IDEALIZNIONXI: Historicalstudies on Abstractionand Ideal Tzation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

IDEALIZNIONXI: Historicalstudies on Abstractionand Ideal Tzation (Aoev MrcruEulczUNn'snsrry) POZNAN STLDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHYOF THE SCIENCESAND THE HLMANITIES IDEALIZNIONXI: HistoricalStudies on Abstractionand Ideal tzation Editedby FrancescoConiglione, RobertoPoli andRobin Rollinger Poanaí Stu.lies in the Philosophl of the ScienL'esarul the Hunanities 2001. Vol.82, pp. 125 l1ó LeenSpruit AGENT INTELLECT AND PHANTASMS. ON THE PRELIMINARIESOF PERIPATETICABSTRACTION Abstract. This paper discussessome aspectsof the controversiesregarding the operationof the agentintellect on sensoryimages. I selectivelyconsider viervs developed between the l3th century and the beginning of the 17th century, focusing on positions which question the need for a (distinct)agent intellect or arguefor its essential"inactivity" rvith respectto phantasms.My aim is to reveal limitations of the Peripateticalframervork for analyzingand explainingthe mechanisms involved in conceptualabstraction. The first sectionsurveys developments of Aristoteliannoetics and abstractionin Ancient and Arabic philosophy. The secondsection presents a discussionof some"positive" accountson abstractionand the agentintellect, and some"nesative" accounrs. In Peripatetic psychology intellectual knowledge arises from the interplay betweenthe mind and sensoryimages. The possibleintellect receives what has beenisolated or abstractedfrom sensoryrepresentations by the agentintellect. In contrastwith the direct grasp of cognitive contentin the phantasms!as Aristotle had suggestedin De anima, the majority of medieval and RenaissancePeripatetics posited a mediatedassimilation of the essenceof sensiblereality, interpretingthe Aristotelianpsychology of cognition in terms of a theory of abstraction.The agentintellect plays a crucial role in conceptual abstraction.It is viewed as the active faculty of human mind or else as a separatesubstance which groundsempiricai knowledgeby illuminating or processingsensory images. The operationof the agentintellect in intellection was intenselydiscussed by ancient,medieval and early modern Aristotelians. Thesedisputes regarded both the ontology of the agentintellect and its role in generatinghuman knowledge.In this paper,I will discusssome aspects of the controversiesregarding the operationof the agentintellect on sensoryimages.l rThe following issueswill not be discussed.(1) The varioustypes ofabstraction rvhich some authorsdistinguish; cf. the list of six intellectualabstractions in Paul of Venice ( I 504), f. I 55rb: (i) "actuatio phantasmatis";(ii) "depuratio", that is, "productio specieiintelligibilis ex phanrasmate tamquam ex causa effectiva"; (iii) "separatio", leading to a more general concept; (iv) "specificatio", consisting in the production of "second order" species; (v) "compositio" of concepts;(vi) "deductio". See also Castaneus(1645),2. who distinguishedbetr.veen four types of t26 Lcen Spruit What doesthe agentintellect exactly do rvith the phantasms?Does it merely reveal their intelligible core or does it processsensory images and (re) constructs mental content'l I lvill selectively consider viervs developed betr,veenthe l3th centuryrand the beginningof the lTth centuryr,focusrng on positionswhich questionthe needfor a (distinct)agent intellect or arguefor its essential"inactivity" with respectto phantasms.My aim is to reveal limitationsof the Peripateticalfrarnervork for analysingand explainingthe mechanismsinvolved in conceptualabstraction. The first section brief-ly surveysdevelopments of Aristoteliannoetics and abstractionin Ancient and Arabic philosophy.The second section presentsa discussionof some "positive" accountson abstractionand the agentintellect, and some"negative" accounts. 1.Aristotle. Alexander and theArabs Aristotle'spsychology of cognitionis developedalong the linesof an integra- ted model of perceptualand noeticactivity. An objectof thought(noeton') is made presentto the mind in virtue of a thought(noema) and this. in turn, requiresan image (phantasma).Aristotle did not havea full-fledgedpsycho- logicalor epistemologicaltheory of abstraction.And his useof termssuch as choriston andaphairesls does not entitle us to assumethat he had such a abstraction,namely, "habitualis" (throughirrpressed and inherentspecies), "actualis'' (through the intellectual act). "cognitiva". and "factiva". (2) irbstractionas an act of the possible intellect (a position endorsedby. among others. Zabarella and Suarez).(3) The issue of rvhetherthe final outcomeof abstractionis an individual fbrm or species,or else a universal.Some iiuthors distinguishedbetrveen two momentsin the generationof intellectualknorvled,ge. In "first order" intellection.a concretenotion of a singuìaressencc is generated:then the intellecîis able to engenderuniversals. See Thomas Wilton (1964), I l9; Gregoryof Rimini (1979-198.1),Super t, dist.3. q. l,352: John Buridan (1518).f.3ra: Paul ofVenice (1503),90vb, and idem (1504). l37rb; Lefèvre cl'Étaples(1525), 221r'-Pornponazzi (1966). 204; Fracastoro(157,{), l29r-v: Castaneus(16.15), 101: Colle-qiumConimbricense (1616). 307b; Suarez (1856), 122a-28a: Collegium Complutense(1637). 300a and 307b. (4) The doctrineof sensìbleand intelligible specieslsome opponentsol the speciesalso rcjectedthe agent intellect:cf. the positionsof Olivi and Durandus(infro'). (5') Only marginally attentionrvill be paíd to ìnnatisticaccounts of the agent intcllect. r Early medieval authors,such as Abelard, John oî Salisbury nnd Hugh of Saint Victor. use the term "abstractio".resuming Boethius' translationoî aphairesis.but before the rediscoveryof Peripateticpsychology in the West there is no systematicreflection on the role of the agent intellectin psychologicalconceptualisation. t Late 17th-centuryScholastic rvorks on psychology show an extensive but often sterile confiontation with authoritativesources: they no longer succeededin devising fresh insights or new methodsand approachesfor tackling in a novel way the central qucstionshanded dorvn by tradìtion. Agr'nt Inteller'r and Phantasms 12'7 theory. In Aristotle, the term abstraction(aphairesís) is mostly usedin logical contexts, indicating a method of subtractionwhich isolates objects for scientificstudy.a In a mathematicalcontext. Aristotle usedthe ferm chorizein.5 A brief analysisof three passagesfrom De anima, rvhich are often cited as evidencethat Aristotle held a psychologicalor epistemologicaltheory of abstraction,confirms our claim. In the first of thesepassages the terminology has a definite ontologicalsense (429b18-23). In the second(43lb12-19), ir refers to a set of mathematicalentities that are logically isolatedand grasped conceptuallythrough the methodof substraction.In the third passage(432a3- 9), the terminologyof abstractionrefers to a realm of intelligible entities r.vhosemode of being is that of dependenceupon sensiblesubstances. According to Aristotle, knowledgeis the graspingof objectswith a noetic status.Sensible forms becomenoetic objects in virtue of the agent intellect. The light metaphorfor the latter's activity doesnot supportan abstractionistor acquisitionalaccount of knowledge. As efficient cause of thinking, the productive mind illuminates what is already there and makes possible the generationof mental representationsof the externalworid in human thought. No preliminary abstractionis required. The agent intellect actualizesnoeta, that is, it generatesor reveals (Aristotle was not clear on this point) the intelligible core contained in the sensoryinformation. Notice that Aristotle regarded the relation between phantasm and active mind to be quite unproblematic,even though there is an overt ontologicalgap betweenthe two elementsinvolved. The roots of the Peripatetictheory of psychologicalabstraction are in Alexander of Aphrodisias.In his De anima, Alexander describedintellectual apprehensionas separating(chorizein) (cf. Alexander1887, p. 90, 1I l) forms from any possible material circumstance(pp. 84, 87-8). In this rvork, Alexanderconcentrated on the capacitiesof the human (material)intellect. The latter is capable of abstractingand grasping both material and immaterial forms. He remainedrather vague about the role of the active mind, identified r.viththe supremeintelligible and first cause,and ensuring the possibility of intellectualknowledge at a metaphysicallevel (pp. 88-9). ln De intellectu6, Alexanderattributed a more precise(cognitive) role to the active mind. As an actually intelligible form the agent intellect enablesthe material intellect to o SeeCleary ( I 9lì5), pp. I 3-zl5,in particularpp. 36-215where De anima. l29bl I -23 and llt.7,g areexamined. 5 Also here, however, he spoke of "subtraction", that is, of separationof certain aspectsof sensible bodies in such a way that they can serve as the primary subjects of mathemaîical attributes. o The authenticity of this work is challenged by Moraux (1942) and defencledby Bazén fl973). 128 Leen Spruit separateforms from matter. Once actualizedby the agentintellect the human intellectimitates this intellect by knowing, which basicallyconsists in making materialobjects intelligible (Alexander 1887, pp. 107-108,110). At a larer stage,the human intellect will also be able to capturepure intelligibles (pp. 110-1).Trvo Alexandrianvier,vs became crucial for further developmentsof Peripateticreflection on the agentintellect: (i) the latter's activity may invesr (also) the potential intellect, leading it to perform its proper activity, and (ii) abstractionis viewed as an activity of the intellectin habitu (seealso Moraux 1942,p.121f;Bazdn 1973, p. 480). Arabic accounts of abstractionwere
Recommended publications
  • Pomponazzi on Identity and Individuation Han Thomas Adriaenssen Abstract. Aristotle Defines Growing As a Process in Which An
    Final version forthcoming in Journal of the History of Philosophy Pomponazzi on Identity and Individuation Han Thomas Adriaenssen Abstract. Aristotle defines growing as a process in which an individual living being persists as it accumulates new matter. This definition raises the question of what enables an individual to persist as its material composition continuously changes over time. This paper provides a systematic account of Pietro Pomponazzi’s answer to this question. In his De nutritione et augmentatione, Pomponazzi argues that individuals persist in virtue of their forms. Forms are individuated in part by their material, causal, and temporal origins, which commits Pomponazzi to the view that individuals necessarily have the material, causal, and temporal origins they do. I provide an account of why Pomponazzi was willing to this view. While his opponents remain unnamed, I argue that his arguments for this view are best read as addressing, among others, Paul of Venice and Gregory of Rimini. In On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle describes growing as a process in which “any and every part of the growing magnitude is made bigger . by the accession of something, and thirdly in such a way that the growing thing is preserved and persists” (321a18–22).1 For instance, when an animal grows as the result of the intake of food, all of its limbs grow larger as the result of the intake of new matter, in such a way that the same individual animal persists throughout the process. 1 All Aristotle translations are taken from the Jonathan Barnes edition of the Complete Works. 1 Final version forthcoming in Journal of the History of Philosophy Simple though it may perhaps appear, this definition confronted Aristotle’s later followers and commentators with a problem.
    [Show full text]
  • Eric W. Hagedorn Curriculum Vitae
    Eric W. Hagedorn Curriculum Vitae Areas of Specialization: Medieval Philosophy Areas of Competence: Metaphysics; Early Modern Philosophy; Philosophy of Religion; Philosophy of Mind; Logic Employment St. Norbert College Associate Professor Philosophy (August 2018-Present) Assistant Professor of Philosophy (January 2014 – August 2018) Teaching Fellow of Philosophy (August 2012 – December 2013) Education University of Notre Dame Ph.D. in Philosophy (January 2013) M.A. in Philosophy (January 2008) Iowa State University B.S. with Honors in Computer Science and Philosophy (May 2004) Journal Articles and Book Chapters “Thomas Aquinas through the 1350s,” in The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Ethics, ed. Thomas Williams (forthcoming). “Ockham’s Scientia Argument for Mental Language,” Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 3 (2015): 145-168. "Is Anyone Else Thinking My Thoughts?: Aquinas's Response to the Too-Many Thinkers Problem," Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 84 (2010): 275-86. Book Reviews Review of John Duns Scotus, On Being and Cognition: Ordinatio I.3, John van den Bercken (tr.) in International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion (forthcoming). Review of Claude Panaccio, Mental Language: From Plato to William of Ockham in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (August 2017). Review of Jari Kaukua and Tomas Ekenberg (eds.), Subjectivity and Selfhood in Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (September 2016). Review of Sander W. de Boer, The Science of the Soul: The Commentary
    [Show full text]
  • Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2021 M
    Z Zabarella, Jacopo chair of logic, succeeding Tomitano. On 4 January 1569 he secured the second extraordinary chair of Born: 5 September 1533, Padua natural philosophy. There was likely a pause in his Died: 15 October 1589, Padua teaching from 1574 to 1576 on account of the severity of plague in Padua. On 26 March 1577 Marco Sgarbi he acquired the first extraordinary chair of natural Ca’ Foscari University of Venice, Venice, Italy philosophy, and in 1578, he published his Opera logica in Venice, thus opening a large debate on the Abstract order and method of knowledge among his con- temporaries – especially with Francesco Jacopo Zabarella (1553–1589) is considered Piccolomini (1520–1604) and Bernardino Petrella one of the most acute and brilliant logicians (1529–1595). In 1580 Zabarella published his of all time. He made an important contribution Tabulae logicae and also founded the Accademia to the interpretation of Aristotle and developed degli Stabili. In 1584, he came under attack in two original ideas especially in the field of logic directions: from Piccolomini in his Universa and epistemology, opening up the pathway of philosophia de moribus, and from Petrella in his early modern science. Logicarum disputationum libri VII. The same year, Zabarella’s reply to Piccolomini was his De doctrina ordine apologia. In the meantime, on Biography 6 September 1585, he became professor of the second ordinary chair of natural philosophy, and He was born in Padua on 5 September 1533, the the following year he published his De naturalis eldest son of Giulio Zabarella. He was well-versed scientiae constitutione.
    [Show full text]
  • The Unity of Science in Early-Modern Philosophy: Subalternation, Metaphysics and the Geometrical Manner in Scholasticism, Galileo and Descartes
    The Unity of Science in Early-Modern Philosophy: Subalternation, Metaphysics and the Geometrical Manner in Scholasticism, Galileo and Descartes by Zvi Biener M.A. in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2004 B.A. in Physics, Rutgers University, 1995 B.A. in Philosophy, Rutgers University, 1995 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2008 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Zvi Biener It was defended on April 3, 2008 and approved by Peter Machamer J.E. McGuire Daniel Garber James G. Lennox Paolo Palmieri Dissertation Advisors: Peter Machamer, J.E. McGuire ii Copyright c by Zvi Biener 2008 iii The Unity of Science in Early-Modern Philosophy: Subalternation, Metaphysics and the Geometrical Manner in Scholasticism, Galileo and Descartes Zvi Biener, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2008 The project of constructing a complete system of knowledge—a system capable of integrating all that is and could possibly be known—was common to many early-modern philosophers and was championed with particular alacrity by Ren´eDescartes. The inspiration for this project often came from mathematics in general and from geometry in particular: Just as propositions were ordered in a geometrical demonstration, the argument went, so should propositions be ordered in an overall system of knowledge. Science, it was thought, had to proceed more geometrico. I offer a new interpretation of ‘science more geometrico’ based on an analysis of the explanatory forms used in certain branches of geometry. These branches were optics, as- tronomy, and mechanics; the so-called subalternate, subordinate, or mixed-mathematical sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Walter Burley on the Kinds of Simple Supposition1
    Walter Burley on The Kinds of Simple Supposition 1 PAUL VINCENT SPADE 1. Background By the early-fourteenth century at the latest, the mediaeval theory of supposition could be divided in most authors into two main branches, which in recent literature have come to be called the theory of “suppo- sition proper” and the theory of “modes of personal supposition,” respec- tively.2 While the relation between these two branches remains obscure, we can say to a rst approximation that the theory of supposition proper was atheory of “reference,” designed to answer the question what entity or enti- ties a term refers to or “supposits” for in a given occurrence in a given proposition, whereas the theory of modes of personal supposition, whatever its ultimate purpose, was the part of the theory that included the much- discussed accounts of “descent to singulars” and “ascent from singulars.”3 Walter Burley and his somewhat younger contemporary, William of Ockham, for the most part agreed about the modes of personal supposition, 4 1 I am grateful to Rega Wood and Elizabeth Karger for their comments and sugges- tions on an earlier draft of this paper. 2 See Paul Vincent Spade, The Semantics of Terms , in: Norman Kretzmann et al. (ed.), The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy , New York 1982, Ch. 9 (188-96). This ter- minology was rst used by T.K. Scott in the “Introduction” to his translation of John Buridan’s Sophismata, and is not mediaeval. See T.K. Scott (trans.), John Buridan: Sophisms on Meaning and Truth , New York 1966, 29-42.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy May 20, 2013
    Outline of Philosophy May 20, 2013 Contents SOCI>Philosophy .............................................................................................................................................................. 3 SOCI>Philosophy>Aesthetics ....................................................................................................................................... 3 SOCI>Philosophy>Aesthetics>Beauty .................................................................................................................... 4 SOCI>Philosophy>Aesthetics>Theory .................................................................................................................... 4 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology ................................................................................................................................. 5 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>Possibility ......................................................................................................... 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>World ................................................................................................................ 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>Object Properties .............................................................................................. 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>System Properties ............................................................................................. 6 SOCI>Philosophy>Epistemology>Representation .................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Lodovico Settala's Aristotelian Problemata Commentary and Late
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Archivio istituzionale della ricerca - Università degli Studi di Venezia Ca' Foscari Lodovico Settala’s Aristotelian Problemata Commentary and Late-Renaissance Hippocratic Medicine Craig Martin Key phrases Aristotelian Problemata; Hippocratic Airs, Waters, Places; Renaissance humanism; Lodovico Settala; Girolamo Cardano Abstract Renaissance physicians, influenced by humanism and spurred by their increased knowledge of Hippocratic and Galenic writings, attempted to assimilate these medical works with Aristotelian thought. The similarities between the Aristotelian Problemata and the Hippocratic Airs, Waters, Places allowed Girolamo Cardano and Lodovico Settala, among others, to blur the distinctions between natural philosophical and medical authorities. Philological and historical considerations of these texts as well as judgments about authenticity were colored by the belief that these works were useful for humoral physiology and offered insights into the unity of ancient and modern knowledge. 1 Introduction Late-Renaissance Italian intellectual debate often involved attempts to change or defend the status of particular disciplines. The hierarchy of subjects was frequently a matter for dispute, and leading intellectual figures attempted to raise the status of their particular fields. Just as this was true for mixed mathematics, it was also true for medicine. A number of physicians attempted 1 to promote the status of medicine by defining it as part
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE 2400 YEARS PROGRAMME.Pdf
    1 PROGRAMME Presentations’ Duration: • Invited Speakers in Plenary Sessions: 45΄ presentation & 15΄ discussion • Invited Speakers in Concurrent Sessions: 40΄ presentation & discussion • All Participants with contributed papers: 20΄ presentation & discussion 2 World Congress “Aristotle 2400 Years” Programme Schedule Monday May 23, 2016 8:00 Registration 10:30-12:30 Welcome City Tour 13:00-14:30 Concurrent Sessions A Invited Speaker Session A • Robert Bolton (USA) Techne and Empeiria: Aristotle's Contributions to the Tradition 14:30-16:00 Break / Free time 16:00-17:30 Concurrent Sessions B Invited Speaker Session B • George Contogeorgis (Greece) Ο Αριςτοτζλθσ και θ δθμοκρατία (Aristotle and Democracy) 17:30-18:00 Break 18:00-20:00 Opening Ceremony - Welcoming Remarks Inaugural Address • Evanghelos Moutsopoulos (Greece) Plenary Lecture A • Demetra Sfendoni-Mentzou (Greece) Aristotle’s Dynamic Vision of Nature and Contemporary Physics 20:00 Welcome Reception 3 World Congress “Aristotle 2400 Years” Tuesday May 24, 2016 8:00 Registration 9:00-10:30 Concurrent Sessions C Invited Speaker Session C • Dermot Moran (Ireland) Aristotle’s Conception of Ousia in the Medieval Christian Tradition: Some Neoplatonic Reflections 10:30-11:00 Break 11:00-12:00 Plenary Lecture B • Abraham Bos (The Netherlands) Aristotle on God’s Life-Generating Power and on Pneuma 12:00 Departure for ancient Mieza 13:30 Arrival to ancient Mieza 13:30-14:30 Welcoming Reception of the Mayor of Naoussa 14:30-15:30 Plenary Lecture C • Lambros Couloubaritsis (Belgium/Greece) The Complex Organisation of Aristotle's Thought 15:30-17:30 Guided Tour 17:30 Departure for Thessaloniki 19:00 Arrival to Thessaloniki 19:30-21:00 Plenary Lecture / Public Event: Armand Marie Leroi (UK) Aristotle & the New Biology 4 World Congress “Aristotle 2400 Years” Wednesday May 25, 2016 8:00 Registration 9:00-10:30 Concurrent Sessions D Invited Speaker Session D • Loucas G.
    [Show full text]
  • A Companion to Walter Burley Brill’S Companions to the Christian Tradition
    A Companion to Walter Burley Brill’s Companions to the Christian Tradition A series of handbooks and reference works on the intellectual and religious life of Europe, 500–1800 Editor-in-Chief Christopher M. Bellitto (Kean University) VOLUME 41 The titles published in this series are listed at brill.com/bcct A Companion to Walter Burley Late Medieval Logician and Metaphysician Edited by Alessandro D. Conti LEIDEN • BOSTON 2013 Cover illustration: detail from the sculptured funerary monument of Giovanni da Legnano (1320–83), Doctor utriusque iuris of the University of Bologna. Courtesy of the Museo Civico Medievale of Bologna. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A companion to Walter Burley : late medieval logician and metaphysician / Edited by Alessandro D. Conti. p. cm. — (Brill’s companions to the Christian tradition ; Volume 41) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-90-04-24461-0 (hardback : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-90-04-24460-3 (e-book) 1. Burlaeus, Gualterus, 1275–1345? 2. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Conti, Alessandro D. B765.B8484C66 2013 189’.4—dc23 2013002068 This publication has been typeset in the multilingual “Brill” typeface. With over 5,100 characters covering Latin, IPA, Greek, and Cyrillic, this typeface is especially suitable for use in the humanities. For more information, please see www.brill.com/brill-typeface. ISSN 1871-6377 ISBN 978-90-04-24461-0 (hardback) ISBN 978-90-04-24460-3 (e-book) Copyright 2013 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Global Oriental, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers and Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Walter Burley, the Longer Treatise on the Purity of the Art of Logic Tract 1
    1 Walter Burley, The Longer Treatise On the Purity of the Art of Logic 5 Tract 1: “On the Properties of Terms” Translated by Paul Vincent Spade Indiana University 10 (1) Assuming the significates of non-complex terms, in this treatise I intend to investigate certain properties of terms, [properties] that are applica- ble to them only insofar as they are parts of propositions. (2) Now I divide this tract into three parts. The first is about the sup- position of terms, the second about appellation, and the third about copula- 15 tion. Supposition belongs to the subject, appellation to the predicate. Copula- tion belongs to the verb that couples the predicate with the subject. For these three are the integral parts of the categorical proposition, to which we turn before [treating] hypotheticals.1 Hence in this tract I want to talk about the suppositions of terms in categoricals. 20 [Part One: On Supposition] (3) The first part will contain six chapters. The first chapter is about the division of supposition in general. The second chapter is about material supposition. The third chapter is about simple supposition. The fourth chapter is about the division of personal supposition in general. The fifth chapter is 25 about various difficulties that arise concerning personal supposition. The sixth chapter is about improper supposition. 1 Hypothetical propositions are propositions composed of two or more categoricals. A categorical proposition is, in modern logical terminology, either an atomic proposition or else the negation of an atomic proposition. Hence the notion of a hypothetical proposition is not exactly the same as the modern notion of a “molecular” proposition, since the negations of atomic propositions are molecular but not hypothetical.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded from Brill.Com10/09/2021 12:18:49PM Via Free Access 442 BIBLIOGRAPHY
    BIBLIOGRAPHY In the following Bibliography and Index, ancient and medieval authors are listed by their first names (e.g., John Philoponus; Roger Bacon; etc.). Post­ medieval authors are listed by their last names (e.g., Zabarella; Descartes; etc.). The medieval names are given in their English forms, as Thomas Aquinas (rather than Tommaso d'Aquino; Thomas von Aquin, etc.) I. Manuscripts ANONYMUS, Quaestiones super De generatione et corruptione. Cambridge, Peter­ house College, 192, fols. 119vb-132vb. -, Quaestiones super Metaphysicam, 1-1v. Assisi, Biblioteca Comunale, 290, fols. 65ra-85rb. - , Quaestiones super Physicam. Cambridge, Gonville and Caius College, 344, fols. io5rb_17ovb. - , Quaestiones super Physicam. Cambridge, Gonville and Caius College, 367, fols. 120r"-125vb, i36ra-151vb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, I, 1v-v1. Cambridge, Peterhouse College, 192, IV, fols. 53ra-96vb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-III. London, Wellcome Historical Medical Library, 333, fols. 8'"-68vb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, I-IV, v, (Fragm.). Oxford, Merton College, 272, fols. i36ra-174Brb. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, 1, m-1v. Oxford, Merton College, 272, fols. 1 19ra-135crb. - , Quaestiones super Physicam, I-V. Oxford, Oriel College, 33, fols. 8'"-7gvh. -, Quaestiones super Physicam, 1-vm. Siena, Biblioteca Comunale degli Intronati, L.II1.21, fols. 1ra-92ra. - , Sententia libri Physicorum "extracta de verbo ad verbum," 1-v. Oxford, Bodleian Library, Lat. Misc. c. 69, fols. i ra-41 rb. ANONYMUS (=GILES OF ORLEANS (?)), Quaestiones super Physicam, I-VIII. Paris, Bibliotheque Nationale de France, lat. 14698, fols. 83ra-129Ar. BARILE, E. (ED.), Rotuli Artistarum (r430-r8r5). Unpublished MS, Antico Archivio dell'Universita, Padova. BARTHOLOMEW OF BRUGES, Quaestiones super Physicam, 1-V, VII, VIII.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Philosophy
    Natural philosophy Natural philosophy or philosophy of nature (from Latin philosophia naturalis) was the philosophical study of nature and the physical universe that was dominant before the development of modern science. It is considered to be the precursor of natural science. From the ancient world, starting with Aristotle, to the 19th century, the term "natural philosophy" was the common term used to describe the practice of studying nature. It was in the 19th century that the A celestial map from the 17th century, by the concept of "science" received its modern shape with Dutch cartographer Frederik de Wit new titles emerging such as "biology" and "biologist", "physics" and "physicist" among other technical fields and titles; institutions and communities were founded, and unprecedented applications to and interactions with other aspects of society and culture occurred.[1] Isaac Newton's book Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687 ), whose title translates to "Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy", reflects the then-current use of the words "natural philosophy", akin to "systematic study of nature". Even in the 19th century, a treatise by Lord Kelvin and Peter Guthrie Tait, which helped define much of modern physics, was titled Treatise on Natural Philosophy (1867 ). In the German tradition, Naturphilosophie (philosophy of nature) persisted into the 18th and 19th century as an attempt to achieve a speculative unity of nature and spirit. Some of the greatest names in German philosophy are associated with this movement, including Goethe, Hegel and Schelling. Naturphilosophie was associated with Romanticism and a view that regarded the natural world as a kind of giant organism, as opposed to the philosophical approach of figures such as John Locke and Isaac Newton who espoused a more mechanical view of the world, regarding it as being like a machine.
    [Show full text]