Downloaded from Brill.Com10/09/2021 12:18:49PM Via Free Access 442 BIBLIOGRAPHY

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Downloaded from Brill.Com10/09/2021 12:18:49PM Via Free Access 442 BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY In the following Bibliography and Index, ancient and medieval authors are listed by their first names (e.g., John Philoponus; Roger Bacon; etc.). Post­ medieval authors are listed by their last names (e.g., Zabarella; Descartes; etc.). The medieval names are given in their English forms, as Thomas Aquinas (rather than Tommaso d'Aquino; Thomas von Aquin, etc.) I. Manuscripts ANONYMUS, Quaestiones super De generatione et corruptione. Cambridge, Peter­ house College, 192, fols. 119vb-132vb. -, Quaestiones super Metaphysicam, 1-1v. Assisi, Biblioteca Comunale, 290, fols. 65ra-85rb. - , Quaestiones super Physicam. Cambridge, Gonville and Caius College, 344, fols. io5rb_17ovb. - , Quaestiones super Physicam. Cambridge, Gonville and Caius College, 367, fols. 120r"-125vb, i36ra-151vb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, I, 1v-v1. Cambridge, Peterhouse College, 192, IV, fols. 53ra-96vb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-III. London, Wellcome Historical Medical Library, 333, fols. 8'"-68vb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-IV, v, (Fragm.). Oxford, Merton College, 272, fols. i36ra-174Brb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, 1, m-1v. Oxford, Merton College, 272, fols. 1 19ra-135crb. - , Quaestiones super Physicam, I-V. Oxford, Oriel College, 33, fols. 8'"-7gvh. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, 1-vm. Siena, Biblioteca Comunale degli Intronati, L.II1.21, fols. 1ra-92ra. - , Sententia libri Physicorum "extracta de verbo ad verbum," 1-v. Oxford, Bodleian Library, Lat. Misc. c. 69, fols. i ra-41 rb. ANONYMUS (=GILES OF ORLEANS (?)), Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII. Paris, Bibliotheque Nationale de France, lat. 14698, fols. 83ra-129Ar. BARILE, E. (ED.), Rotuli Artistarum (r430-r8r5). Unpublished MS, Antico Archivio dell'Universita, Padova. BARTHOLOMEW OF BRUGES, Quaestiones super Physicam, 1-V, VII, VIII. Leipzig, Universitatsbibliothek, 1426, fols. 1 r-114v. CORTI, M., Lectiones in artem medicinalem Galeni. London, Wellcome Historical Medical Library, 216, fols. 66r-281'. GEOFFREY OF AsPALL, Quaestiones super Physicam, 1-m, IV (Fragm.), vm. Oxford, Merton College, 272, fols. 88r"-118vb. GERALD OF Ono, Quaestiones naturalis philowphia, Madrid, Biblioteca Na­ cional, cod. 4229. Cees Leijenhorst, Christoph Lüthy, and Johannes M.M.H. Thijssen - 9789004453319 Downloaded from Brill.com10/09/2021 12:18:49PM via free access 442 BIBLIOGRAPHY GILES (= GILES OF ORLEANS ?), Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII. Padova, Biblioteca Antoniana, XVII. 380, fols. 1ra_52ra. JOHN THE CANON, Quaestiones super octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis, Citta del Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Vat. lat. 3013; Miinchen, Baye­ rische Staatsbibliothek, Clm. 5874; Cambridge, Gonville and Caius Li­ brary, MS 368 (590). JOHN OF WACFELD, Quaestiones super Physicam, I. Cambridge, Gonville and Caius College, 344, fols. 264ra-277vb. PENDASIO, F., Lectiones in libros De anima. Padova, Biblioteca Universitaria, 1264, 1-221. PosSEVINUS, A., Annales quinquagi,nta annorum quos Sacerdos e Societate Jesu iussus est scribere iis de rebus ad quas missus est. Decas I. Roma, ARSI, Opp. NN. 336. RAouLPHUS BRITO, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII, Firenze, Biblioteca Nazionale Centrale, Conv. Soppr. E. 1. 252, fols. 1ra_5ora. RICHARD OF CLIVE, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII. Worcester, Cathedral Library, Q. 13, fols. 79r•-1 i 6'". Ps.-SIMPLICIUS, "Prooemium" of In libros Aristotelis De anima commentaria. Partial translation by Michael Sophianus. Milano, Biblioteca Ambrosiana, o 465 inf. Fasc. 12. TAURELLUS, N., Theses clarissimi Dn. D. Nicolai Taurelli de persona Christi. Er­ langen, Universitatsbibliothek, 695, pp. 137-160. THOMAS ANGLicus (?), Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII. Erfurt, Wis­ senschaftliche Bibliothek der Stadt, Amplon. F. 348, fols. 69va-115vb. THOMAS WYLTON, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII. Cesena, Biblioteca Malatestiana, Plut. VIII Sin. 2. - , Quodlibet. Citta de! Vaticano, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Borgh. 36, fols. 4 7r-96v. WALTER BURLEY, Expositio libri Physicorum cum questionibus optime disputatis, I-VIII. Cambridge, Gonville and Caius College, 448, pp. 172-543. (Ps.?) WALTER BURLEY, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VI. Worcester, Cathedral Library, Q. 38, fols. 25va-96va. WALTER BURLEY, Quaestiones super Physicam. Basel, Universitatsbibliothek, F V 12, fols. l08r-171v. WILLIAM BoNKES, Quaestiones super De generatione et corruptione. Cambridge, Gonville and Caius College 344, fols. 92ra-102rb. - (?), Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII. Cambridge, Peterhouse College, i92, I, fols. 37r•-119vb. WILLIAM OF CHELVESTUN, Quaestiones super Physicam, I. Cambridge, Peter­ house Colleg,e 192, I, fols. lra-35vb. Cees Leijenhorst, Christoph Lüthy, and Johannes M.M.H. Thijssen - 9789004453319 Downloaded from Brill.com10/09/2021 12:18:49PM via free access BIBLIOGRAPHY 443 2. Published Sources o'ABANO, P., Conciliator controversiarum, quae inter philosophos et medicos ver­ santur. Venezia, 1548. ABATTOUY, M., "Al-Mu'.?affar al-Isfizari, 'alim mikaniki min al-qarnayn 5- 6/ 11-12, mu'allif Irshad dhawz al-'irfan ila #na'at al-qaffan." ("Al-Mu'.?affar al-Isfizari, a mechanician from the eleventh/twelfth century, author of Guiding the Learned Men in the Art of the Steelyard.") In Quelques aspects de l'evolution des idees scientifiques, pp. 135-175. -, "The Arabic Tradition of Mechanics. Textual and Historical Character­ isation." Majallat kulliyyat al-adab wa al- 'uliim al-insaniyya bi-Fas. journal of the Faculty of Letters and Humanities in Fez, 1 2 ( 1999), 7 5-109. -, "Greek Mechanics in Arabic Context. Thabit ibn Qurra, al-Isfizari and the Arabic Traditions of Aristotelian and Euclidean Mechanics." Science in Context, 14 (2001), 179-247. - , "Nutaf min al-1).iyal. A Short Arabic Version of Pseudo-Aristotle's Prob­ lemata Mechanica." Early Science and Medicine, 6 ( 2001), 96-122. - , "Sur quelques demonstrations grecques et arabes de la loi du levier: transmission et transformation." In Aliyyiit al-istidlal, pp. 7-43. -, "La tradition arabe de la balance. Thabit ibn Qurra et al-Khazini." In Quelques aspects de l'evolution des idees scientifiques, pp. 49-91. ABBONDANZA, R., "Gli atti degli Ufficiali dello Studio fiorentino, dal maggio al settembre 1388." Archivio storico italiano, 117 ( 1959), 85-110. AcHILLINI, A, Opera omnia in unum collecta. Venezia, 1545· ADAMS, M. M., William Ockham. Notre Dame, Indiana, 1987. AERTSEN,J. A., K EMERY,JR., A SPEER (EDS.), Nach der Verurteilungvon I2J7. Philosophie und Theologie an der Universitiit von Paris im letzten Viertel des I 3. jahrhunderts. Berlin & New York, 2001. AERTSEN, J. & A SPEER (EDS.), Raum und Raumvorstellungen im Mittelalter. Berlin & New York, igg8. AGRIMI,J. & C. CRISCIANI, Edocere medicos. Medicina scolastica nei secoli XIII-xv. Napoli, 1988. ALBERT THE GREAT, Liber VIII Physicorum. In Opera omnia. Ed. A Borgnet. 38 vols. Paris, 1890-1899. Vol. 3. -, Opera omnia. Gen. ed. B. Geyer. Munster, 1951-. - , Physica. Ed. P. Hossfeld. In Opera omnia, tom us 4. 2 parts. Munster, 1987 and 1993· ALBERT OF SAXONY, Questiones in octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis. In Lokert (ed.), Questiones et decisiones. ALBERTI, A & R. W. SHARPLES (EDS.), Aspasius: The Earliest Extant Commentary on Aristotle's Ethics. Berlin, 1999· ALDEROTTI, T., In C. Galeni microtechnen commentarii. Napoli, 1522. ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIAS, In Aristotelis Metaphysica commentaria. Ed. M. Hayduck. Berlin, 189i. -, On Aristotl,e's Metaphysics I. Trans. W. E. Dooley. London, 1989. - , De anima liber cum mantissa. Trans. H. Donatus. Venezia, 1514. - , Praeter commentaria scripta minora. Vol. I: De anima liber cum mantissa. Vol. Cees Leijenhorst, Christoph Lüthy, and Johannes M.M.H. Thijssen - 9789004453319 Downloaded from Brill.com10/09/2021 12:18:49PM via free access 444 BIBLIOGRAPHY 2: Quaestiones, Defato, De mixtione. Ed. I. Bruns. Berlin, 1887-1892. -, Quaestiones r.r-2.r5. Trans. R. W. Sharples. London, 1992. - , Quaestiones natural,es, de anima, moraks .. .. Trans. G. Hervet. Basel, 1548. Ps.-ALEXANDER, In Aristotelis Metaphysica commentaria. Ed. M. Hayduck. Berlin, 189i. (Commentaria in Aristotelem graeca, 1) ALFARABI, De intell,ectu et intell,ecto. In E. Gilson, "Les sources greco-arabes de l'augustinianisme avicennisant," Archives d'histoire doctrinal,e et litteraire du Mayen Age, 4 (1930), 115-126. ALGAZEL, Metaphysics. A Medieval Translation. Ed.]. T. Muckle. Toronto, 1933· ALGRA, K., Concepts of Space in Greek Thought. Leiden, 1995· Aliyyat al-istidlal fi 'l-'ilm [The Mechanism of Reasoning in the Sciences]. Rabat, 2000. ALLIEZ, E. (ED.), Metamorphosen der 'Zeit. Miinchen, 1999· ALLINEY, G., The Medieval Concept of Time and Its Influence on Early Modern Philosophy. Leiden, forthcoming. AMATORI, E. (ED.), Storia dell'Universita di Pisa. Pisa, 1993-. AMMONIUS, In Aristotelis De interpretatione commentarius. Ed. A Busse. Berlin, 1897. ANTON,]. P. (ED.), Naturalism and Historical Understanding: Essays on the Phi­ losophy ofJ H. Randall, Jr. New York, 1967. ANTON,]. P. & G. L. KusTAS (EDS.), Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy. Albany, 1971. ANTONACI, A., Ricerche sull'aristotelismo del Rinascimento. Marcantonio Zi­ mara. Vol. n: Dal periodo sal,ernitano al secondo periodo padovano. Lecce, 1978. ARGENTERIUS, J., In artem medicinalem Galeni commentarii tres. Konigsberg, 1566. ARIEW, R., "Bernier et les doctrines gassendistes et cartesiennes de I' es pace: Reponses au probleme de !'explication de l'eucharistie." Corpus, Revue de Philosophie, 20/21 (1992), 155-170. -, "Damned ifYou Do. Cartesians and Censorship, 1663-1706." Perspec­ tives on
Recommended publications
  • Pomponazzi on Identity and Individuation Han Thomas Adriaenssen Abstract. Aristotle Defines Growing As a Process in Which An
    Final version forthcoming in Journal of the History of Philosophy Pomponazzi on Identity and Individuation Han Thomas Adriaenssen Abstract. Aristotle defines growing as a process in which an individual living being persists as it accumulates new matter. This definition raises the question of what enables an individual to persist as its material composition continuously changes over time. This paper provides a systematic account of Pietro Pomponazzi’s answer to this question. In his De nutritione et augmentatione, Pomponazzi argues that individuals persist in virtue of their forms. Forms are individuated in part by their material, causal, and temporal origins, which commits Pomponazzi to the view that individuals necessarily have the material, causal, and temporal origins they do. I provide an account of why Pomponazzi was willing to this view. While his opponents remain unnamed, I argue that his arguments for this view are best read as addressing, among others, Paul of Venice and Gregory of Rimini. In On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle describes growing as a process in which “any and every part of the growing magnitude is made bigger . by the accession of something, and thirdly in such a way that the growing thing is preserved and persists” (321a18–22).1 For instance, when an animal grows as the result of the intake of food, all of its limbs grow larger as the result of the intake of new matter, in such a way that the same individual animal persists throughout the process. 1 All Aristotle translations are taken from the Jonathan Barnes edition of the Complete Works. 1 Final version forthcoming in Journal of the History of Philosophy Simple though it may perhaps appear, this definition confronted Aristotle’s later followers and commentators with a problem.
    [Show full text]
  • Eric W. Hagedorn Curriculum Vitae
    Eric W. Hagedorn Curriculum Vitae Areas of Specialization: Medieval Philosophy Areas of Competence: Metaphysics; Early Modern Philosophy; Philosophy of Religion; Philosophy of Mind; Logic Employment St. Norbert College Associate Professor Philosophy (August 2018-Present) Assistant Professor of Philosophy (January 2014 – August 2018) Teaching Fellow of Philosophy (August 2012 – December 2013) Education University of Notre Dame Ph.D. in Philosophy (January 2013) M.A. in Philosophy (January 2008) Iowa State University B.S. with Honors in Computer Science and Philosophy (May 2004) Journal Articles and Book Chapters “Thomas Aquinas through the 1350s,” in The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Ethics, ed. Thomas Williams (forthcoming). “Ockham’s Scientia Argument for Mental Language,” Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 3 (2015): 145-168. "Is Anyone Else Thinking My Thoughts?: Aquinas's Response to the Too-Many Thinkers Problem," Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 84 (2010): 275-86. Book Reviews Review of John Duns Scotus, On Being and Cognition: Ordinatio I.3, John van den Bercken (tr.) in International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion (forthcoming). Review of Claude Panaccio, Mental Language: From Plato to William of Ockham in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (August 2017). Review of Jari Kaukua and Tomas Ekenberg (eds.), Subjectivity and Selfhood in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (September 2016). Review of Sander W. de Boer, The Science of the Soul: The Commentary
    [Show full text]
  • Walter Burley on the Kinds of Simple Supposition1
    Walter Burley on The Kinds of Simple Supposition 1 PAUL VINCENT SPADE 1. Background By the early-fourteenth century at the latest, the mediaeval theory of supposition could be divided in most authors into two main branches, which in recent literature have come to be called the theory of “suppo- sition proper” and the theory of “modes of personal supposition,” respec- tively.2 While the relation between these two branches remains obscure, we can say to a rst approximation that the theory of supposition proper was atheory of “reference,” designed to answer the question what entity or enti- ties a term refers to or “supposits” for in a given occurrence in a given proposition, whereas the theory of modes of personal supposition, whatever its ultimate purpose, was the part of the theory that included the much- discussed accounts of “descent to singulars” and “ascent from singulars.”3 Walter Burley and his somewhat younger contemporary, William of Ockham, for the most part agreed about the modes of personal supposition, 4 1 I am grateful to Rega Wood and Elizabeth Karger for their comments and sugges- tions on an earlier draft of this paper. 2 See Paul Vincent Spade, The Semantics of Terms , in: Norman Kretzmann et al. (ed.), The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy , New York 1982, Ch. 9 (188-96). This ter- minology was rst used by T.K. Scott in the “Introduction” to his translation of John Buridan’s Sophismata, and is not mediaeval. See T.K. Scott (trans.), John Buridan: Sophisms on Meaning and Truth , New York 1966, 29-42.
    [Show full text]
  • A Companion to Walter Burley Brill’S Companions to the Christian Tradition
    A Companion to Walter Burley Brill’s Companions to the Christian Tradition A series of handbooks and reference works on the intellectual and religious life of Europe, 500–1800 Editor-in-Chief Christopher M. Bellitto (Kean University) VOLUME 41 The titles published in this series are listed at brill.com/bcct A Companion to Walter Burley Late Medieval Logician and Metaphysician Edited by Alessandro D. Conti LEIDEN • BOSTON 2013 Cover illustration: detail from the sculptured funerary monument of Giovanni da Legnano (1320–83), Doctor utriusque iuris of the University of Bologna. Courtesy of the Museo Civico Medievale of Bologna. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A companion to Walter Burley : late medieval logician and metaphysician / Edited by Alessandro D. Conti. p. cm. — (Brill’s companions to the Christian tradition ; Volume 41) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-90-04-24461-0 (hardback : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-90-04-24460-3 (e-book) 1. Burlaeus, Gualterus, 1275–1345? 2. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Conti, Alessandro D. B765.B8484C66 2013 189’.4—dc23 2013002068 This publication has been typeset in the multilingual “Brill” typeface. With over 5,100 characters covering Latin, IPA, Greek, and Cyrillic, this typeface is especially suitable for use in the humanities. For more information, please see www.brill.com/brill-typeface. ISSN 1871-6377 ISBN 978-90-04-24461-0 (hardback) ISBN 978-90-04-24460-3 (e-book) Copyright 2013 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Global Oriental, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers and Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Walter Burley, the Longer Treatise on the Purity of the Art of Logic Tract 1
    1 Walter Burley, The Longer Treatise On the Purity of the Art of Logic 5 Tract 1: “On the Properties of Terms” Translated by Paul Vincent Spade Indiana University 10 (1) Assuming the significates of non-complex terms, in this treatise I intend to investigate certain properties of terms, [properties] that are applica- ble to them only insofar as they are parts of propositions. (2) Now I divide this tract into three parts. The first is about the sup- position of terms, the second about appellation, and the third about copula- 15 tion. Supposition belongs to the subject, appellation to the predicate. Copula- tion belongs to the verb that couples the predicate with the subject. For these three are the integral parts of the categorical proposition, to which we turn before [treating] hypotheticals.1 Hence in this tract I want to talk about the suppositions of terms in categoricals. 20 [Part One: On Supposition] (3) The first part will contain six chapters. The first chapter is about the division of supposition in general. The second chapter is about material supposition. The third chapter is about simple supposition. The fourth chapter is about the division of personal supposition in general. The fifth chapter is 25 about various difficulties that arise concerning personal supposition. The sixth chapter is about improper supposition. 1 Hypothetical propositions are propositions composed of two or more categoricals. A categorical proposition is, in modern logical terminology, either an atomic proposition or else the negation of an atomic proposition. Hence the notion of a hypothetical proposition is not exactly the same as the modern notion of a “molecular” proposition, since the negations of atomic propositions are molecular but not hypothetical.
    [Show full text]
  • Archbishop Fitz Ralph of Armagh. a Precursor of the Reformation
    414 ART. II.-ARCHBISHOP FITZ RALPH OF ARMAGH. A PRECURSOR OF THE REFORMATION. UST as the drops come before the shower, so we find that J there were many isolated attempts at Reformation long before the great movement of the sixteenth century. Even before Wickliffe, both in England and Ireland, there were some protestants against the errors and enormities £a voured by the Roman See in the name of religion. Amongst these, one of the most remarkable, yet least known at the present day, is Richard Fitz Ralph, Archbishop of Armagh. By his piety and reforming zeal the name Armachanus was as well known in his time, throughout the whole Christian world, as it was two •centuries later by the learning of Archbishop U ssher. Of the six great primates of Armagh-Patrick, Apostle of Ireland, Malachy, the friend of Bernard, Fitz Ralph, U ssher, Boulter, Beresford-he is by no means the least worthy of notice. With Malachy he may well be compared: both were reformers, but in different directions. He will be seen to have well earned the character given of him by John Foxe:-" He was a man worthy, for his Christian zeal, of immortal commendation." Fitz Ralph lived in the reign of King Edward III. This reign, extending over exactly half a century (1327-1377), was one of the most brilliant epochs of our national history. The importance of the political affairs of the time has no doubt obscured the view of ecclesiastical events and leaders, and to a :great extent caused the suppression of many important details.
    [Show full text]
  • Walter Burley
    Walter Burley From the Beginning of His Treatise on the Kinds of Supposition (De suppositionibus) 5 Translated from Stephen F. Brown, “Walter Burleigh’s Treatise De suppo- sitionibus and Its Influence on William of Ockham,” Franciscan Studies 32 (1972), 1 10 pp. 15–64 Translated by Paul Vincent Spade, Department of Philosophy, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN, 47405 <On the Kinds of Supposition according to Walter Bu rley>2 15 [Introduction] (1) (p. 31) (1.1) “Some things that are said are said with complexity, and others are said without complexity.”3 Those that are said without com- plexity are, for example, ‘man’, ‘animal’. Those that are said with complex- ity are, for example, ‘A man runs’, ‘An animal runs’.4 20 (2) It is plain from this that the incomplex is part of the complex. And because a knowledge of the part is very helpful for knowing the whole, therefore in this treatise we must talk about incomplex [expressions] and the properties of incomplex [expressions] — that is, about supposition and ap- pellation. For the knowledge of these is very helpful for knowing the 25 proposition, and consequently for knowing the syllogism. 1I have here translated the first part of Burley’s text (pp. 31–43), on the supposition of “absolute” terms, but not the remainder (pp. 43–64), on the supposition of “respective” or “relative” terms and other material. (See paragraph (18) below.) Page breaks have been inserted in parentheses. Parenthetical numerals with decimal points are Brown’s paragraph numbers. My own paragraph numbering is in boldface. 2Here and throughout this translation, pointed brackets enclose Brown’s editorial additions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Envious Instant: Material Conditions of Truth in Thomas Bradwardine
    Sean Hannan Villanova PMR October 2016 The Envious Instant: Material Conditions of Truth in Thomas Bradwardine Long before his all-too-brief tenure as Archbishop of Canterbury, Thomas Bradwardine spent his formative years untying logical knots at Oxford. The knottiest of those knots were to be found in semantic paradoxes like that of the well-known liar who says, “I am lying to you right now.” In order to unweave these tangled threads, Bradwardine made use of an unloved instrument from the medieval logicians’ toolkit: the ut nunc consequence.1 Often translated as ‘matter of fact’ consequence, this logical maneuver involved the supposition of a contingent premise which may not hold ‘absolutely’ (simpliciter) or in every case. Bradwardine embraced the ut nunc consequence as central to his understanding of how the truth of propositions may be judged in relation to their contingent premises. By relating insolubles like the Liar’s Paradox back to contingent, material states of affairs, he was able to push past the limits of paradox and ground truth anew in an apprehension of the facts of the matter—at least, as of now (ut nunc). While Bradwardine’s idiosyncratic reliance upon the ut nunc has already been established, there remains work to be done on how this dependence of logic on temporality relates to the theological account of time we meet in his De Causa Dei contra Pelagianos. One central claim there is that human matters can perhaps be understood in terms of temporal instants, whereas God must not be so measured, dwelling as He does in the simultaneity of an “instantaneous presentiality,” which Bradwardine dubs the “simultas of the temporal instant.”2 While simultas here presumably means sheer simultaneitas, it is tempting (for this reader, at 1 My understanding of the use of the ut nunc consequence in medieval logic is indebted to the work of Stephen Read, Edith Wilks Dolnikowski, Eleonore Stump, and Catarina Dutilh Novaes.
    [Show full text]
  • The Routledge Companion to Medieval Philosophy
    16 QUALITATIVE CHANGE Robert Pasnau At the boundaries of metaphysics and natural philosophy lies a fascinating medieval dispute over the way qualitative change takes place. Although modern philosophy has had little to say about this issue, anyone who needs properties or dispositions to do serious explanatory work should attend to how such qualitative features of reality intensify and diminish. For now, the most so- phisticated such accounts are to be found in the later Middle Ages. Motivating the Problem A qualitative change is a change to quality, as opposed to a change to quantity or substance. The difference arises ultimately out of Aristotle’s division of being in the Categories, which was widely understood to license a fundamental distinction between these different kinds of being. For pres- ent purposes, we can set aside the many controversies over the precise nature of the distinction be- tween quality, quantity, and substance, and content ourselves with a few paradigmatic examples. When a thing becomes larger or heavier, or moves faster, it undergoes a change in quantity. When the thing itself—a dog, a tree, some water—goes out of existence, and is succeeded by something else, then there is a change in substance. When the thing endures, but becomes hotter, moister, or greener, it undergoes a change in quality. For scholastic Aristotelians, such qualities are in fact the fundamental causal agents in the natural world, completely overshadowing the peripheral role played by quantitative (geometric or kinetic) explanations. In keeping with this prominent phys- ical role, for most scholastic authors, qualities also have a robust metaphysical status as accidental forms that are really distinct from the subjects (typically, the substances) in which they inhere.1 In thinking about why the debate over qualitative change matters, we might start by imagining a theory of the world that makes no use of forms whatsoever: a view on which the only facts about the world worth keeping track of are facts about the location of particles in space over time.
    [Show full text]
  • The Love of Books the Philobiblon of Richard De Bury Translated Into English by E
    THE LOVE OF BOOKS THE PHILOBIBLON OF RICHARD DE BURY TRANSLATED INTO ENGLISH BY E. C. THOMAS "TAKE THOU A BOOK INTO THINE HANDS AS SIMON THE JUST TOOK THE CHILD JESUS INTO HIS ARMS TO CARRY HIM AND KISS HIM. AND WHEN THOU HAST FINISHED READING, CLOSE THE BOOK AND GIVE THANKS FOR EVERY WORD OUT OF THE MOUTH OF GOD; BECAUSE IN THE LORD'S FIELD THOU HAST FOUND A HIDDEN TREASURE." THOMAS A KEMPIS: Doctrinale Juvenum PREFACE The Author of the Book. Richard de Bury (1281-1345), so called from being born near Bury St. Edmunds, was the son of Sir Richard Aungerville. He studied at Oxford; and was subsequently chosen to be tutor to Prince Edward of Windsor, afterwards Edward III. His loyalty to the cause of Queen Isabella and the Prince involved him in danger. On the accession of his pupil he was made successively Cofferer, Treasurer of the Wardrobe, Archdeacon of Northampton, Prebendary of Lincoln, Sarum, and Lichfield, Keeper of the Privy Purse, Ambassador on two occasions to Pope John XXII, who appointed him a chaplain of the papal chapel, Dean of Wells, and ultimately, at the end of the year 1333, Bishop of Durham; the King and Queen, the King of Scots, and all the magnates north of the Trent, together with a multitude of nobles and many others, were present at his enthronization. It is noteworthy that during his stay at Avignon, probably in 1330, he made the acquaintance of Petrarch, who has left us a brief account of their intercourse. In 1332 Richard visited Cambridge, as one of the King's commissioners, to inquire into the state of the King's Scholars there, and perhaps then became a member of the Gild of St.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth, Signification and Paradox
    Truth, Signification and Paradox∗ Stephen Read University of St Andrews, Scotland [email protected] March 16, 2015 Abstract Thomas Bradwardine's solution to the semantic paradoxes, pre- sented in his Insolubilia written in Oxford in the early 1320s, turns on two main principles: that a proposition is true only if things are wholly as it signifies; and that signification is closed under consequence. After exploring the background in Walter Burley's account of the significa- tion of propositions, I consider the extent to which Bradwardine's the- ory is compatible with the compositional principles of the distribution of truth over conjunction, disjunction, negation and the conditional. Keywords: truth, meaning, paradox, sophism, bivalence, closure prin- ciples, conjunction, disjunction, negation, conditional, compositional- ity, distributivity; Bradwardine, Burley, Geulincx, Ricardus Sophista. 1 A Sophism about Saying That We find an intriguing sophism about signification, or saying that, in an oration delivered at the University of Cambridge in 1660: \I don't doubt that the proverb `The ass and the lyre' was coined for you alone. Yet surely you are not worthy to be proctor in the schools of the sophists. For a sophist attacks the Proctor like this: `Whoever says you are an animal says something true; and whoever says you are an ass says you are an animal; so whoever says you are an ass says something true.' `I grant the whole thing,' says the Proctor: `I wouldn't dare deny it on account of my ears.' See, then, the Proctor confesses himself to be an ass by auricular confession."1 ∗Presented at the Conference on `Truth at Work', Paris 20-23 June 2011, and forth- coming in Unifying the Philosophy of Truth, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    Curriculum Vitae Most recent update: October 21, 2011. Name Paul Vincent Spade. Professional Address Department of Philosophy, Indiana University, Sycamore Hall 026, 1033 E. Third St., Bloomington, IN 47405-7005. E-Mail Address: Born 25 August 1944, Richmond, Indiana. Education A.B., magna cum laude, Wabash College, 1966. Specialization in Philosophy (major) and Far Eastern Studies (minor). Licentiate of Mediaeval Studies, summa cum laude, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies (Toronto), 1969. Specialization in Philosophy. Dissertation: "An Anonymous Fourteenth-Century Treatise on 'Insolubles': Text and Study." Director: E. A. Synan. Ph.D. in Philosophy, University of Toronto, 1972. Specialization in Mediaeval Philosophy. Dissertation: "The Mediaeval Liar: A Study of John Buridan's Position on the Paradox, with a Catalogue of the Insolubilia-Literature of the Middle Ages." Director: Hans G. Herzberger. Specializations Research Specialty: Mediaeval logic and semantic theory, Mediaeval Philosophy. Teaching Specialties: History of Philosophy, Phenomenology and Existentialism (particularly Sartre and Kierkegaard), Philosophy of Religion. Professional Academic Positions 1972–1975, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Indiana University. 1975–1981, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Indiana University. 1980–1986, Executive Committee, Society for Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy. 1980 (summer), member of the faculty of the Institute on Medieval Philosophy (Norman Kretzmann, Director), held at Cornell University under the auspices of the Council for Philosophical Studies and the National Endowment for the Humanities. 1981–2011, Professor of Philosophy, Indiana University. 2011– . Professor Philosophy Emeritus, Indiana University. 1981–1986, Editor, Society for Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy Newsletter. 1981–1984, Co-Chairman, Publications Committee, Society for Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy. 1982–1984, Program Committee for 1984 meetings, American Philosophical Association (Western Division).
    [Show full text]