Non-Commercial Use Only

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Non-Commercial Use Only Biomedical Science and Engineering 2019; volume 3(s2):95 For an ethics of experimenta- issues about animal use in research involves tion. Moral arguments support- that: i) the debate developed since modern Correspondence:Franco Manti, Department of age to these days about ontological status of Education Sciences, University of Genoa, ing 3Rs animals and what is required or we have to Genoa, Italy. recognize to them; ii) new knowledge E-mail: [email protected] Franco Manti issues initiated from ethology, antrozoolo- gy, animal psicology; iii) evidences sup- Key words: 3Rs; moral questions; animal; Department of Education Sciences, experimentation; ethics. porting or in contrast with animal use in University of Genoa, Genoa, Italy experimentation, with reference to new Conference presentation: this paper was pre- points of view initiated from alternative sented at the Second Centro 3R Annual methods. Meeting - 3Rs in Italian Universities, 2019, Reference to 3Rs is an important start- June 20-21, University of Genoa, Italy. Abstract ing point for critical consideration of the A non-ideological approach to the impasse caused from the contrast between Received for publication: 28 October 2019. moral questions posed by the use of animals human and animal “wellbeing” (that is dif- Accepted for publication: 6 November 2019. for experimental purposes involves taking ficult to define) or humans’ benefits – ani- mal costs. This work is licensed under a Creative into account: i) the debate that has devel- Commons Attribution NonCommercial 4.0 We need to critically analyze (pseudo) oped since the modern age on the ontologi- License (CC BY-NC 4.0). cal status of animals and on what is due to utilitarian approach upon which cost-bene- them or we must recognize; ii) the new fit analysis rests. ©Copyright: the Author(s), 2019 frontiers of knowledge opened up by disci- A correct cost-benefit analysis requires: Licensee PAGEPress, Italy plines such as ethology, anthrozoology, ani- i) same consideration for all stakeholder Biomedical Science and Engineering 2019; 3(s2):95 mal psychology; iii) the arguments in sup- interests; ii) measurable and predictive con- doi:10.4081/bse.2019.95 port of or against experimentation with ani- sequences; iii) agent neutral position; iv) mals, referring also to new perspectives results not influenced by morally irrelevant only parameters. opened up by methodologies commonly Results defined as alternatives. All these conditions are usually not con- Referring to the 3Rs, an important start- sidered in the project evaluation. The result is that the management of ing point is to critically consider the J. Harsanyi introduced the notionuse of animal suffering in experimentation and impasse generated by the conflict of inter- “imaginative empathy” to enable an inter- cost-benefit analysis (in the case of use) ests between human and animal welfare or, personal comparison of utilities and explain must be reconsidered. We should replace in another respect, by the conflict of bene- how we can imagine to be in the shoes of the word “cost” with “harm”. fits for humans - costs for animals. another person, simulating another’s desires In view of this, I support an effective, Effective development of the 3Rs requires and discover his preferred course of action. aware, increasingly widespread use of 3R epistemological awareness and ethical com- If we assume the “similarity postulate”, a through the implementation and the devel- petence as the assumption of responsibility priori we can look at human reactions and opment of an ethics competence of by researchers and OPBA members for the basic feelings as similar, considering differ- researchers and animal-welfare bodies well-being of humans and animals, giving ence factors. How far is possible to extend members. Ethics competence is the ability reasons for the choices that are made. this postulate to animals? to make moral judgments, justifying the Researchers, ethics committees, ani- choices, and the extension of ethics of care mal-welfare bodies, do not look at the issue to interspecific relations. of developing a related interspecific social Environment is very important in biog- Introduction utility (assuming it was possible). raphy of animal used in experimentation, If we support the method of calculation, just like “sentience” and opportunity of D.L. no. 26/2014, art.1, proclaims that is cost-benefit analysis the most appropriate realize their cognitive abilities in the con- the use of animals for scientificNon-commercial or educa- to answer to the question: “animal experi- text they are living in. tional purposes should only be considered mentation can considerably reduce human That means issues of animal use in where a scientifically valid, non-animal risk?”. experimentation need to be studied and con- alternative is unavailable to achieve the As to animal welfare we can consider sidered as processes in a complex system. result. This is a principle assertion, very the issue from two perspectives. The first is In this complex system, animal-human oth- demanding and difficult to apply. The defi- that instrumentally animal welfare is func- erness is, ethically, and requires a specific nition of “desired result” raises specific tional to the experiment’s correct outcome; and aware accountability: researchers and epistemological and ethical problems in the second is that humans are responsible of animal-welfare bodies members have a experimentation, for example the use and animal welfare, whether in captivity or in moral duty to take care of animal welfare. function of ad hoc assumptions, as well as cohabitation with them. Anywhere, this Moral responsibility ensures possible the methods and modality of experimenta- issue involves: i) centrality of animals’ cog- well-being of animals used in experimenta- tion. History teaches that scientifically nitive dimension; ii) the transition, both for tion, so we have to deal with underestima- valid, reasonable and desirable methods are humans and animals, from a quantitative tions in customary practices. In particular, not neutral at all, but strictly connected to (material resources based) to a qualitative we have to consider: i) the environmental philosophic, metaphysic, scientific views. approach to welfare; iii) consider wellbeing conditions in which animals are kept or Galileo’s theories, in fact, were not scientif- as opportunity of realize the capabilities in used influence animal’s stress and quality of ically valid or reasonable for his time, and specific contexts, and develop physical and life; ii) these conditions are usually not con- raised ethical and theological issues. cognitive abilities, both species specific or sidered as researcher’s responsibility; iii) A non-ideological approach to moral biographically gained. assessment of psycological stress must be [Biomedical Science and Engineering 2019; 3(s2):95] [page 28] Article associated to no invasive procedures too, D.L. no. 26/2014, art.1 requires, ethical- effective ethics competence that they can- because animals don’t get easily used to ly, that researchers and therefore animal- not delegate to experts. Everyone is respon- routine procedures; iv) ethics committee welfare bodies members must assume the sible to himself, to others (animals too) for and animal-welfare bodies members, often burden of proof about the need for use of his choices. Everyone must evaluate critical underestimate the harm and distress caused animals for scientific purposes, considering issues of his choices and rationally justify to animals by daily routine procedures; v) rigorously all the available alternatives. them. the animals’ capacity to experience pleasure For this to happen there is a need for a is underestimated. strong epistemological awareness and an only use Non-commercial [page 29] [Biomedical Science and Engineering 2019; 3(s2):95].
Recommended publications
  • Mental States in Animals: Cognitive Ethology Jacques Vauclair
    Mental states in animals: cognitive ethology Jacques Vauclair This artHe addresses the quegtion of mentaJ states in animak as viewed in ‘cognitive ethology”. In effect, thk field of research aims at studying naturally occurring behaviours such as food caching, individual recognition, imitation, tool use and communication in wild animals, in order to seek for evidence of mental experiences, self-aw&&reness and intentional@. Cognitive ethologists use some philosophical cencepts (e.g., the ‘intentional stance’) to carry out their programme of the investigation of natural behaviours. A comparison between cognitive ethology and other approaches to the investigation of cognitive processes in animals (e.g., experimental animal psychology) helps to point out the strengths and weaknesses of cognitive ethology. Moreover, laboratory attempts to analyse experimentally Mentional behaviours such as deception, the relationship between seeing and knowing, as well as the ability of animals to monitor their own states of knowing, suggest that cognitive ethology could benefit significantly from the conceptual frameworks and methods of animal cognitive psychology. Both disciplines could, in fact, co&ribute to the understanding of which cognitive abilities are evolutionary adaptations. T he term ‘cognirive ethology’ (CE) was comed by that it advances a purposive or Intentional interpretation Griffin in The Question ofAnimd Au~aarmess’ and later de- for activities which are a mixture of some fixed genetically veloped in other publications’ ‘_ Although Griffin‘s IS’6 transmitred elements with more hexible behaviour?. book was first a strong (and certainly salutary) reacrion (Cognitive ethologists USC conceptual frameworks against the inhibitions imposed by strict behaviourism in provided by philosophers (such as rhe ‘intentional stance’)“.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Ethology: Theory Or Poetry?
    Cognitive ethology: Theory or poetry? Jonathan Bennett from Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1983), pp. 356–358. Comments on Daniel Dennett, ‘Intentional Systems in Cognitive Ethology: the “Panglossian Paradigm” defended’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1983), pp. 343–345. Dennett is perhaps the most interesting, fertile, and chal- I take it as uncontroversial that the intentional stance— lenging philosopher of mind on the contemporary scene, and considered as a program for theorizing about behavior—must I count myself among his grateful admirers. But this present be centered on the idea that beliefs are functions from desires paper of his, enjoyable as it is to read, and acceptable as to behavior, and that desires are functions from beliefs to its conclusions are, is likely to do more harm than good. behavior. Down in the foundations, then, we need some Some will object that the intentional stance is a dead end; theory about what behavior must be like to be reasonably but I think, as Dennett does, that it is premature to turn interpreted as manifesting beliefs and desires; and these our backs on explanations of animal behavior in terms of concepts must presumably tail off somehow, being strongly desires and beliefs, and I am in favor of continuing with applicable to men and apes, less strongly to monkeys, and this endeavor; but only if it gets some structure, only if it so on down to animals that do not have beliefs and desires is guided by some firm underlying theory. That is what but can be described in terms of weaker analogues of those the ethologists might get from philosophy, but Dennett has notions.
    [Show full text]
  • Anthrozoology and Sharks, Looking at How Human-Shark Interactions Have Shaped Human Life Over Time
    Anthrozoology and Public Perception: Humans and Great White Sharks (Carchardon carcharias) on Cape Cod, Massachusetts, USA Jessica O’Toole A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Marine Affairs University of Washington 2020 Committee: Marc L. Miller, Chair Vincent F. Gallucci Program Authorized to Offer Degree School of Marine and Environmental Affairs © Copywrite 2020 Jessica O’Toole 2 University of Washington Abstract Anthrozoology and Public Perception: Humans and Great White Sharks (Carchardon carcharias) on Cape Cod, Massachusetts, USA Jessica O’Toole Chair of the Supervisory Committee: Dr. Marc L. Miller School of Marine and Environmental Affairs Anthrozoology is a relatively new field of study in the world of academia. This discipline, which includes researchers ranging from social studies to natural sciences, examines human-animal interactions. Understanding what affect these interactions have on a person’s perception of a species could be used to create better conservation strategies and policies. This thesis uses a mixed qualitative methodology to examine the public perception of great white sharks on Cape Cod, Massachusetts. While the area has a history of shark interactions, a shark related death in 2018 forced many people to re-evaluate how they view sharks. Not only did people express both positive and negative perceptions of the animals but they also discussed how the attack caused them to change their behavior in and around the ocean. Residents also acknowledged that the sharks were not the only problem living in the ocean. They often blame seals for the shark attacks, while also claiming they are a threat to the fishing industry.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind and Deception
    PS452 Intelligent Behaviour Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind and Deception Maxwell J Roberts Department of Psychology University of Essex www.tubemapcentral.com version date: 19/11/2019 Part 3: Intelligent Behaviour in Animals • Lecture 7: Animal Intelligence Tests Measuring animal cognitive capacity • Learning and logic between species • The ubiquitous g factor • Lecture 8: Tools, Puzzles, Beliefs, and Intentions Complex interactions with objects • Natural tool use • Understanding the properties of objects 2 Part 3: Intelligent Behaviour in Animals • Lecture 9: Animal Communication Mindless signals or deliberate acts • Natural communication • Taught language in the laboratory • Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind and Deception In search of proto-modules • Animal (lack of) awareness of other minds • Social versus non-social origins of general intelligence 3 Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind & Deception • 10.1 Theory of Mind: A Tool for Deception • Theory of Mind and modularity • Evidence for Theory of Mind in animals • 10.2 The Special Case of Deception • Deception in the wild • Primate deception in the wild • Deception in the laboratory • Return of the crows • 10.3 Evaluation: Theory of Mind & Deception 4 Lecture 10: Animal Theory of Mind & Deception • 10.4 The Origins of General Intelligence? • 10.5 Animal, Human, and Machine Intelligence 5 10.1 Theory of Mind: A Tool for Deception • Theory of Mind: A popular concept in child psychology • The assumption that other beings are intentional systems and have mental states, including: Knowledge
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Introduction
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. 1 Introduction Whether signals are reliable or deceptive has been a central question in the study of animal communication in recent years. The crux of the issue is whether animal signals are honest, in the sense of conveying reliable informa­ tion from signaler to receiver, or deceitful, in the sense of conveying unreliable information, the falsity of which somehow benefits the signaler. This issue arises in a variety of contexts. When a male courts a female, do his signals honestly convey his quality relative to other males? Or does he exaggerate his quality in order to win over females that would otherwise choose some other male? When one animal signals aggressively in a contest over a resource, does the signaler honestly convey its likelihood of attack? Or does the signaler exaggerate that likelihood in order to intimidate competitors that would other­ wise defeat him? The question of reliability versus deceit arises even in interac­ tions that, on the face of things, seem to be predominantly cooperative. When an offspring begs for food from its parents, does it honestly convey its level of need? Or does the offspring exaggerate its need in order to get more food than the parents would otherwise provide? The issue of reliability and deceit in animal communication resonates with humanobservers for a variety of reasons. One is that the occurrence of deceit is fraught with moral implications.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Ethology Ádám Miklósi Dept
    Introduction to Cognitive ethology Ádám Miklósi Dept. of Ethology Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest [email protected] 2018 Literature This lecture series is based on Shettleworth, S. J. 2010 Cognition, evolution and behaviour (2nd edition) Oxford University Press Pages where you find background information to these topics: •CH 1, 2: 1-53 Introduction •CH 4: 96-119 Learning •CH 8: 261-283; 296-310 Spatial Cognition •CH 12: 417-455 Social cognition •CH 13: 466-497 Social learning •CH 14: 508-546 Communication You DON NOT have to know/learn all of this, check by means of the ppt files which parts of the chapters are relevant Ethology is the biological study of animal and human behaviour in the natural environment (Tinbergen 1953) Why do we study animals? 1. Understanding the biology of animal behaviour (evolution, genetics, physiology, cognition) 2. Understanding human behaviour 3. Practical reasons (welfare, agriculture) Ethological research has significant effect on people’s perceptions of animals Movies, television, shows, books, magazines Concept 1: Darwinian Evolution Natural selection: Change in the characteristics of organisms over time („continuity”) 1. Large reproductive potential in populations 2. Fixed amount of resources 3. Individuals compete for resources (fitness = offspring) 4. There is an individual variation 5. Individual traits can be inherited (Darwin: Origin of the species) Levels (unit) of selection: gene, individual, kin Concept 1: Darwinian Evolution Sources of variation: Mutation and recombination Adaptation: Is it a circular argument? Just so stories? Can we detect and measure adaptation? Distinguishing „adaptation” from „adaptive” Gould and Vrba (1982): Adaptation: specific evolutionary change as a response to a specific environmental parameter Exaptation: earlier adaptation new function non-adaptation („by product”) new function Adaptation has a function Exaptation has an effect E.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Niko Tinbergen R
    Niko Tinbergen R. W. Burkhardt, Jr., University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, Urbana, IL, USA ã 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. Life and Scientific Career was to live in the Arctic among the Inuit and witness the stark, natural beauties of the area. Nikolaas (Niko) Tinbergen, the third of five children of After 15 months in Greenland, the Tinbergens two Dutch schoolteachers, was born in The Hague on returned in the fall of 1933 to Holland. Tinbergen took 15 April 1907. Remarkably, two of the family’s four up again an assistantship in the Leiden Department of sons were eventually awarded Nobel Prizes. Niko’s elder Zoology (a position to which he had been originally brother Jan received the Nobel Prize in Economics in 1969; appointed in 1931). In this capacity, he developed a pro- Niko received the Nobel Prize in Physiology or Medicine gram of research and teaching involving field and labora- in 1973. When reporters asked Niko how it was that his tory studies of animal behavior. He established in the family had produced two Nobel Prize winners, he attrib- spring of 1935 a special, 6 week, laboratory ‘practical’ for uted this not to innate abilities but rather to the support- third-year undergraduates. In this course, he and his ive conditions in which he and his siblings were raised. students researched the reproductive behavior of fish, The Tinbergen parents allowed their children to follow most notably the three-spined stickleback. In summers, their own interests. For Niko, this meant outdoor activ- he took students to a field camp in the Dutch dunes to ities – sports, nature rambles, camping out, and eventually study the behavior of insects and birds.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Umwelten in a Changing World
    Tartu Semiotics Library 18 Tartu Tartu Semiotics Library 18 Animal umwelten in a changing world: Zoosemiotic perspectives represents a clear and concise review of zoosemiotics, present- ing theories, models and methods, and providing interesting examples of human–animal interactions. The reader is invited to explore the umwelten of animals in a successful attempt to retrieve the relationship of people with animals: a cornerstone of the past common evolutionary processes. The twelve chapters, which cover recent developments in zoosemiotics and much more, inspire the reader to think about the human condition and about ways to recover our lost contact with the animal world. Written in a clear, concise style, this collection of articles creates a wonderful bridge between Timo Maran, Morten Tønnessen, human and animal worlds. It represents a holistic approach Kristin Armstrong Oma, rich with suggestions for how to educate people to face the dynamic relationships with nature within the conceptual Laura Kiiroja, Riin Magnus, framework of the umwelt, providing stimulus and opportuni- Nelly Mäekivi, Silver Rattasepp, ties to develop new studies in zoosemiotics. Professor Almo Farina, CHANGING WORLD A IN UMWELTEN ANIMAL Paul Thibault, Kadri Tüür University of Urbino “Carlo Bo” This important book offers the first coherent gathering of perspectives on the way animals are communicating with each ANIMAL UMWELTEN other and with us as environmental change requires increasing adaptation. Produced by a young generation of zoosemiotics scholars engaged in international research programs at Tartu, IN A CHANGING this work introduces an exciting research field linking the biological sciences with the humanities. Its key premises are that all animals participate in a dynamic web of meanings WORLD: and signs in their own distinctive styles, and all animal spe- cies have distinctive cultures.
    [Show full text]
  • Evidence for Tactical Concealment in a Wild Primate
    ARTICLE Received 16 Aug 2012 | Accepted 9 Jan 2013 | Published 12 Feb 2013 DOI: 10.1038/ncomms2468 Evidence for tactical concealment in a wild primate Aliza le Roux1, Noah Snyder-Mackler2, Eila K. Roberts3, Jacinta C. Beehner3,4 & Thore J. Bergman3,5 Theory predicts that cheating individuals should alter their behaviour to avoid detection, yet empirical data for such ‘deceptive’ behaviour (and its putative consequence—punishment) is almost entirely absent from the literature. This dearth of evidence, particularly among pri- mates, limits our understanding of the evolution of deception and punishment. Here, we quantify deception and punishment in a reproductive context in wild geladas (Theropithecus gelada). Individuals involved in extra-pair copulations (9% of observed copulations) exhibited behaviour consistent with tactical deception: they were less likely to vocalize and more likely to copulate when the cuckolded male was a sizable distance away (420 m). Further, many extra-pair copulations (B20%) elicited post-copulatory aggression—likely, punishment— from cuckolded males. This rare empirical evidence of both tactical concealment and reta- liatory aggression offers a potential model system for examining the co-occurrence of deception and punishment in natural settings. 1 Department of Zoology and Entomology, University of the Free State Qwaqwa, Phuthaditjhaba 9866, South Africa. 2 Department of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 90383, USA. 3 Department of Psychology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109, USA. 4 Department of Anthropology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109, USA. 5 Department of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109, USA. Correspondence and requests for materials should be addressed to A.L.R.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Von Frisch
    EntomologistBugBug BUMBLEBEEKARLSWEAT VON FRISCH BEE MIMIC ofof theof the the (1886 - 1982)(LaphriaSubject: flavicollis)Honey bees Month Field:(Agapostemon Ethology Nationality: spp.) Austrian MonthMonth The round dance (left) indicates resources that are a short distance from the hive, while the waggle dance (right) communicates longer distances. Credit: Oliver Feldwick Karl von Frisch is most famous for his discovery and interpretation of the honey bee dance language, for which he and his colleagues were awarded the Nobel Prize in 1973. His experiments relied on training paint-marked bees to feeders at known locations relative to their hive. Then, through careful observation, von Frisch discovered that honey bees per- form a ‘waggle dance’ to communicate the distance and direction of food resources to other Agapostemon is a widespread preference. Like other members of cases, multiple females may share foragers. von Frisch is less well known for many other important contributions that he made Atgenus first of bees glance, in North youAmerica, may flavicollisHalictidae, ,they is commonly are short-tongued found aand single beetles. nest entrance, Once but they each have towithbelieve the 14 studyknown this ofspeciesis honeya bumblebee. across bees, the which acrossand included have the difficulty eastern investigations Unitedextracting States. nectarinto honeyindividualcollected bee builds their vision and prey, andprovisions they the return her studyUnitedHowever, ofStates a microsporidianit’s and shortCanada. straight Most parasite
    [Show full text]
  • E.O. Wilson and B.F. Skinner a Dialogue Between Sociobiology and Radical Behaviorism
    springer.com Life Sciences : Evolutionary Biology Naour, Paul E.O. Wilson and B.F. Skinner A Dialogue Between Sociobiology and Radical Behaviorism The book utilizes an unpublished conversation between B.F. Skinner and E.O. Wilson in 1987 as a springboard to lead readers to a more integrated view of behaviorism and sociobiology Reviewers have characterized Paul Naour's A Dialogue Between Sociobiology and Radical Behaviorism, which includes brief introductions by E.O. Wilson and B.F. Skinner's elder daughter, Julie Vargus, as an idea book. The work will undoubtedly have a significant academic market and provide students and scholars in biology, ethology, psychology, anthropology, sociology and economics a strong foundation in twentieth century history and systems. Praise for A Dialogue Between Sociobiology and Radical Behaviorism: - E.O. Wilson says of the book: ". excellent, an outstanding addition to the history of ideas. It will put Fred Skinner back in the pantheon and, providing context, serve as an excellent introduction to the content and central truths in radical behaviorism. Needless to say, I'm also grateful to have my work following Sociobiology Springer given proper attention." -David Sloan Wilson, author of Darwin’s Cathedral writes: "E.O. Wilson 2009, XIX, 138 p. 25 illus. and B.F. Skinner agreed that the human capacity for change is both a product of genetic 1st evolution and an evolutionary process in its own right. Yet, the paradigms of sociobiology and edition radical behaviorism went in very different directions. Paul Naour's insightful analysis of a taped conversation between Wilson and Skinner goes beyond the historical significance of the conversation and helps to integrate the two paradigms for the future." -Carl Haywood writes: Printed book "The present question is whether evolution by natural selection is a useful set of concepts for Hardcover the development of psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Minds, Cognitive Ethology, and Ethics Colin Allen Indiana University
    The Humane Society Institute for Science and Policy Animal Studies Repository 9-2007 Animal Minds, Cognitive Ethology, and Ethics Colin Allen Indiana University Marc Bekoff University of Colorado, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://animalstudiesrepository.org/acwp_asie Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Comparative Psychology Commons, and the Other Animal Sciences Commons Recommended Citation Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (2007). Animal minds, cognitive ethology, and ethics. The ourJ nal of Ethics, 11(3), 299-317. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Humane Society Institute for Science and Policy. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the Animal Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Animal Minds, Cognitive Ethology, and Ethics Colin Allen1 and Marc Bekoff2 1 Indiana University 2 University of Colorado KEYWORDS animal cognition, consciousness, ethics, science ABSTRACT Our goal in this paper is to provide enough of an account of the origins of cognitive ethology and the controversy surrounding it to help ethicists to gauge for themselves how to balance skepticism and credulity about animal minds when communicating with scientists. We believe that ethicists’ arguments would benefit from better understanding of the historical roots of ongoing controversies. It is not appropriate to treat some widely reported results in animal cognition as if their interpretations are a matter of scientific consensus. It is especially important to understand why loose references to ‘‘cognitive ethology’’ by philosophers can signal ignorance of the field to scientists who are more deeply immersed in the relevant literature.
    [Show full text]