Science, Reason, Knowledge, and Wisdom: a Critique of Specialism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Science, Reason, Knowledge, and Wisdom: a Critique of Specialism Science, Reason, Knowledge, and Wisdom: A Critique of Specialism Nicholas Maxwell University College, London Published in Inquiry, vol. 23, 1980, pp. 19-81. In this paper I argue for a kind of intellectual inquiry which has, as its basic aim, to help all of us to resolve rationally the most important problems that we encounter in our lives, problems that arise as we seek to discover and achieve that which is of value in life. Rational problem-solving involves articulating our problems, proposing and criticizing possible solutions. It also involves breaking problems up into subordinate problems, creating a tradition of specialized problem-solving - specialized scientific, academic inquiry, in other words. It is vital, however, that specialized academic problem-solving be subordinated to discussion of our more fundamental problems of living. At present specialized academic inquiry is dissociated from problems of living - the sin of specialism, which I criticize. I In this paper I discuss two rival views about the nature of intellectual inquiry. I call these two views fundamentalism and specialism. I shall argue that at present the whole institutional structure of scientific, academic inquiry, by and large, presupposes specialism. Of the two views under consideration it is, however, fundamentalism, and not specialism, which provides us with a rational conception of intellectual inquiry. Failure to put fundamentalism into practice has profoundly damaging con-sequences for science and scholarship, and indeed for life, for our whole modern world. Ideally intellectual inquiry ought to help us to tackle rationally those problems of living which we encounter in seeking to discover and achieve that which is of value in life. Intellectual inquiry ought, in other words, to devote reason to the enhancement of wisdom (wisdom being defined here as the capacity to discover and achieve that which is of value in life, for oneself and others - wisdom thus including knowledge and understanding). In fact, at present, scientific, academic inquiry gives priority to the achievement of knowledge only, rather than to the achievement of wisdom. It is essentially the general adoption of specialism which is responsible for the persistence of this highly undesirable state of affairs. II According to fundamentalism, in the end the whole point of intellectual inquiry is to help us to improve our answers to four fundamental questions, namely: 1. What kind of world is this? 2. How do we fit into the world and how did we come to be? 3. What is of most value in life and how is it to be achieved? 4. How can we help develop a better human world?1 In particular, according to fundamentalism, it is a basic task of intellectual inquiry to help us to tackle these four fundamental problems in a rational fashion. Rational problem-solving is understood here to involve, at the very least, putting into practice the two heuristic rules: a. Articulate, and seek to improve the articulation of, the problem to be solved; b. Propose and critically assess possible solutions.2 There is of course more to rational problem-solving than this.3 But these two rules are understood by fundamentalism to constitute the nub of rationality. Thus, according to fundamentalism, the central and fundamental task of intellectual inquiry is to improve the articulation of the above four problems, and to propose and critically assess possible solutions to them. All other intellectual activity is subservient to this. A basic idea of fundamentalism is that ideally it is we ourselves who answer the above four questions, as we live. The proper task of reason, thought, intellectual inquiry is to help us to arrive at answers that we really do wish to give to these questions, rather than to determine the answers for us. Intellectual inquiry is our servant, not our master. It is not in itself any kind of authority or oracle. Two further extremely important, elementary heuristic rules of rational problem-solving are: c. Break up the basic problem to be solved into subordinate, specialized, easier-to-solve problems. d. Interconnect attempts to solve basic and specialized problems, so that the one may influence and be influenced by the other. According to fundamentalism, an immense amount of intellectual activity arises, quite properly, as a result of putting these two heuristic rules into practice. That is, in order to improve our answers to our four basic problems we create a vast network of sub-problems and preliminary problems-the specialized, technical problems of science and scholarship. A great deal of intellectual activity consists in seeking to solve these limited, technical problems of specialized scientific, academic disciplines. It is however of supreme importance - according to fundamentalism - that we do not lose our way within this network, this maze, of sub-problems. If intellectual inquiry is to be rational, it is essential that intellectual priority be given to the four fundamental problems, and to the tasks of proposing and critically assessing possible solutions to them. In order to tackle specialized problems in a rational fashion, in short, it is essential to tackle such problems as sub-problems of the four fundamental problems. Specialized scientists and scholars, in other words, in order to be rational, must also be philosophers or generalists, concerned in their specialized work to help us solve our fundamental problems. Figure 1 gives an indication of the way in which some current specialized academic disciplines may be conceived, in fundamentalist terms, as being designed to help us solve the above four basic problems. As the diagram indicates, it is essential for the intellectual integrity and rationality of intellectual inquiry as a whole that there be a constant two-way flow of information between specialized problem-solving and fundamental problem-solving. Two minor adjustments may be made to the doctrine of fundamentalism as just outlined. In the first place it may be argued that philosophy ought not to be conceived as yet another specialized discipline concerned to solve its own special problems. Rather, philosophy needs to be conceived as that part of the whole intellectual enterprise which seeks to articulate fundamental problems, propose and criticize possible solutions to these problems. Philosophy, according to this conception, constantly gives rise to new specialized problems, and is itself profoundly influenced by our success and failure in seeking to solve specialized problems. It is in just this sense that almost all the great philosophers of the past have contributed to 'philosophy': Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Bacon, Hobbes, Locke, Spinoza, Leibniz, Hume, Kant. Mill, Comte, Marx, Rousseau, Nietzsche, Mach, Russell - to name a few. It is vital, however, according to this viewpoint, that philosophy is not treated as a specialized, professional discipline, the exclusive preserve of the expert. The whole rationale of intellectual inquiry is to promote fundamental rational problem-solving as widely as possible, as an integral part of life. Rendering this the exclusive task of professional philosophers sabotages utterly the whole raison d'etre of intellectual inquiry. This non- specialized, fundamentalist conception of philosophy is perhaps above all to be found upheld by the thinkers of the Enlightenment - for whom critical philosophy was the basic instrument of human enlightenment.4 Strictly, of course, formulating fundamentalism in terms of this Enlightenment conception of philosophy requires us to modify Figure 1, in that 'philosophy' ceases altogether to be any kind of specialized academic discipline existing alongside other disciplines, and becomes instead identical to all thought about fundamental problems, ideally pursued rationally as an integral part of life. Formulating fundamentalism in this way, however, is unfortunately liable to lead to misunderstandings. Academic philosophers will object to the disappearance of specialized philosophy, not realizing that there must always be an important place in academic inquiry for those concerned with fundamental problems and concerned to promote open, critical discussion of fundamental problems. Everyone else will object to the idea that philosophy should monopolize concern with fundamental problems, 'philosophy' being misunderstood here to mean 'academic philosophy' rather than being understood to be simply all our personal and public thinking about our fundamental problems. The essential tenet of fundamentalism after all is that all inquiry, personal, social, and academic, ought to be organized along fundamentalist lines. Whether or not thought about fundamental problems is called 'philosophy', and whether or not academic philosophy continues to exist as a specialized discipline, are matters of minor importance. In order to avoid misunderstandings concerning these minor matters, I leave Figure 1 unmodified. (The diagram is, in fact, a modified version of the original diagram, one that appears in my Cutting God in Half – And Putting the Pieces Together Again.) The second qualification that may be made to the above viewpoint amounts to this. It is quite wrong - it may be argued - to suggest that the enterprise of seeking to improve our answers to the above four fundamental questions is somehow exclusively the concern of intellectual inquiry. Literature, theatre, music, art, religion can all be interpreted as being concerned to illuminate our responses to these basic questions - especially the last two questions. Our whole culture can, in other words, be conceived of in fundamentalist terms as being designed, ideally, to help us to discover and create that which is of most value in life. In engaging in our work, in social and political activity, we should, ideally - it may be argued - be seeking to develop improved answers in practice to the last two questions, in one way or another. Indeed, in our whole way of life -our way of being on this earth - we give implicitly our actual answers to such questions, whether we are aware of this or not. And in so far as we seek to improve our lives, we seek to improve the actual answers that we give to these questions, in the fabric of our actions.
Recommended publications
  • Life Without Meaning? Richard Norman
    17 Life Without Meaning? Richard Norman The Alpha Course, a well‐known evangelical Christian programme, advertises itself with posters displaying the words THE MEANING OF LIFE IS_________, followed by the invitation ‘Fill in the blanks at alpha.org’. Followers of the course will discover that ‘Men and women were created to live in a relationship with God’, and that ‘without that relationship there will always be a hunger, an emptiness, a feeling that something is missing’.1 We all have that need because we are all sinners, we are told, and the truth which will fill the need is that Jesus Christ died to save us from our sins. Not all Christian or other religious views about the meaning of life are as simplistic as this, but they typically share the assumptions that the meaning of life is to be found in some belief whose truth we need to recognize, and that this is a belief about the purpose for which we exist. A further implication is that this purpose is the purpose intended by the God who created us, and that if we fail to identify and live in accordance with that purpose, our lives will lack meaning. The assumption is echoed in the question many humanists will have encountered: if you don’t believe in a God, what’s the point of it all? And many people who don’t share the answer still accept the legitimacy of the question – ‘What is the meaning of life?’ – and assume that what we need is a correct belief, religious or non‐religious, which will fill the blank in the sentence ‘The meaning of life is …’.
    [Show full text]
  • History and Theory of Philosophy
    FEDERAL STATE BUDGETARY EDUCATIONAL INSTITUTION OF HIGHER EDUCATION "BASHKIR STATE MEDICAL UNIVERSITY" OF THE MINISTRY OF HEALTHCARE OF THE RUSSIAN FEDERATION (FSBEI HE BSMU MOH Russia) HISTORY AND THEORY OF PHILOSOPHY Textbook Ufa 2020 1 UDC 1(09)(075.8) BBC 87.3я7 H90 Reviewers: Doctor of Philosophy, Professor, Head of the department «Social work» FSBEI HE «Bashkir State University» U.S. Vildanov Doctor of Philosophy, Professor at the Department of Philosophy and History FSBEIHE «Bashkir State Agricultural University» A.I. Stoletov History and theory of philosophy:textbook/ K.V. Khramova, H90 R.I. Devyatkina, Z.R. Sadikova, O.M. Ivanova, O.G. Afanasyeva, A.S. Zubairova-Valeeva, N.R. Mingazova, G.R. Davletshina — Ufa: Ufa: FSBEIHEBSMUMOHRussia, 2020. – 127 p. The manual was prepared in accordance with the requirements of the Federal State Educational Standard of Higher Education in specialty 31.05.01 «General Medicine» the current curriculum and on the basis of the work program on the discipline of philosophy. The manual is focused on the competence-based learning model. It has an original, uniform for all classes structure, including the topic, a summary of the training questions, the subject of essays, training materials, test items with response standards, recommended literature. This manual covers topics related to the periods of development of world philosophy. Designed for students in the specialty 31.05.01 «General Medicine». It is recommended to be published by the Coordinating Scientific and Methodological Council and was approved by the decision of the Editorial and Publishing Council of the BSMU of the Ministry of Healthcare of Russia.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy and Life by Saad Malook
    57 Al-Hikmat Volume 28 (2008), pp. 57-70 PHILOSOPHY AND LIFE SAAD MALOOK* Abstract. The paper presents the applications of philosophy to life. Philosophy has been serving the homo sapiens for thousands of years. It has been the queen of all sciences and was the cradle for entire human civilization. The topic, ‘Philosophy and Life’ is so extensive and rich in its nature that many volumes of books could be written but my purpose to write on this topic is to clear the misconceptions regarding philosophy and its significance to life, which are present among various circles in the present age. What is the nature of philosophy? How was it in the past? What is life? Has it meaning and purpose in this world? How does philosophy contribute for man today? How will it improve the quality of life of man in future? Which philosophy of life should man adopt to make this world a heaven? These are the questions, whose answers are tried to be sought out in this paper. Man’s impatient mind has ever been in search of the hidden realities in the microcosm (man) and the macrocosm (universe). The history of man reveals that he has contributed to the improve- ment of the world. Thales’ search for the ultimate substance made a start to the odyssey of philosophy, which journeyed through various trenches, uneven paths, faced numerous challenges from *Mr. Saad Malook is Lecturer at Department of Philosophy, University of the Punjab, New Campus, Lahore-54590 (Pakistan). (E-mail: [email protected]) 58 S.
    [Show full text]
  • Complete Issue
    Center for Open Access in Science Open Journal for Studies in Philosophy 2019 ● Volume 3 ● Number 1 https://doi.org/10.32591/coas.ojsp.0301 ISSN (Online) 2560-5380 OPEN JOURNAL FOR STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY (OJSP) ISSN (Online) 2560-5380 https://www.centerprode.com/ojsp.html [email protected] Publisher: Center for Open Access in Science (COAS) Belgrade, SERBIA https://www.centerprode.com [email protected] Editor-in-Chief: Tatyana Vasileva Petkova (PhD) South-West University “Neofit Rilski”, Faculty of Philosophy, Blagoevgrad, BULGARIA Editorial Board: Jane Forsey (PhD) University of Winnipeg, Faculty of Arts, CANADA Cristóbal Friz Echeverria (PhD) University of Santiago de Chile, Faculty of Humanities, CHILE Plamen Makariev (PhD) Sofia University “St. Kliment Ohridski”, Faculty of Philosophy, BULGARIA Antoaneta Nikolova (PhD) South-West University “Neofit Rilski”, Faculty of Philosophy, Blagoevgrad, BULGARIA Adrian Nita (PhD) Romanian Academy, Institute of Philosophy and Psychology, Bucharest, ROMANIA Hasnije Ilazi (PhD) University of Prishtina, Faculty of Philosophy, KOSOVO Copy Editor: Goran Pešić Center for Open Access in Science, Belgrade Open Journal for Studies in Philosophy, 2019, 3(1), 1-24. ISSN (Online) 2560-5380 __________________________________________________________________ CONTENTS 1 Hellenistic Philosophy in Greek and Roman Times Ioanna-Soultana Kotsori 6 Pedagogical Views of Plato in his Dialogues Marina Nasaina 17 The Idea of Tolerance – John Locke and Immanuel Kant Tatyana Vasileva Petkova Open Journal for Studies
    [Show full text]
  • Rudolf Eucken's Philsophy of Life
    RUDOLF EUCKEN’S PHILOSOPHY OF LIFE BY W. R. BOYCE GIBSON LECTURER IN PHILOSOPHY AT THE UNIVERSITY OF LONDON LONDON ADAM AND CHARLES BLACK 1906 PREFACE T he chapters in this book were originally delivered as inter-collegiate lectures at Westfield College, Uni­ versity of London, during the Michaelmas term, 1905. They arose out of the deep respect I feel for the work and personality of Professor Eucken, and from a profound sense of the importance of his teaching for philosophy, for religion, and for everyday life. In the publication of these lectures I have been most generously assisted by the Hibbert Trustees. My sincerest thanks are due to them, not only for the grant defraying the expenses of publication, but for their sympathetic recognition of the value of Professor Eucken’s work, and of the need for making it better known to English readers. I gratefully acknowledge the help given me by my wife in the typing of the manuscript and the reading of the proofs. I am also most indebted in this connec­ tion to Professor Eucken himself, who very kindly read through all the proof-sheets, and assisted me in many ways with the most unfailing cordiality and goodwill. CONTENTS CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY— EUCKEN’S PHILOSOPHICAL PUBLICA­ TIONS— OUTLINE SKETCH OF THE NEW IDEALISM, WITH PRELIMINARY APPRECIATION AND CRITICISM— EUCKEN’S PHILOSOPHY A RALLYING-POINT FOR IDEALISTIC EFFORT— THE SOLIDARITY OF IDEALISM 1 -2 1 CHAPTER II e u c k e n ’s v i e w s o n t h e r e l a t i o n o f p h il o s o p h y t o HISTORY, PARTICULARLY TO THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY,
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kanfs Influence on the Psychology of Alfred Adler
    Immanuel Kanfs Influence on the Psychology of Alfred Adler Mark H. Stone Abstract The influence of immanuel Kant's philosophy on the psychology of Alfred Adler is important to understand because Kant much earlier addressed many ideas and concepts assumed original with Adler. Kant addressed the concepts of private sense and common sense, the primacy of reason, the existential questions of life, fictions, the power ofthe mind over sense perceptions, the unconscious and conscious mind, unity of the person, fostering community feeling, and determining a moral course of action, all concepts Adler later applied to his psychology. Familiarity with Kant's works can help clinicians gain a better understanding of what Adler wrote and im- plied when explicating Individual Psychology. Kant's writings can be complicated and difficult to understand, but several very readable essays are recommended and readily available. The purpose of this article is to show the influence of Immanuel Kant's (1 724-1804) philosofjhy upon the psychology of Alfred Adler (1870-1937). A number of Adier's important ideas can be traced back to the writings of Kant. This is not to diminish Adier's contributions to psychology because it is Adier's elucidation of these concepts for understanding behavior that is striking. This connection between Kant and Adler relates a segment of the continuing stream of thought in intellectual history that connects the ideas from one thinker to those of another. Ellenberger (1970) wrote, "Adler has many affinities with Kant" (p. 628). However, Ellenberger stopped short of elucidating any of these connections save a very short discussion of com- mon sense and private sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Pursuits of Wisdom
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher Chapter 1 Introduction On Philosophy as a Way of Life 1.1. Philosophy Ancient, Modern, and Contemporary Philosophy is a subject of study. In this, it is just like physics, mathematics, French language and literature, anthropology, economics, and all the other established specialties in contemporary higher education. Undergraduate institutions every- where have departments of philosophy offering degrees in the subject. These de- partments are staffed with lecturers and professors with advanced degrees certi- fying their preparation as teachers and as professional philosophers—as people who pursue research in the field and write articles and books of philosophy and on philosophy, just as physics lecturers do physics and write on physics, or an- thropologists do and write on anthropology. In fact, this book is just such a book of philosophy, written by a professional philosopher and teacher of philosophy. But, even as a subject of study, philosophy is different from all these others. One indication of this is the fact—often a cause of frustration, even irritation, in professional philosophers when confronted by it—that in the popular imagina- tion, and even among many beginning students, a philosopher is often conceived simply as someone who has a wide and deep experience of human life and insight into its problems. On this view, a philosopher is supposed to be a wise person, full of good advice on what to value in life most and what is worth valuing less, on how to deal with adversity and how to develop and sustain a balanced and harmonious, properly human, outlook on life, one’s own and others’.
    [Show full text]
  • Getting Beyond Religion As Science: "Unstifling" Worldview Formation in American Public Education
    Getting Beyond Religion as Science: "Unstifling" Worldview Formation in American Public Education Barry P. McDonald* Abstract Since ancient times, Western civilization has witnessed a great debate over a simple but profound question: From whence did we come? Two major worldviews have dominated that debate: a theistic worldview holding that we, and the world in which we live, are the purposeful product of a supernatural creator; and a materialistic worldview holding that we are the product of unintelligent and random natural forces. This debate rose to the fore with Darwin’s publication of his theory of evolution and the development of the modern scientific establishment. In America, it initially took its most conspicuous form in efforts by creationists to ban the teaching of evolution in American public schools, and then to have creationism taught as science. After legal setbacks based on the Establishment Clause of the First Amendment, that effort morphed into the intelligent design movement of the past couple of decades. That movement’s aim to gain a place in the science curriculum recently stalled with a court ruling that it was, like the creationists before it, attempting to teach religious concepts as science. Most recently, a notable group of scientists and atheists have reversed the trend of defending science against religious attacks and launched a very public and aggressive campaign against religion itself. Prominent scientists and other believers have responded with works attempting to reconcile science and faith. * Associate Professor of Law, Pepperdine University School of Law. J.D., Northwestern University, Chicago, Illinois (1988). I would like to extend my grateful thanks and appreciation to Kent Greenawalt, Kurt Lash, and Steve Smith for some very helpful comments on this Article.
    [Show full text]
  • Anthropos Redux: a Defence of Monism in the Anthropocene Epoch
    © FRAME NO. 29.2 NOVEMBER 2016 | 29 – 46 Anthropos Redux: A Defence of Monism in the Anthropocene Epoch ROSI BRAIDOTTI ABSTRACT This essay starts from the new and internally contradictory assumption that the historical contemporary concerns, such as the situation of today is unprecedented fast technological developments on in ecological, economic, socio- the one hand and the perpetuation political, as well as affective of more familiar patterns of terms. The era known as the oppression, like structural Anthropocene requires new ways economic inequalities, on the of thinking in order to account other. Both aspects of the present for new practices and discourses predicament will receive critical related to this situation. By attention in the cartography of offering a defence of Spinozist the Anthropocenic era that I will monism, this essay attempts to discuss here and which I read in strike a critical balance between terms of the posthuman condition. 30 ROSI BRAIDOTTI About Monism Monistic ontologies have had a hard time in critical thought. A “monistic universe,” predicated upon the rejection of binary oppositions and dialectical negativity has often been misunderstood or dismissed. In this paper I will therefore challenge this knee-jerk reaction and defend monism by exploring some of its implications for a theory and practice of neo-material vitalist vision of political subjectivity. In the recently emerged framework of the Anthropocene,1 a monistic approach to subjectivity can offer not only an escape from the dualistic foundations locatable in most ideological and political social structures, but also the starting-point of a new relational ecology that rejects violent hierarchies, is more compassionate, and actively de-centres anthropocentrism.
    [Show full text]
  • Life Is Meaningless.’ Compared to What? Damian Veal*
    Journal of Philosophy of Life Vol.7, No.1 (July 2017):208-260 ‘Life is Meaningless.’ Compared to What? Damian Veal* Abstract James Tartaglia argues that the question of the meaning of life, when properly construed, is ‘the keystone of philosophy,’ that which ‘locks its traditional preoccupations in place’ and ‘allows them to bear weight in an intellectual culture dominated by science.’ He also argues that we ought to reject the question’s premise and conclude that ‘life is meaningless.’ This paper critically examines what Tartaglia calls ‘the real question of the meaning of life’ and its implications. It concludes that Tartaglia provides no good reasons for maintaining that his version of the question is not, in the words of his imaginary interlocutor, ‘a philosophical dead-end,’ but that there is a broader sense of the question that might indeed qualify as a fundamental wellspring of philosophical inquiry. Introduction James Tartaglia’s Philosophy in a Meaningless Life: A System of Nihilism, Consciousness and Reality is a work of rare philosophical ambition.1 Deeming the ‘big ideas’ and ‘sweeping visions’ of the great systematic metaphysicians of the past to be both more interesting and more ‘philosophical’ than the modest, piecemeal efforts of his contemporaries, Tartaglia has self-consciously set out to emulate the former. Mercifully lacking the overweening grandiosity of some of those past greats who seem to have inspired him, however, Tartaglia is modest enough to admit that he ‘may well not have succeeded.’2 Also happily absent is the kind of tortuous, circumlocutory prose for which some of those same luminaries are notorious: Tartaglia’s book is elegantly written and clearly argued throughout.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Understanding of Communication As Testimony Jessica Nicole Sturgess Purdue University
    Purdue University Purdue e-Pubs Open Access Dissertations Theses and Dissertations January 2016 Saying the World Anew: A Philosophical Understanding of Communication as Testimony Jessica Nicole Sturgess Purdue University Follow this and additional works at: https://docs.lib.purdue.edu/open_access_dissertations Recommended Citation Sturgess, Jessica Nicole, "Saying the World Anew: A Philosophical Understanding of Communication as Testimony" (2016). Open Access Dissertations. 1276. https://docs.lib.purdue.edu/open_access_dissertations/1276 This document has been made available through Purdue e-Pubs, a service of the Purdue University Libraries. Please contact [email protected] for additional information. Graduate School Form 30 Updated 12/26/2015 PURDUE UNIVERSITY GRADUATE SCHOOL Thesis/Dissertation Acceptance This is to certify that the thesis/dissertation prepared By Jessica N. Sturgess Entitled SAYING THE WORLD ANEW: A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF COMMUNICATION AS TESTIMONY For the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Is approved by the final examining committee: Dr. Patrice Buzzanell Dr. Ramsey Eric Ramsey Co-chair Dr. Daniel W. Smith Co-chair Dr. Stacey Connaughton Dr. Calvin O. Schrag To the best of my knowledge and as understood by the student in the Thesis/Dissertation Agreement, Publication Delay, and Certification Disclaimer (Graduate School Form 32), this thesis/dissertation adheres to the provisions of Purdue University’s “Policy of Integrity in Research” and the use of copyright material. Approved by Major Professor(s): Dr. Patrice Buzzanell and Dr. Daniel W. Smith Dr. Marifran Mattson 4/11/2016 Approved by: Head of the Departmental Graduate Program Date i SAYING THE WORLD ANEW: A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF COMMUNICATION AS TESTIMONY A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of Purdue University by Jessica N.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Life in Contemporary Society Masahiro Morioka*
    The Review of Life Studies Vol.8 (October 2017):15-22 Philosophy of Life in Contemporary Society Masahiro Morioka* 1. Introduction Academic bioethics and environmental ethics were imported from the United States and Europe to Japan in the 1980s. At that time I was a graduate student. I started studying the English literature on those disciplines, but I soon developed a huge frustration with them. The first reason for this was that bioethics at that time lacked deep philosophical investigations on the concept of life and the concept of death, and without having undertaken such investigations they were trying to figure out sound guidelines on difficult ethical issues surrounding advanced medicine. Of course, consensus building is very important, but it seemed to me that pursuing consensus without a deep philosophical understanding of life and death was senseless and fruitless. For example, in the 1970s and 80s there was a worldwide debate on whether or not brain death is human death, and many advanced nations concluded that a human being that has lost the integrated function of the whole body should be considered dead, and that when the function of the whole brain is irreversibly lost the integrated function of the human being should be considered to disappear permanently. However, in the debate about brain death, the fundamental question of “what is death?” has rarely been investigated from a philosophical point of view. Philosophically speaking, the reason that a human being that has irreversibly lost the function of the whole brain should be considered dead is not so crystal clear. It should also be noted that this question was heavily discussed in the Japanese debate on brain death in the 1980s and 90s.
    [Show full text]