Quantum Theory, the Chinese Room Argument and the Symbol Grounding Problem Abstract

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Quantum Theory, the Chinese Room Argument and the Symbol Grounding Problem Abstract Quantum Theory, the Chinese Room Argument and the * Symbol Grounding Problem Ravi Gomatam † [email protected] Abstract: I o ffer an alternative to Searle’s original Chinese Room argument which I call the Sanskrit Room argument (SRA). SRA distinguishes between syntactic TOKEN and semantic SYMBOL manipulations and shows that both are involved in human language understanding. Within classical mechanics, which gives an adequate scientific account of TOKEN manipulation, a symbol remains a subjective construct. I describe how an objective, quantitative theory of semantic symbols could be developed by applying the Schrodinger equation directly to macroscopic objects independent of Born’s rule and hence independent of current statistical quantum mechanics. Such a macroscopic quantum mechanics opens the possibility for developing a new theory of computing wherein the Universal Turing Machine (UTM) performs semantic symbol manipulation and models macroscopic quantum computing. 1. Introduction This paper seeks to relate quantum mechanics to artificial intelligence, human language, and cognition. It is a position paper, reporting some relevant details of a long-term research program currently in progress. In his justly famous Chinese Room Argument (CRA), Searle argued that “we could not give the capacity to understand Chinese or English [that humans evidently have] to a machine where the operation of the machine is solely defined as the instantiation of a computer program.” ([1], p. 422) Searle avoided the need to positively define ‘human understanding’ by relying on an operator (such as himself) who does not understand Chinese in any sense. Skipping the details of this well-known paper, Searle’s main conclusions were as follows: 1. At present, digital computers only perform symbol manipulation. 2. The CRA shows that symbol manipulation alone will never lead the operator to understand *Originally published in Bruza, P. et al. (Eds.), Quantum Interaction 2009, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Volume 5494, pp. 174-183, Springer-Verlag: Berlin, Heidelberg †Institute of Semantic Information Sciences and Technology, 2334 Stuart St, Berkeley, CA 94705; Juhu Road, Juhu, Mumbai 400 049 (www.isist.info) 1 Chinese; thus an equivalent digital computer cannot be said to understand Chinese. 3. Hence, the thesis of Strong AI is false. An appropriately programmed digital computer may be able to simulate human thinking and intelligence, but it cannot be said to literally possess cognitive states. Searle identifies the Chinese language letters only in terms of their shape, and refers to them as symbols. But the term “symbol” implies something more. Henceforth I shall distinguish between syntactic TOKENS (letters qua shapes) and semantic SYMBOLS (letters qua components of a language, generating meaning).‡ Under this terminology, Searle’s argument is that computers, by virtue of performing token manipulation alone, cannot demonstrate understanding of Chinese. I wish to show that the CRA does not preclude in any way a more general form of the strong-AI thesis, namely that present digital computers can be said to possess some portion of the abilities constituting human ‘understanding’. To this end, without much ado, I o ffer an alternative to the CRA, which I shall call the “Sanskrit Room argument”. 2. The Sanskrit Room Argument (SRA) The Sanskrit Room is similar to the Chinese Room in all respects but two. The language spoken is Sanskrit§, and the person inside (say, myself) understands Sanskrit. There are now two possibilities: Scenario 1: I ignore my ability to understand the questions, merely decomposing the queries into a sequence of shapes. I then string together replies from baskets containing a good supply of these same shapes, following a hypothetical program. As with the CRA, let us say that I pass the Turing test in this mode without di fficulty. Scenario 2: I discard the program, and use my Sanskrit skills to construct an appropriate response from the store of language symbols . In this case I should also pass the Turing test. To an outsider, my behavior is the same in both cases. However, I hold it as self-evident that I am doing something fundamentally di fferent in each scenario. In the first, I am mimicking Searle’s operator in the Chinese room (who doesn’t know the language) and am doing solely token manipulation. In the second, I understand the input and answer on my own (without reference to the program). I am therefore manipulating semantic symbols. But I am also doing token manipulation at the level of physically stringing together letters. Thus, unlike the CRA, the SRA gives some insight into the nature of human language processing. It involves both token and symbol manipulation at the level of the subject. ‡ TOKENS are also referred to in the literature as physical symbols. § Although for the purposes of this paper I could simply replace Searle by a native Chinese speaker, I shift to Sanskrit for a reason. It is a well-discussed topic in the field of natural language processing (NLP) that Panini’s grammar can generate semantically valid sentences in Sanskrit to an extent that has so far been impossible for other natural languages [2]. I expect the idea that the individual letters in Sanskrit carry semantic content, in a manner possibly unique to that language, to become relevant to the issue at hand in future publications. 2 I now turn to a key question: Are there any di fferences between token and symbol manipulation at the objective level? 3. TOKENS and Classical Physics I shall assume metaphysical realism to start with, and refer to the external identity of objects I manipulate as the Kantian things-in-themselves (or THINGS ). From this viewpoint, the terms token and symbol both refer to our subjective conceptions of the THING . In standard philosophical parlance, tokens and symbols are phenomenal objects given in our experience. We objectify phenomenal tokens as res extensa in everyday thinking and in physics. That is, we endow them with an absolute location, mass and derived extensional attributes such as velocity, acceleration, etc. We believe that there is an object out there with features that correspond in every detail to our conception of the phenomenal token. We might call this belief the classical version of direct realism. Classical direct realism is referred to as naive realism in everyday thinking, and as correspondence realism in physics. ** Let us refer to the phenomenal token objectified in classical realism as a TOKEN . It is a physical object defined entirely in terms of its primary physical properties. On this basis, we could say that I am manipulating objective TOKENS in Scenario-1. Classical physics su ffices to explain how I can recognize and manipulate objects qua TOKENS . The operation of the digital computers is presently understood in similar classical terms, rendering the computer a token manipulating system. From this perspective, any symbol manipulation (and thus ‘understanding’) attributed to the computer (or, to the human operator in Scenario-1 of SRA) becomes our interpretation of operations that objectively must be considered solely syntactic. However, this is more a limitation of our classical point of view than an intrinsic limitation of the computer (or the human operator). We must find a way to overcome this limitation, since classical physics itself has been superseded by quantum theory. This paper will propose that present-day computers can be understood as objectively performing, not just TOKEN manipulation but also SYMBOL manipulation, provided we apply the Schrodinger equation to macroscopic objects in a new manner. †† To develop this proposal further, we need to move toward a direct realist view of phenomenal symbols in everyday thinking and physics, one which is complementary to our direct realist view of the phenomenal tokens. That is to say, just as classical physics and its associated ordinary language-based thinking link our sense experiences to objective TOKENS , phenomenal symbols can be given objective counterparts in a new physics and its associated range of everyday thinking. I call these objective counterparts SYMBOLS . I will now argue that the quantum formalism, if properly applied to the macroscopic world, can serve as the basis for a scientific theory of SYMBOLS in physics. ** It is now recognized that a logical defense of scientific realism is highly problematic, even with regard to pre-quantum theories. (See reference [3] for an easy introduction to the topic.) The underdetermination of theory by data and pessimistic meta-induction are but two reasons. Nevertheless, physicists maintain a realist view of their theories based on pragmatic success. Likewise, it has been impossible to logically justify naive version of direct realism in everyday thinking too. Yet this viewpoint is embraced by all of us uncritically, again on pragmatic grounds. Physicists too rely on naive realism, at the level of reporting their laboratory observations using ordinary language. †† While it is true that present SQM has nothing to o ffer to neuroscience (see [4]), the move being outlined here would be of significance to neuroscience, and for our scientific understanding of symbol manipulation at the human level. 3 4. SYMBOLS and Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics Quantum theory arose out of the failure of classical physics to give an account of certain phenomena (blackbody radiation, the photoelectric e ffect, and atomic spectra). In statistical quantum mechanics, atomic objects acquire context sensitive properties reminiscent of symbols. This feature suggests that quantum mechanics, if it can be directly applied to the macroscopic world, could provide a basis for physically treating phenomenal symbols on a non-classical footing, i.e. as physical objects other than TOKENS . Indeed, Schrodinger’s equation in principle applies to the world of tables and chairs and measuring devices just as much as it applies to the world of atomic particles. The modern practice of statistical quantum mechanics (SQM), however, presupposes the classicality of the everyday world in general, and our measurement devices in particular.
Recommended publications
  • Artificial Intelligence Is Stupid and Causal Reasoning Won't Fix It
    Artificial Intelligence is stupid and causal reasoning wont fix it J. Mark Bishop1 1 TCIDA, Goldsmiths, University of London, London, UK Email: [email protected] Abstract Artificial Neural Networks have reached `Grandmaster' and even `super- human' performance' across a variety of games, from those involving perfect- information, such as Go [Silver et al., 2016]; to those involving imperfect- information, such as `Starcraft' [Vinyals et al., 2019]. Such technological developments from AI-labs have ushered concomitant applications across the world of business, where an `AI' brand-tag is fast becoming ubiquitous. A corollary of such widespread commercial deployment is that when AI gets things wrong - an autonomous vehicle crashes; a chatbot exhibits `racist' behaviour; automated credit-scoring processes `discriminate' on gender etc. - there are often significant financial, legal and brand consequences, and the incident becomes major news. As Judea Pearl sees it, the underlying reason for such mistakes is that \... all the impressive achievements of deep learning amount to just curve fitting". The key, Pearl suggests [Pearl and Mackenzie, 2018], is to replace `reasoning by association' with `causal reasoning' - the ability to infer causes from observed phenomena. It is a point that was echoed by Gary Marcus and Ernest Davis in a recent piece for the New York Times: \we need to stop building computer systems that merely get better and better at detecting statistical patterns in data sets { often using an approach known as \Deep Learning" { and start building computer systems that from the moment of arXiv:2008.07371v1 [cs.CY] 20 Jul 2020 their assembly innately grasp three basic concepts: time, space and causal- ity"[Marcus and Davis, 2019].
    [Show full text]
  • The Thought Experiments Are Rigged: Mechanistic Understanding Inhibits Mentalistic Understanding
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy Summer 8-13-2013 The Thought Experiments are Rigged: Mechanistic Understanding Inhibits Mentalistic Understanding Toni S. Adleberg Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Adleberg, Toni S., "The Thought Experiments are Rigged: Mechanistic Understanding Inhibits Mentalistic Understanding." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2013. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/141 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS ARE RIGGED: MECHANISTIC UNDERSTANDING INHIBITS MENTALISTIC UNDERSTANDING by TONI ADLEBERG Under the Direction of Eddy Nahmias ABSTRACT Many well-known arguments in the philosophy of mind use thought experiments to elicit intuitions about consciousness. Often, these thought experiments include mechanistic explana- tions of a systems’ behavior. I argue that when we understand a system as a mechanism, we are not likely to understand it as an agent. According to Arico, Fiala, Goldberg, and Nichols’ (2011) AGENCY Model, understanding a system as an agent is necessary for generating the intuition that it is conscious. Thus, if we are presented with a mechanistic description of a system, we will be very unlikely to understand that system as conscious. Many of the thought experiments in the philosophy of mind describe systems mechanistically. I argue that my account of consciousness attributions is preferable to the “Simplicity Intuition” account proposed by David Barnett (2008) because it is more explanatory and more consistent with our intuitions.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy Fall 2019—Test 3 1. According to Descartes, … A. What I Really Am Is a Body, but I Also Possess
    Introduction to Philosophy Fall 2019—Test 3 1. According to Descartes, … a. what I really am is a body, but I also possess a mind. b. minds and bodies can’t causally interact with one another, but God fools us into believing they do. c. cats and dogs have immortal souls, just like us. d. conscious states always have physical causes, but never have physical effects. e. what I really am is a mind, but I also possess a body. 2. Which of the following would Descartes agree with? a. We can conceive of existing without a body. b. We can conceive of existing without a mind. c. We can conceive of existing without either a mind or a body. d. We can’t conceive of mental substance. e. We can’t conceive of material substance. 3. Substance dualism is the view that … a. there are two kinds of minds. b. there are two kinds of “basic stuff” in the world. c. there are two kinds of physical particles. d. there are two kinds of people in the world—those who divide the world into two kinds of people, and those that don’t. e. material substance comes in two forms, matter and energy. 4. We call a property “accidental” (as opposed to “essential”) when ... a. it is the result of a car crash. b. it follows from a thing’s very nature. c. it is a property a thing can’t lose (without ceasing to exist). d. it is a property a thing can lose (without ceasing to exist).
    [Show full text]
  • Preston, John, & Bishop, Mark
    Preston, John, & Bishop, Mark (2002), Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence (Oxford: Oxford University Press), xvi + 410 pp., ISBN 0-19-825057-6. Reviewed by: William J. Rapaport Department of Computer Science and Engineering, Department of Philosophy, and Center for Cognitive Science, State University of New York at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260-2000; [email protected], http://www.cse.buffalo.edu/ rapaport ∼ This anthology’s 20 new articles and bibliography attest to continued interest in Searle’s (1980) Chinese Room Argument. Preston’s excellent “Introduction” ties the history and nature of cognitive science, computation, AI, and the CRA to relevant chapters. Searle (“Twenty-One Years in the Chinese Room”) says, “purely . syntactical processes of the implemented computer program could not by themselves . guarantee . semantic content . essential to human cognition” (51). “Semantic content” appears to be mind-external entities “attached” (53) to the program’s symbols. But the program’s implementation must accept these entities as input (suitably transduced), so the program in execution, accepting and processing this input, would provide the required content. The transduced input would then be internal representatives of the external content and would be related to the symbols of the formal, syntactic program in ways that play the same roles as the “attachment” relationships between the external contents and the symbols (Rapaport 2000). The “semantic content” could then just be those mind-internal
    [Show full text]
  • Digital Culture: Pragmatic and Philosophical Challenges
    DIOGENES Diogenes 211: 23–39 ISSN 0392-1921 Digital Culture: Pragmatic and Philosophical Challenges Marcelo Dascal Over the coming decades, the so-called telematic technologies are destined to grow more and more encompassing in scale and the repercussions they will have on our professional and personal lives will become ever more accentuated. The transforma- tions resulting from the digitization of data have already profoundly modified a great many of the activities of human life and exercise significant influence on the way we design, draw up, store and send documents, as well as on the means used for locating information in libraries, databases and on the net. These changes are transforming the nature of international communication and are modifying the way in which we carry out research, engage in study, keep our accounts, plan our travel, do our shopping, look after our health, organize our leisure time, undertake wars and so on. The time is not far off when miniaturized digital systems will be installed everywhere – in our homes and offices, in the car, in our pockets or even embedded within the bodies of each one of us. They will help us to keep control over every aspect of our lives and will efficiently and effectively carry out multiple tasks which today we have to devote precious time to. As a consequence, our ways of acting and thinking will be transformed. These new winds of change, which are blowing strongly, are giving birth to a new culture to which the name ‘digital culture’ has been given.1 It is timely that a study should be made of the different aspects and consequences of this culture, but that this study should not be just undertaken from the point of view of the simple user who quickly embraces the latest successful inno- vation, in reaction essentially to market forces.
    [Show full text]
  • Zombie Mouse in a Chinese Room
    Philosophy and Technology manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Zombie mouse in a Chinese room Slawomir J. Nasuto · J. Mark Bishop · Etienne B. Roesch · Matthew C. Spencer the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Abstract John Searle's Chinese Room Argument (CRA) purports to demon- strate that syntax is not sucient for semantics, and hence that because com- putation cannot yield understanding, the computational theory of mind, which equates the mind to an information processing system based on formal com- putations, fails. In this paper, we use the CRA, and the debate that emerged from it, to develop a philosophical critique of recent advances in robotics and neuroscience. We describe results from a body of work that contributes to blurring the divide between biological and articial systems: so-called ani- mats, autonomous robots that are controlled by biological neural tissue, and what may be described as remote-controlled rodents, living animals endowed with augmented abilities provided by external controllers. We argue that, even though at rst sight these chimeric systems may seem to escape the CRA, on closer analysis they do not. We conclude by discussing the role of the body- brain dynamics in the processes that give rise to genuine understanding of the world, in line with recent proposals from enactive cognitive science1. Slawomir J. Nasuto Univ. Reading, Reading, UK, E-mail: [email protected] J. Mark Bishop Goldsmiths, Univ. London, UK, E-mail: [email protected] Etienne B. Roesch Univ. Reading, Reading, UK, E-mail: [email protected] Matthew C.
    [Show full text]
  • Invitation to Quantum Mechanics
    i Invitation to Quantum Mechanics Daniel F. Styer ii Invitation to Quantum Mechanics Daniel F. Styer Schiffer Professor of Physics, Oberlin College copyright c 31 May 2021 Daniel F. Styer The copyright holder grants the freedom to copy, modify, convey, adapt, and/or redistribute this work under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Share Alike 4.0 International License. A copy of that license is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/legalcode. You may freely download this book in pdf format from http://www.oberlin.edu/physics/dstyer/InvitationToQM: It is formatted to print nicely on either A4 or U.S. Letter paper. You may also purchase a printed and bound copy from World Scientific Publishing Company. In neither case does the author receive monetary gain from your download/purchase: it is reward enough for him that you want to explore quantum mechanics. Love all God's creation, the whole and every grain of sand in it. Love the stars, the trees, the thunderstorms, the atoms. The more you love, the more you will grow curious. The more you grow curious, the more you will question. The more you question, the more you will uncover. The more you uncover, the more you will love. And so at last you will come to love the entire universe with an agile and resilient love founded upon facts and understanding. | This improvisation by Dan Styer was inspired by the first sentence, which appears in Fyodor Dostoyevsky's The Brothers Karamazov. iii iv Dedicated to Linda Ong Styer, adventurer Contents Synoptic Contents 1 Welcome 3 1.
    [Show full text]
  • A Selected Bibliography of Publications By, and About, Niels Bohr
    A Selected Bibliography of Publications by, and about, Niels Bohr Nelson H. F. Beebe University of Utah Department of Mathematics, 110 LCB 155 S 1400 E RM 233 Salt Lake City, UT 84112-0090 USA Tel: +1 801 581 5254 FAX: +1 801 581 4148 E-mail: [email protected], [email protected], [email protected] (Internet) WWW URL: http://www.math.utah.edu/~beebe/ 09 June 2021 Version 1.308 Title word cross-reference + [VIR+08]. $1 [Duf46]. $1.00 [N.38, Bal39]. $105.95 [Dor79]. $11.95 [Bus20]. $12.00 [Kra07, Lan08]. $189 [Tan09]. $21.95 [Hub14]. $24.95 [RS07]. $29.95 [Gor17]. $32.00 [RS07]. $35.00 [Par06]. $47.50 [Kri91]. $6.95 [Sha67]. $61 [Kra16b]. $9 [Jam67]. − [VIR+08]. 238 [Tur46a, Tur46b]. ◦ [Fra55]. 2 [Som18]. β [Gau14]. c [Dar92d, Gam39]. G [Gam39]. h [Gam39]. q [Dar92d]. × [wB90]. -numbers [Dar92d]. /Hasse [KZN+88]. /Rath [GRE+01]. 0 [wB90, Hub14, Tur06]. 0-19-852049-2 [Ano93a, Red93, Seg93]. 0-19-853977-0 [Hub14]. 0-521-35366-1 [Kri91]. 0-674-01519-3 [Tur06]. 0-85224-458-4 [Hen86a]. 0-9672617-2-4 [Kra07, Lan08]. 1 2 1.5 [GRE+01]. 100-˚aret [BR+85]. 100th [BR+85, KRW05, Sch13, vM02]. 110th [Rub97a]. 121 [Boh87a]. 153 [MP97]. 16 [SE13]. 17 [Boh55a, KRBR62]. 175 [Bad83]. 18.11.1962 [Hei63a]. 1911 [Meh75]. 1915 [SE13]. 1915/16 [SE13, SE13]. 1918 [Boh21a]. 1920s [PP16]. 1922 [Boh22a]. 1923 [Ros18]. 1925 [Cla13, Bor13, Jan17, Sho13]. 1927 [Ano28]. 1929 [HEB+80, HvMW79, Pye81]. 1930 [Lin81, Whe81]. 1930/41 [Fer68, Fer71]. 1930s [Aas85b, Stu79]. 1933 [CCJ+34].
    [Show full text]
  • A Logical Hole in the Chinese Room
    Minds & Machines (2009) 19:229–235 DOI 10.1007/s11023-009-9151-9 A Logical Hole in the Chinese Room Michael John Shaffer Received: 27 August 2007 / Accepted: 18 May 2009 / Published online: 12 June 2009 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009 Abstract Searle’s Chinese Room Argument (CRA) has been the object of great interest in the philosophy of mind, artificial intelligence and cognitive science since its initial presentation in ‘Minds, Brains and Programs’ in 1980. It is by no means an overstatement to assert that it has been a main focus of attention for philosophers and computer scientists of many stripes. It is then especially interesting to note that relatively little has been said about the detailed logic of the argument, whatever significance Searle intended CRA to have. The problem with the CRA is that it involves a very strong modal claim, the truth of which is both unproved and highly questionable. So it will be argued here that the CRA does not prove what it was intended to prove. Keywords Chinese room Á Computation Á Mind Á Artificial intelligence Searle’s Chinese Room Argument (CRA) has been the object of great interest in the philosophy of mind, artificial intelligence and cognitive science since its initial presentation in ‘Minds, Brains and Programs’ in 1980. It is by no means an overstatement to assert that it has been a main focus of attention for philosophers and computer scientists of many stripes. In fact, one recent book (Preston and Bishop 2002) is exclusively dedicated to the ongoing debate about that argument 20 some years since its introduction.
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. Ravi V. Gomatam Prof. Ravi V. Gomatam
    Prof. Ravi V. Gomatam Curriculum Vitae Director , Institute of Semantic Information Sciences & Technology, Berkeley Mumbai Adjunct Professor , Birla Institute of Technology and Science, Pilani, India Contact Info Email: [email protected] India: Juhu Road, Juhu, Mumbai, Maharashtra 400 049, India +91-22-2620-2332 (board line), +91-99-6797-5499 (cell) USA: PO Box 3206, Berkeley, CA 94703, USA +1-510-841-7618 (main), +1-510-868-4957 (direct) Wikipedia entry http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gomatam_Ravi Education • (1998) Ph.D. in Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Mumbai University, India • (1974) M.E. in Electronics Engineering, BITS, Pilani, India • (1972) B.E. in Electrical and Electronics Engineering, Annamalai University, India Fields of Research Interest Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics; Semantic Information; Semantic web; Semantic Computing; Macroscopic Quantum Computing; Foundations of Chemistry; Complex Analysis; Exotic Manifolds; Complexity and Information; Entropy and Information; Quantum Signal Processing; Biology and Information. Career Summary Professor Ravi Gomatam is an NRI research scientist, who has lived over three decades in the USA, working in both industry and later in full-time research & academic positions. After obtaining his Masters degree in electronics engineering from India, he moved to the USA in the early 1970s, ran his own consultancy firm in the areas of operating system design, data communications and very-large 1 database design, and carried out projects for many fortune-500 companies including General Motors, Ford, Chrysler, Burroughs and IBM. In the mid 1980s, he turned to academics, obtaining his Ph.D. in the foundations of quantum mechanics, which remains his area of active research. He now does full-time research and graduate level teaching.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Foundations Is Weak AI Possible?
    Philosophical Foundations • Weak AI – claim: computers can be programmed to act as if they were intelligent (as if they were thinking) • Strong AI – claim: computers can be programmed to think (i.e., they really are thinking) • Most AI researchers assume Weak AI is true and Strong AI is irrelevant (c) 2003 Thomas G. Dietterich 1 Is Weak AI possible? • Traditionally posed as the question “Can Machines Think?” – problem: This depends on customary use of the word “think” – compare: • Can machines fly? • Can machines swim? (c) 2003 Thomas G. Dietterich 2 1 Flying and Swimming • In English, machines can fly but they do not swim • In Russian, machines can do both (c) 2003 Thomas G. Dietterich 3 Arguments against Weak AI • Turing’s famous paper “Computing Machinery and Intelligence” (1950) – Argument from disability – Argument from mathematics – Argument from informality (c) 2003 Thomas G. Dietterich 4 2 Argument from Disability • A machine will never be able to… – be kind, resourceful, beautiful, friendly, have initiative, have a sense of humor, tell right from wrong, make mistakes, fall in love, enjoy strawberries and cream, make someone fall in love with it, learn from experience, use words properly, be the subject of its own thought, have as much diversity of behavior as man, do something really new. • But nowadays, computers do many things that used to be exclusively human: – play chess, checkers, and other games, inspect parts on assembly lines, check the spelling of documents, steer cars and helicopters, diagnose diseases, and 100’s of other things. Computers have made small but significant discoveries in astronomy, mathematics, chemistry, minerology, biology, computer science, and other fields (c) 2003 Thomas G.
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. Ravi Gomatam Curriculum Vitae
    Prof. Ravi Gomatam Curriculum Vitae Education (1998) Ph.D. in Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Mumbai University (1974) M.E. in Electronics Engineering, BITS, Pilani, India (1972) B.E. in Electronics Engineering, Annamalai University, India Positions Held Director, Institute of Semantic Information Sciences and Technology (www.insist.ac.in), 2008-current Visiting Professor, Indian Council of Philosophical Research (ICPR), New Delhi, 2016-2017 Director, Bhaktivedanta Institute, Berkeley & Mumbai (www.bvinst.edu), 1997-current Adjunct Professor, Birla Institute of Technology and Sciences (BITS), Pilani, India, 1997-2007 Professor and Ph.D. Guide, University of Mumbai, 2015-Present Career Arc After Masters, moved to USA, worked with many fortune- 500 companies in Detroit, in the areas of operating system design, data communications and very large data base design. Returned to academics, obtained Ph.D. in Philosophy, foundations of quantum mechanics, from University of Mumbai. Over two decades of experience in research, post-graduate level teaching, and guiding M.S./Ph.D. dissertations. Pioneering work in three different fields of science Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics Semantic Information Sciences and Technology (SIST) Consciousness Studies Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics (MQM) Developing a quantum theory of the macroscopic regime logically independent of current microscopic quantum mechanics (mQM). A Nobel Laureate in quantum physics has remarked regarding his approach: "We can get out of the confusions in QM with this approach. Perhaps, this is how we should be doing science." His work in Macroscopic Quantum Mechanics (MQM) has already been cited in wide ranging fields from control engineering, neuroscience, ecology and marketing theory. Two of his papers have been part of curriculum at Masters level in courses at Brown University and University of Connecticut.
    [Show full text]