philosophical and literary), and questions about duty cannot be wholly separated from questions of knowledge and expectation. As Kant‟s Critique of Practical Reason explores the nature and implications of moral duty, Eliot‟s novels frequently take on duty as a central thematic and site for conflict and drama. These philosophical and literary investigations arise, in part, from the conclusions and developments of critical works preceding them, which destabilize prior religious certitudes even as they seek to maintain a space for meaningful morality. In an aphorism entitled “George Eliot” in Twilight of the Idols, Nietzsche writes “In England, one must rehabilitate oneself after every little emancipation from theology by showing in a veritably awe-inspiring manner what a moral fanatic one is” (The Portable Nietzsche 515, qtd. in Anger 92). In the same work, Nietzsche parenthetically identifies Kant as “a crafty 1 Christian, when all‟s said and done” (The Nietzsche Reader 464). Despite the apparent opposition between fanaticism and craft, one registers a similar sort of complaint being brought against both the English novelist and German philosopher: that the promise of liberation from theology incurs only a greater subjection to Christian morality. Nietzsche is anything but alone in this complaint – Kant had already been attacked on this account by Goethe, and Eliot‟s fall from favor in the early twentieth century was due in no small part to a moral seriousness that could come off as didacticism (Levine, “Introduction,” 1). Yet Nietzsche is indebted to a critical legacy running from Kant, through figures like Strauss and Feuerbach, to Eliot, their English translator – a legacy which surely played no small part in generating the intellectual climate in which Zarathustra could be surprised that the saint in the forest had not yet heard that God is dead. Distancing ourselves somewhat from Nietzsche‟s hostility, we can nonetheless affirm that religion forms a necessary background for understanding duty in George Eliot and Kant, and a background with which each writer has a complex relationship. Moreover, the terms Nietzsche employs get directly at the complexity of this relationship: both Eliot and Kant write in opposition to enthusiasm or fanaticism, yet both hold that there is something in morality which should inspire our awe. Likewise, rationality (satirized by Nietzsche as craft, and thus more the craft of Socrates than that of Odysseus) seems like a necessary component of morality – Eliot insists on the need for “intellect” to regulate “feeling,” as a means of correcting the evangelical excesses of Dr. Cumming, and Kant identifies practical reason and morality. Yet the prospect
Recommended publications
  • Part Four - 'Made in America: Christian Fundamentalism' Transcript
    Part Four - 'Made in America: Christian Fundamentalism' Transcript Date: Wednesday, 10 November 2010 - 2:00PM Location: Barnard's Inn Hall 10 November 2010 Made in America Christian Fundamentalism Dr John A Dick Noam Chomsky: “We must bear in mind that the U.S. is a very fundamentalist society, perhaps more than any other society in the world – even more fundamentalist than Saudi Arabia or the Taliban. That's very surprising.” Overview: (1) Introduction (2) Five-stage evolution of fundamentalism in the United States (3) Features common to all fundamentalisms (4) What one does about fundamentalism INTRODUCTION: In 1980 the greatly respected American historian, George Marsden published Fundamentalism and American Culture, a history of the first decades of American fundamentalism. The book quickly rose to prominence, provoking new studies of American fundamentalism and contributing to a renewal of interest in American religious history. The book’s timing was fortunate, for it was published as a resurgent fundamentalism was becoming active in politics and society. The term “fundamentalism” was first applied in the 1920’s to Protestant movements in the United States that interpreted the Bible in an extreme and literal sense. In the United States, the term “fundamentalism” was first extended to other religious traditions around the time of the Iranian Revolution in 1978-79. In general all fundamentalist movements arise when traditional societies are forced to face a kind of social disintegration of their way of life, a loss of personal and group meaning and the introduction of new customs that lead to a loss of personal and group orientation.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume and the Origin of Modern Rationalism Donald Livingston Emory University
    A Symposium: Morality Reconsidered David Hume and the Origin of Modern Rationalism Donald Livingston Emory University In “How Desperate Should We Be?” Claes Ryn argues that “morality” in modern societies is generally understood to be a form of moral rationalism, a matter of applying preconceived moral principles to particular situations in much the same way one talks of “pure” and “applied” geometry. Ryn finds a num- ber of pernicious consequences to follow from this rationalist model of morals. First, the purity of the principles, untainted by the particularities of tradition, creates a great distance between what the principles demand and what is possible in actual experience. The iridescent beauty and demands of the moral ideal distract the mind from what is before experience.1 The practical barriers to idealistically demanded change are oc- cluded from perception, and what realistically can and ought to be done is dismissed as insufficient. And “moral indignation is deemed sufficient”2 to carry the day in disputes over policy. Further, the destruction wrought by misplaced idealistic change is not acknowledged to be the result of bad policy but is ascribed to insufficient effort or to wicked persons or groups who have derailed it. A special point Ryn wants to make is that, “One of the dangers of moral rationalism and idealism is DONAL D LIVINGSTON is Professor of Philosophy Emeritus at Emory Univer- sity. 1 Claes Ryn, “How Desperate Should We Be?” Humanitas, Vol. XXVIII, Nos. 1 & 2 (2015), 9. 2 Ibid., 18. 44 • Volume XXVIII, Nos. 1 and 2, 2015 Donald Livingston that they set human beings up for desperation.
    [Show full text]
  • Duty-To-Protect.Pdf
    2 APA PRACTICE ORGANIZATION LEGAL ISSUES Duty to Protect A BRIEF HISTORY OF DUTY TO PROTECT In 1976, the California Supreme Court issued its decision in Tarasoff v. Regents of the University of Roles and Responsibilities for California after a patient carried out a threat to kill a Psychologists young woman. In that case, the court ruled: When a therapist determines, or pursuant to the ecent mass shootings heightened the focus on standards of his profession should determine, that widespread state laws that require or allow his patient presents a serious danger of violence psychologists and other mental health professionals R to another [person], he incurs an obligation to use to breach confidentiality in order to prevent harm by their reasonable care to protect the intended victim potentially violent patients. This article is intended to help against such danger . [This duty] may call for practitioners with the challenging task of applying these [the therapist] to warn the intended victim or duty to protect* laws in working with these individuals. others likely to apprise the victim of the danger, to notify the police, or take whatever other steps are Mandatory versus permissive laws reasonably necessary under the circumstances. Most psychologists think of duty to protect laws as those After the Tarasoff case, many states passed legislation that create a mandatory obligation to take action and impose defining a “duty to protect”* and the steps needed to liability for failing to carry out that duty. But there are closely discharge that duty. In other states, courts created a related laws that give psychologists discretion or permission duty to protect through case law.
    [Show full text]
  • Addressing Fundamentalism by Legal and Spiritual Means
    H UMAN R IGHTS & H UMAN W ELFARE Addressing Fundamentalism by Legal and Spiritual Means By Dan Wessner Religion and Humane Global Governance by Richard A. Falk. New York: Palgrave, 2001. 191 pp. Gender and Human Rights in Islam and International Law: Equal before Allah, Unequal before Man? by Shaheen Sardar Ali. The Hague: Kluwer Law International, 2000. 358 pp. Religious Fundamentalisms and the Human Rights of Women edited by Courtney W. Howland. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1999. 326 pp. The Islamic Quest for Democracy, Pluralism, and Human Rights by Ahmad S. Moussalli. Gainesville: University Press of Florida, 2001. 226 pp. The post-Cold War era stands at a crossroads. Some sort of new world order or disorder is under construction. Our choice to move more toward multilateralism or unilateralism is informed well by inter-religious debate and international law. Both disciplines rightly challenge the “post- Enlightenment divide between religion and politics,” and reinvigorate a spiritual-legal dialogue once thought to be “irrelevant or substandard” (Falk: 1-8, 101). These disciplines can dissemble illusory walls between spiritual/sacred and material/modernist concerns, between realpolitik interests and ethical judgment (Kung 1998: 66). They place praxis and war-peace issues firmly in the context of a suffering humanity and world. Both warn as to how fundamentalism may subjugate peace and security to a demagogic, uncompromising quest. These disciplines also nurture a community of speech that continues to find its voice even as others resort to war. The four books considered in this essay respond to the rush and risk of unnecessary conflict wrought by fundamentalists.
    [Show full text]
  • Monitoring the Duty to Monitor
    Corporate Governance WWW. NYLJ.COM MONDAY, NOVEMBER 28, 2011 Monitoring the Duty to Monitor statements. As a result, the stock prices of Chinese by an actual intent to do harm” or an “intentional BY LOUIS J. BEVILACQUA listed companies have collapsed. Do directors dereliction of duty, [and] a conscious disregard have a duty to monitor and react to trends that for one’s responsibilities.”9 Examples of conduct HE SIGNIFICANT LOSSES suffered by inves- raise obvious concerns that are industry “red amounting to bad faith include “where the fidu- tors during the recent financial crisis have flags,” but not specific to the individual company? ciary intentionally acts with a purpose other than again left many shareholders clamoring to T And if so, what is the appropriate penalty for the that of advancing the best interests of the corpo- find someone responsible. Where were the direc- board’s failure to act? “Sine poena nulla lex.” (“No ration, where the fiduciary acts with the intent tors who were supposed to be watching over the law without punishment.”).3 to violate applicable positive law, or where the company? What did they know? What should they fiduciary intentionally fails to act in the face of have known? Fiduciary Duties Generally a known duty to act, demonstrating a conscious Obviously, directors should not be liable for The duty to monitor arose out of the general disregard for his duties.”10 losses resulting from changes in general economic fiduciary duties of directors. Under Delaware law, Absent a conflict of interest, claims of breaches conditions, but what about the boards of mort- directors have fiduciary duties to the corporation of duty of care by a board are subject to the judicial gage companies and financial institutions that and its stockholders that include the duty of care review standard known as the “business judgment had a business model tied to market risk.
    [Show full text]
  • Networked Framing Between Source Posts and Their Reposts: an Analysis of Public Opinion on China’S Microblogs CM3 ¶ Joyce Y
    INFORMATION, COMMUNICATION & SOCIETY, 2015 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1369118X.2015.1104372 5 Networked framing between source posts and their reposts: an analysis of public opinion on China’s microblogs CM3 ¶ Joyce Y. M. Nipa and King-wa Fub aDepartment of Media and Communications, The University of Sydney, Sydney, NSW, Australia; bJournalism 10 and Media Studies Centre, The University of Hong Kong, Hong Kong ABSTRACT ARTICLE HISTORY Retweeting a post on a social media platform is a part of a process of Received 20 January 2015 growing significance through which public opinion formation takes Accepted 2 October 2015 place. A ‘retweet count’ on, say Twitter or weibo, can be taken as a KEYWORDS 15 measure of user influence. The assumption is that when B retweets ’ China; framing; public A s message, B empathizes with A and wishes to disseminate the opinion; retweet; social message more widely. But this assumption has hardly been tested media; Twitter; weibo and preliminary evidence suggests practices for retweeting on Twitter vary. Nor can retweeting practices on Twitter be assumed to apply on weibo. This paper makes the first effort to understand 20 the practice of reposting on China’s weibo, focusing on the content of reposts in comparison to that of the original messages. A quantitative comparison is made of the frame [Entman, R. M. (1993). Framing: Toward clarification of a fractured paradigm. Journal of Communication, 43(4), 51–58; Gamson, W. A., & Modigliani, A. (1989). Media discourse and public opinion on nuclear power: A constructionist approach. American Journal of 25 Sociology, 95,1–37] of the source post of 21 cases, and their reposts.
    [Show full text]
  • Emergentism As an Option in the Philosophy of Religion: Between Materialist Atheism and Pantheism
    SURI 7 (2) 2019: 1-22 Emergentism as an Option in the Philosophy of Religion: Between Materialist Atheism and Pantheism James Franklin University of New South Wales Abstract: Among worldviews, in addition to the options of materialist atheism, pantheism and personal theism, there exists a fourth, “local emergentism”. It holds that there are no gods, nor does the universe overall have divine aspects or any purpose. But locally, in our region of space and time, the properties of matter have given rise to entities which are completely different from matter in kind and to a degree god-like: consciousnesses with rational powers and intrinsic worth. The emergentist option is compared with the standard alternatives and the arguments for and against it are laid out. It is argued that, among options in the philosophy of religion, it involves the minimal reworking of the manifest image of common sense. Hence it deserves a place at the table in arguments as to the overall nature of the universe. Keywords: Emergence; pantheism; personal theism; naturalism; consciousness 1. INTRODUCTION The main options among world views are normally classifiable as either materialist atheism, pantheism (widely understood) or personal theism. According to materialist atheism, there exists nothing except the material universe as we ordinarily conceive it, and its properties are fully described by science (present or future). According to personal theism, there exists a separate entity (or entities) of a much higher form than those found in the 2019 Philosophical Association of the Philippines 2 Emergentism as an Option in the Philosophy of Religion material universe, a god or gods.
    [Show full text]
  • MORAL OBJECTIVITY and the PSYCHOLOGY of MOTIVATION by Jude Ndubuisi Edeh a DISSERTATION Submitted in Partial Fulfilment Of
    Philosophy MORAL OBJECTIVITY AND THE PSYCHOLOGY OF MOTIVATION By Jude Ndubuisi Edeh A DISSERTATION Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Dr.phil) University of Münster Münster, Germany 2017 Dekan:Prof. Dr. Thomas Großbölting Erstgutachter: PD. Dr. Michael Kühler Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Reinold Schmücker Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 04.10.2018 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am immensely grateful to Michael Kühler and Reinold Schmücker, my supervisors, for their generosity with their time, energy and support. It’s not always a given that you find people who are both interested in your project and believe you can handle it, especially at its budding stage. I benefited tremendously from your constructive criticisms and helpful comments, without which the completion of this project would not have been successful. I owe, in addition, a significant debt of gratitude to Nadine Elzein for supervising this project during my research stay at the King’s College, University of London. Nadine, your enthusiasm, philosophical insight and suggestions are invaluable. I owe special thanks also to Lukas Meyer for hosting me in August 2015 at the Institute of Philosophy, University of Graz. This project would not have been possible without the friendship, support, and insight of a good many people. In particular, I owe a significant debt of gratitude to: Nnaemeka’s family, Anthony Anih’s family, Anthony C. Ajah, Uzoma Emenogu, Vitus Egwu. I will always remain indebted to my family for their undying care and love. I would never have made it this far without your encouragement and support. ii ABSTRACT This dissertation provides a solution to the tension of specifying and reconciling the relationship between moral judgement and motivation.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of 142 Strand: a Radical Address in Victorian London & George Eliot in Germany,1854-55: 'Cherished Memories'
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln The George Eliot Review English, Department of 2007 Review of 142 Strand: A Radical Address in Victorian London & George Eliot in Germany,1854-55: 'Cherished Memories' Rosemary Ashton Gerlinde Roder-Bolton Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/ger Part of the Comparative Literature Commons, Literature in English, British Isles Commons, and the Women's Studies Commons Ashton, Rosemary and Roder-Bolton, Gerlinde, "Review of 142 Strand: A Radical Address in Victorian London & George Eliot in Germany,1854-55: 'Cherished Memories'" (2007). The George Eliot Review. 522. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/ger/522 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the English, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in The George Eliot Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Rosemary Ashton, 142 Strand: A RadicalAddress in Victorian London (Chatto & Windus, 2006). pp. xiv + 386. ISBN 0 7011 7370 X Gerlinde Roder-Bolton, George Eliot in Germany,1854-55: 'Cherished Memories' (Ashgate, 2006). pp. xiii + 180. ISBN 0 7546 5054 5 The outlines of Marian Evans's life in the years immediately preceding her emergence as George Eliot are well-known-her work for the Westminster Review, her relationships with Chapman, Spencer and Lewes, and then her departure with the latter to Germany in July 1854. What these two studies do in their different ways is fill in the picture with fascinating detail. In focusing on the house that John Chapman rented from 1847 to 1854 and from which he ran the Westminster Review and his publishing business, Rosemary Ashton recreates the circle of radical intellectuals that the future novelist came into contact with through living there and working as the effective editor of Chapman' s journal.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of George Henry Lewes in George Eliot's Career
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications -- Department of English English, Department of 2017 The Role of George Henry Lewes in George Eliot’s Career: A Reconsideration Beverley Rilett University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/englishfacpubs Part of the Comparative Literature Commons, English Language and Literature Commons, Modern Literature Commons, Reading and Language Commons, and the Women's Studies Commons Rilett, Beverley, "The Role of George Henry Lewes in George Eliot’s Career: A Reconsideration" (2017). Faculty Publications -- Department of English. 186. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/englishfacpubs/186 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the English, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications -- Department of English by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Published in George Eliot—George Henry Lewes Studies, Vol. 69, No. 1, (2017), pp. 2-34. doi:10.5325/georelioghlstud.69.1.0002 Copyright © 2017 The Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA. Used by permission. digitalcommons.unl.edudigitalcommons.unl.edu The Role of George Henry Lewes in George Eliot’s Career: A Reconsideration Beverley Park Rilett University of Nebraska–Lincoln Abstract This article examines the “protection” and “encouragement” George Henry Lewes provided to Eliot throughout her fiction-writing career. According to biographers, Lewes showed his selfless devotion to Eliot by encouraging her to begin and continue writing fiction; by foster- ing the mystery of her authorship; by managing her finances; by negotiating her publishing con- tracts; by managing her schedule; by hosting a salon to promote her books; and by staying close by her side for twenty-four years until death parted them.
    [Show full text]
  • George Eliot's Coventry Friend, Caroline (Cara) Bray (1814-1905)
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln The George Eliot Review English, Department of 1998 'My Own Dear Heart's Ease': George Eliot's Coventry Friend, Caroline (Cara) Bray (1814-1905) Kathleen Adams Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/ger Part of the Comparative Literature Commons, Literature in English, British Isles Commons, and the Women's Studies Commons Adams, Kathleen, "'My Own Dear Heart's Ease': George Eliot's Coventry Friend, Caroline (Cara) Bray (1814-1905)" (1998). The George Eliot Review. 317. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/ger/317 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the English, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in The George Eliot Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. 'MY OWN DEAR HEART'S EASE': GEORGE ELIOT'S COVENTRY FRIEND, CAROLINE (CARA) BRAY (1814-1905) by Kathleen Adams In September 1842 Mary Ann Evans wrote a short but illuminating letter to her Coventry friend Cara Bray: My own dear Heart's Ease [it was not unusual for her to give her closest friends the name of a flower as she had done this on several occasions before], ... your looks and words of love are so precious to me. I am together ashamed of myself - do not tell anyone that I am so silly as I appear to her whom I love best ... ' We don't know why Mary Ann was so ashamed but we do see clearly what Cara's friendship meant to her: Gordon S.
    [Show full text]
  • George Eliot's Middlemarch, Spinoza, and the Ethics of Power
    W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2015 “A Constant Unfolding of Far-Resonate Action”: George Eliot’s Middlemarch, Spinoza, and the Ethics of Power Zachary J. Hardy Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Literature in English, British Isles Commons, and the Other German Language and Literature Commons Recommended Citation Hardy, Zachary J., "“A Constant Unfolding of Far-Resonate Action”: George Eliot’s Middlemarch, Spinoza, and the Ethics of Power" (2015). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 205. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/honorstheses/205 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects at W&M ScholarWorks. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected]. “A Constant Unfolding of Far-Resonate Action”: George Eliot’s Middlemarch, Spinoza, and the Ethics of Power A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Bachelor of Arts in English from The College of William and Mary by Zachary Joseph Hardy Accepted for ___________________________________ (Honors, High Honors, Highest Honors) ________________________________________ Adam Potkay, Advisor ________________________________________ Simon Joyce, Director ________________________________________ Robert
    [Show full text]