Reid on the Real Foundation of the Primary/Secondary Quality Distinction
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Thomas Reid on Consciousness and Attention 165 Volume 39, Number 2, June 2009, Pp
CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHYThomas Reid on Consciousness and Attention 165 Volume 39, Number 2, June 2009, pp. 165-194 Thomas Reid on Consciousness and Attention GIDEON YAFFE University of Southern California Los Angeles, CA 90089 USA I Introduction It was common enough in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries to fi nd philosophers holding the position that for something to be ‘in the mind’ and for that mind to be conscious of it are one and the same thing. The thought is that consciousness is a relation between a mind and a mental entity playing the same role as the relation of inherence found between a substance and qualities belonging to it. What it is, on this view, for something to ‘inhere’ in the mind is for that mind to be conscious of it. Locke was explicit in his acceptance of such a claim, writing, for instance, [T]o be in the Mind, and, never to be perceived, is all one, as to say, any thing is, and is not, in the Mind.1 The implication here is that it is a fl at contradiction to assert that some- thing is in the mind and ‘unperceived’ where a mind ‘perceives’ some- 1 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Nidditch, P. H. (ed.), Ox- ford: Clarendon Press, 1975, I.ii.5. 166 Gideon Yaffe thing, in this context, just in case it is conscious of it. On this issue, as on many others, Locke’s position was accepted almost verbatim by the most infl uential Anglophone philosophers of the century that followed, including even those, such as Thomas Reid, who opposed many of the tenets of Locke’s philosophy of mind. -
Reverse Engineering Epistemic Evaluations
Reverse Engineering Epistemic Evaluations Sinan Dogramaci∗ 1 A Puzzle: What Is the Function of Epistemically Evaluative Language? What is the function of words like `irrational' as used in ordinary epistemic evaluations? I'm thinking of simple evaluations: criticism like `Smith's belief that Obama's a Muslim is irrational' or praise like `Green's belief that all humans are mortal is rational'. We don't make such claims just for the sake of it, just for fun, or for no reason at all. So what is the real point or purpose of this epistemically evaluative aspect of our linguistic practice? It must have some utility, but what? What would we lose if epistemically evaluative words suddenly disappeared from our vocabulary?1 The question requires some motivation, since discovering a word's func- tion doesn't necessarily call for armchair philosophy. Some words might serve a hidden psycho-sociological function that only empirical science can uncover. This might be true of words like `hello' and `thanks'. And for many words, their basic function isn't particularly mysterious. For example, we ∗I pronounce it, when speaking English, like this: sin·on dor·uh·mudge·uh. 1The question of this paper thus contrasts with the timeworn questions of how to give necessary and sufficient conditions for this or that philosophically interesting property. There are, however, a few excellent philosophical explorations of the function of this or that philosophically interesting word or concept. In philosophy of logic and language, Quine offered an elegantly simple insight about the utility of the truth predicate which precipitated the contemporary development of deflationism about truth; see Quine (1970), Leeds (1978), Horwich (1990/98), and Field (1994). -
Philosophies of Common Sense
Philosophies of Common Sense Fall 2009 - Winter 2010 This course will focus on a series of philosophers whose work can be loosely characterized as philosophy of common sense, namely, Hume, Reid, Moore, Austin, and among contemporaries, Mark Wilson. Our goal will be to trace a number of inter-related meta- philosophical themes: naturalism, the nature and viability of conceptual analysis, and the role of ordinary language. (The ‘naturalism’ in question will often be the specific form I call ‘Second Philosophy’, so some grasp of that approach, as in Maddy [2007] or [200?], would be useful as background.) Skepticism, and particularly the Argument from Illusion, will feature as a recurring case study for comparing and contrasting these various approaches to philosophical inquiry. The default requirement for those taking the course for a grade (other than S/U) is three short papers (750-1250 words) due at the beginning of class in the 4th week, 7th week, and 10th week. Each paper should isolate one localized point in the readings and offer some analysis and/or critique. Other options are open to negotiation. I assume everyone has access to copies of: J. L. Austin, Sense and Sensibilia. Mark Wilson, Wandering Significance. All other assigned materials are available to enrolled students at the links below. Copies of these books will be available in Brian Rogers’s office (795 SST): Austin, Philosophical Papers. Baldwin, G. E. Moore. 2 Cuneo and Woudenberg, Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid. Fratantaro, The Methodology of G. E. Moore. Moore, Philosophical Papers. Philosophical Studies. Some Main Problems of Philosophy. Reid, An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense. -
Internalism Explained* Ralph Wedgwood
Internalism Explained* Ralph Wedgwood 1. The word ‘rational’ is used in many ways. But when the word is used in the way that is most common among philosophers, the following intuition seems compelling. Consider two possible worlds, w1 and w2. In both worlds, you have exactly the same experiences, apparent memories, and intuitions, and in both worlds you go through exactly the same processes of reasoning, and form exactly the same beliefs. In this case, it seems, exactly the same beliefs are rational in both worlds, and exactly the same beliefs are irrational in both worlds. Now suppose that in w1 you are bedevilled by an evil demon who ensures that many of your experiences are misleading, with the result that many of the beliefs that you hold in w1 are false. In w2, on the other hand, almost all your experiences are veridical, with the result that almost all the beliefs that you hold in w2 are true. Intuitively, this makes no difference at all. Exactly the same beliefs are rational and irrational in both worlds.1 This intuition seems to support an “internalist” conception of rational belief. According to this conception, the rationality of a belief supervenes purely on “internal facts” about the thinker’s mental states — in this example, on facts that hold in both these two possible worlds w1 and w2, not on facts about the external world that vary between w1 and w2. Moreover, this seems to be a completely general feature of rationality, since a parallel claim seems plausible with respect to rational decisions or choices as well. -
Locke's Distinctions Between Primary and Secondary Qualities
Locke’s Distinctions Between Primary and Secondary Qualities Michael Jacovides1 Is there a distinction between primary and secondary qualities? The question may rest on a confusion. It is not obvious that it would be raised if the questioner knew what he meant by ‘primary’ and ‘secondary’ qualities. There is at least this distinction. We may distinguish between the basic explanatory features of things and the derivative features they explain. In the disciplines that gave rise to chemistry, there’s a long tradition of calling the fundamental explanatory qualities or principles ‘firsts’ (Maier 1968: 17-18, Anstey 2000: 20-30). Aristotle’s ‘first qualities’ are hot, cold, dry, and wet; Paracelsus’s tria prima (‘three firsts’) are salt, sulphur, and mercury. Boyle was willing to follow Aristotelian usage in calling hot, cold, dry, and wet ‘first qualities’; he called what he considered to be the more fundamental attributes of size, shape, motion, and rest “Primary Modes of the parts of Matter, since from these simple Attributes or Primordiall Affections all the Qualities are deriv’d” (Boyle [1670] 1999: 6.267). If Locke were only interested in advocating mechanistic physics, his discussion of primary and secondary qualities would be of marginal interest. Long before the publication of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Boyle offers a defense of the thesis that “allmost all sorts of Qualities . may be produced Mechanically—I mean by such Corporeall Agents as do not appear, either to Work otherwise than by vertue of the Motion, Size, Figure, and Contrivance of their own Parts” (Boyle [1666] 1999: 5.302) which is clearer and more developed than Locke’s defense. -
Berkeley's Theory of Common Sense
Berkeley Studies 24 (2013) 3 Berkeley’s Theory of Common Sense Matthew Holtzman Abstract: This essay situates Berkeley’s views on common sense within the context of eighteenth- century debates about the nature of common sense. It argues that in his Notebooks, Berkeley develops a theory according to which to possess common sense is to use the faculties of the mind properly, and that Berkeley’s approach to common sense can be understood as a response to John Toland’s epistemology of religion. It concludes with a discussion of consequences of this analysis for our understanding of Berkeley’s later works, his methods, and his overarching philosophical aims. In The Principles of Human Knowledge (PHK) and Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (DHP), Berkeley argues that matter does not exist (PHK 9),1 that spirit is the only substance (PHK 6), and that physical objects are not causes but signs (PHK 66). If these claims initially shock readers’ philosophical sensibilities, the effort required to come to terms with them will seem familiar enough. One must take pains to work one’s way into a perspective from which they can be seen as not only consistent but mutually supporting or even inevitable. Yet Berkeley seems firmly to deny that effort is required, for he repeatedly insists that his philosophy agrees with common sense: immaterialism is difficult to accept not because it is abstruse, but because readers come to it corrupted by modern philosophy.2 Learning to accept immaterialism is not like an initiation into an esoteric system of thought, but, as Berkeley claims in the preface to the Three Dialogues, like a long journey home (DHP 2:168). -
Substance, Causation and Free Will in Spinoza and Leibniz
6x9:Layout 1 8/21/2008 2:00 PM Page 17 a0rxh/ Substance, Causation and Free Will in Spinoza and Leibniz ROSS WOLFE Pennsylvania State University In Western monotheism, it is believed that God possesses all of man’s moral features in their perfection—that indeed man was created in His1 (spiritual) image. It follows from this doctrine that He possesses a perfect will, which guides the fates of men and the material flow of reality. This divine attribute is usually referred to as Providence. Much energy has been devoted through the ages to reconciling our own claim to free will as humans with this transcendent will of God. But a more fundamental question remains to be asked, if one considers the logical intricacies this notion. For how can it be logically consistent that God’s determinations are freely chosen, if every one of these choices can be traced back to prior causes that themselves demand that certain necessary effects result? If one were to pursue the logic of this proposition back to its strictest foundation (the causa sui), he would be forced to conclude that there was never any point at which a deviation could have occurred, where different possibilities might have emerged. The conception of God as acting freely according to His will would thus seem fundamentally flawed in this system of causation. This apparent contradiction was the occasion of a major controversy at the close of the seventeenth century. The iconic philosophers Baruch Spinoza and Gottfried Wil- helm Leibniz stood at opposite poles in this debate. The former’s final treatise, The Ethics, lays forth the provocative assertion that God lacks free will. -
Ideas and Explanation in Early Modern Philosophy∗
Ideas and Explanation in Early Modern Philosophy∗ Kenneth L. Pearce Trinity College Dublin March 9, 2019 Abstract Malebranche argues that ideas are representative beings existing in God. He defends this thesis by an inference to the best explanation of human perception. It is well known that Malebranche's theory of vision in God was forcefully rejected by philosophers such as Arnauld, Locke, and Berkeley. However, the notion that ideas exist in God was not the only controversial aspect of Malebranche's approach. Another controversy centered around Malebranche's view that ideas are to be understood as posits in an explanatory theory. Opponents of this approach, including Arnauld and Locke, held that our talk about ideas was not explanatory but instead merely descriptive: we use the word `idea' to describe phenomena that we observe by reflecting on our own minds. This controversy has not received much attention from scholars, but in the present paper I will show that it was an explicit and important subject of concern for Malebranche, Arnuald, Locke, and Berkeley and that attention to this controversy can illuminate several aspects of these philosophers' work. For the 17th and 18th century opponents of the `New Philosophy', one of its most visible identifying features was \the talking of ideas, and running endless divisions upon them" (Browne 1697, 3; compare Stillingfleet 1697, 273; Sergeant 1697, Epistle Dedicatory).1 Since their use of the word `idea' was new and controversial, it is surprising that most early modern philosophers say so little about what they take ideas to be and why we ought to believe in such things. -
History of the Human Sciences
History of the Human Sciences http://hhs.sagepub.com Herder: culture, anthropology and the Enlightenment David Denby History of the Human Sciences 2005; 18; 55 DOI: 10.1177/0952695105051126 The online version of this article can be found at: http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/18/1/55 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com Additional services and information for History of the Human Sciences can be found at: Email Alerts: http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://hhs.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav Citations http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/18/1/55 Downloaded from http://hhs.sagepub.com at CAPES on December 11, 2009 03HHS18-1 Denby (ds) 8/3/05 8:47 am Page 55 HISTORY OF THE HUMAN SCIENCES Vol. 18 No. 1 © 2005 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) pp. 55–76 [18:1;55–76; DOI: 10.1177/0952695105051126] Herder: culture, anthropology and the Enlightenment DAVID DENBY ABSTRACT The anthropological sensibility has often been seen as growing out of opposition to Enlightenment universalism. Johann Gottfried Herder (1744–1803) is often cited as an ancestor of modern cultural relativism, in which cultures exist in the plural. This article argues that Herder’s anthropology, and anthropology generally, are more closely related to Enlightenment thought than is generally considered. Herder certainly attacks Enlightenment abstraction, the arrogance of its Eurocentric historical teleology, and argues the case for a proto-hermeneutical approach which emphasizes embeddedness, horizon, the usefulness of prejudice. His suspicion of the ideology of progress and of associated theories of stadial development leads to a critique of cosmopolitanism and, particularly, of colonialism. -
Doç. Dr. Hacı Mustafa AÇIKÖZ a BRIEF OVERVIEW of REID's
DİCLE ÜNİVERSİTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER ENSTİTÜSÜ DERGİSİ ISSN: 1308-6219 Ekim 2020 YIL-12 Sayı 25 Araştırma Makalesi / Research Article Yayın Geliş Tarihi / Article Arrival Date Yayınlanma Tarihi / The Publication Date 07.06.2020 19.10.2020 Doç. Dr. Hacı Mustafa AÇIKÖZ Muş Alparslan Üniversitesi Fen-Edebiyat Fakültesi Felsefe Bölümü [email protected] A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF REID’S PHILOSOPHY AND ITS HISTORICAL IMPACTS AT HIS 310TH BIRTH ANNIVERSARY Abstract Without referring to common sense it is impossible to act and talk both individually and socially, whether we are aware of it or not. Both action itself and act of speech brought about at the conventional realms necessarily require rational processes excluding some unhealty irational cases so that without applying common sense none can talk of rational process in any action of an agent. Thus common sense equated or matched with huge, live and matured sides of a shared, general, sound and valid conventional reason. Initially, common sense seems an inevitable accidential mode of theoretical and applicable functions of the mind. For Reid common sense in large is equated to reasion or mind as to its content, function and importance so that it is a multi functional safe heaven of human rationality. Although common sense philosophy, founded and codified by Reid, has been obvious historical impact over the philosophers of Scotland, France and America, it unfortunatelly ignored. Because notion and phenemon of common sense deliberately and unjustly negativated, for instance, Kant, as a Scotish Germanian Humeist, has an absurd and unjust role in this process. Herein we shall briefly introduce Thomas Reid’s common sense philosophy and its global influences over philosophers at 310th anniversary of his birth (i.e. -
Thomas Reid's Common-Sense Philosophy in the Development Of
Thomas Reid’s Common-Sense Philosophy in the Development of Nineteenth-Century French Spiritualism by James Crombie Université Sainte-Anne 1695 Route 1, Pointe-de-l’Église Nova Scotia, Canada james.crombie <at> usainteanne.ca Conference 19th-Century French Philosophy: The 'Spiritualist' Tradition and its Critics, 14-15 September 2017, Manchester Metropolitan University, Manchester, UK This presentation calls attention to the surprising level of influence which the Scottish philosopher Thomas Reid (1710-1796) had on nineteenth-century French philosophy – especially among professional teachers of philosophy in French universities – in particular among those identified as belonging to the so-called ‘spiritualist’ tradition. Some of the political, social, personal – and even philosophical – reasons for this phenomenon will be adumbrated. There were many figures who could be considered to be influential Reidians during the nineteenth-century in France. This presentation will focus on the major players: firstly, Royer-Collard; secondly, Cousin, Damiron and Jouffroy. Some attention will be paid, thirdly, to some of the members of the third generation: Adolphe Garnier, Amédée Jacques, Émile Saisset, Jules Simon, Adolphe Bertereau and Adolphe Franck. Pierre Maine de Biran and Joseph- Marie Degérando (aka de Gérando) are mentioned but not Pierre Prévost who, in Geneva, was publishing on the subject of Reid before he was discovered in Paris by Royer-Collard. Thomas Reid This portrait is reputed to be the only surviving visual likeness of Thomas Reid. It was painted by Sir Henry Raeburn in 1796, upon the urging of James Gregory, on the occasion of a visit by Reid, in the year in which Reid died, at the age of 86. -
A Theological Account of John Henry Newman's
“READING CUSTOM AS ILLATIVE SENSE” A THEOLOGICAL ACCOUNT OF JOHN HENRY NEWMAN’S APPROPRIATION OF A REALIST INTERPRETATION OF DAVID HUME Thesis Submitted to The College of Arts and Sciences of the UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for The Degree of Master of Arts in Theological Studies By Sean Swain Martin UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON Dayton, Ohio August, 2015 “READING CUSTOM AS ILLATIVE SENSE” A THEOLOGICAL ACCOUNT OF JOHN HENRY NEWMAN’S APPROPRIATION OF A REALIST INTERPRETATION OF DAVID HUME Name: Martin, Sean Swain APPROVED BY: ______________________________ William L. Portier, Ph.D. Faculty Advisor ______________________________ Sandra A. Yocum, Ph.D. Committee Member ______________________________ Dennis M. Doyle, Ph.D. Committee Member ii ABSTRACT “READING CUSTOM AS ILLATIVE SENSE” A THEOLOGICAL ACCOUNT OF JOHN HENRY NEWMAN’S APPROPRIATION OF A REALIST INTERPRETATION OF DAVID HUME Name: Martin, Sean Swain University of Dayton Advisor: Dr. William Portier This thesis explores the notion that John Henry Newman offered an epistemological system that in some way mirrors the image of the non-skeptical, realist reading of Hume that we have only seen become popular over the last few decades and that understanding this commonality to Newman’s system is extremely helpful in making sense of the complicated notion he names the illative sense and the function it is to play in the practice of the Christian faith. I first formulate the historically accepted skeptical epistemology associated with Hume, with specific attention given to his discussion of the problems surrounding the idea of causation. I contrast this traditionally rendered Hume with the model provided by his contemporary, Thomas Reid, which includes explicit interaction with this understanding of Hume’s philosophy.