Work Done at Princeton Caleb Cohoe

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Work Done at Princeton Caleb Cohoe WORK DONE AT PRINCETON CALEB COHOE ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY PHI 500 The Philosophy of Plato A. Nehamas F ‘06 Republic PHI 516 Special Topics in the History of Philosophy B. Morison F ‘06 Sextus Empiricus: Outlines I PHI 501 The Philosophy of Aristotle H. Lorenz S ‘07 Metaphysics Lambda PHI 516 Special Topics in the History of Philosophy P. Kalligas S ‘07 Plotinus’ Theory of the Soul PHI 515 Special Topics in the History of Philosophy J. Cooper F ‘07 Philosophy as a Way of Life: Plotinus vis-à vis the Earlier Tradition PHI 501 The Philosophy of Aristotle H. Lorenz S ‘08 Nicomachean Ethics VI PHI 515 Special Topics in the History of Philosophy J. Cooper F ‘08 Human Action: Aristotle and the Stoics Rutgers The Philosophy of Aristotle A. Code F ‘08 Metaphysics Zeta PHI 515 Special Topics in the History of Philosophy H. Lorenz S ‘09 Posidonius’ Moral Psychology PHI 501 The Philosophy of Aristotle H. Lorenz/ F ‘09 Posterior Analytics I B. Morison PHI 501 The Philosophy of Aristotle H. Lorenz/ S ‘10 Posterior Analytics II B. Morison PHI 501 The Philosophy of Aristotle B. Morison F ‘10 Prior Analytics Units Written and Oral Examination on Plato’s Republic A. Nehamas/ F ‘06 (PHI 500) H. Lorenz ‚Aristotle, Zeno, and Continuity‛ (Independent B. Morison F ‘06 Work) ‚The Principles of Change and of Substance: Aristo- H. Lorenz F ‘08 tle’s Metaphysics Lambda 2‛ (PHI 501 ‘08) Classical Philosophy Reading Group (CPRG) Plato, Republic, V 473e-VI 503a F ‘06-S ‘07 Epicurus, Letter to Herodotus S ‘07 Aristotle, De Motu Animalium S ‘08 Plato, Sophist, 236d9-261b F ‘08-S ‘09 Aristotle, Physics II F ‘09 Simplicius, Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, Selec- S ‘10 tions that quote and discuss Anaxagoras Plato, Timaeus, 27c-47e F ‘10 Presentations ‚Republic 489-90, Philosophy and the City: Transla- CPRG F ‘06 tion and Comments‛ Caleb Cohoe ▪ Work Done at Princeton 2 ‚The Principles of Change and of Substance: Aristo- H. Lorenz S ‘07 tle’s Metaphysics Lambda 2‛ (PHI 501) ‚Republic 497-8, Philosophical Education: Translation CPRG S ‘07 and Comments‛ ‚Enneads IV 7.11-12, Plotinus on the Immortality of P. Kalligas S ‘07 the Soul: Translation and Comments‛ (PHI 516) ‚De Motu Animalium 3-4, The Need for an Unmoved CPRG S ‘08 Origin: Translation and Comments‛ ‚The Significance of Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean: H. Lorenz S ‘08 A Response to Hursthouse,‛(PHI 501) ‚Sophist 242-4, The Earlier Philosophers’ Neglect of CPRG F ‘08 Being: Translation and Comments‛ ‚Sophist 251-2, The Need for Some Mixture among CPRG S ‘09 Things: Translation and Comments‛ ‚Physics II 5, Chance as a Cause: Translation and CPRG F ‘09 Comments‛ ‚Simplicius’s Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, CPRG S ‘10 177-79, Aristotle’s Criticisms of Anaxagoras’ Use of Infinity: Translation and Comments‛ ‚Timaeus 46a2-47e2, The Purpose and Causes of Per- CPRG F ‘10 ception: Translation and Comments‛ SPECIAL REQUIREMENTS IN ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Units Greek Sight Translation C. Wildberg F ‘06 Latin Sight Translation C. Wildberg F ‘07 Latin Reading List Examination J. Cooper F ‘08 Texts: Augustine: Confessiones XI; De Libero Arbitrio II Boethius: Consolation of Philosophy, Theological Tractates Cicero: De Finibus I, II, III, and V Lucretius: De Rerum Natura I-III Seneca: De Ira I-II Greek Reading List Examination J. Cooper S ‘09 Texts: Aristophanes: Clouds Aristotle: Categories 1-5; Nicomachean Ethics I, II 1-6, III 1-5, VII 1-3, X 6-8; Physics II; De Anima II 1-7, 12; Metaphysics and Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers, VII, 39-160 Euclid: Elements I Herodotus: Histories I Plato: Apology; Parmenides 126a-137b; Phaedo; Protagoras; Republic I, II, IV, V 471c-VII, X to 607a; Theaetetus 142a-187a Plotinus: Enneads I 4 (On Eudaimonia), IV 8 (On the Descent of the Soul into Bodies), V 1 (On the Three Primary Hypostases) Sextus Empiricus: Outlines of Pyrrhonian Skepticism I Zeno of Elea: ‚B‛ fragments in Diels-Kranz MEDIEVAL AND MODERN HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY PHI 515 Special Topics in the History of Philosophy C. Normore F ‘06 Duns Scotus’s De Primo Principio Caleb Cohoe ▪ Work Done at Princeton 3 PHI 705 First-Year Seminar P. Benacerraf F ‘06 Frege’s Foundations of Arithmetic PHI 515 Special Topics in the History of Philosophy D. Garber S ‘07 Cartesian Dualism and 17 th Century Material- ism PHI 502 The Philosophy of Kant D. Hogan F ‘10 Kant’s Philosophy of Religion Unit Written Examination on Cartesian Dualism (PHI 515) D. Garber F ‘06 Reading Groups Soren Kierkegaard, Concluding Unscientific Postscript a F ‘06-S ‘07 Thomas Aquinas, De Ente et Essentia S ‘10 METAPHYSICS, EPISTEMOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF MIND PHI 539 Theory of Knowledge T. Kelly/ S ‘08 Evidence B. van Fraassen PHI 540 Metaphysics J. Hawthorne S ‘09 Topics in Contemporary Metaphysics PHI 513 Topics in Recent and Contemporary Philosophy F. Jackson/ F ‘09 Perception M. Johnston PHI 535 Philosophy of Mind A. Nehamas F ‘10 Intention, Action, and Freedom Units ‚Rationality, Evidence, and Epistemic Permission: T. Kelly S ‘08 Against Roger White’s ‚Epistemic Permissive- ness‛ (PHI 539) ‚Tenseless Theories and the Passing of Time: An Ex- A. Elga F ‘08 amination of Two B-Theory Attempts to Explain Our Experience of Temporal Asymmetry‛ (Inde- pendent Work) Presentations and Workshops Participant, ‚Knowledge, Faith and Disagreement: Departmental S ‘08 The Epistemological Significance of Religious Plu- Workshop ralism‛ ETHICS, VALUE THEORY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Units ‚The Aim and Method of Ethics: John McDowell and J. Cooper S ‘09 Aristotle‛ (Independent Work) ‚God, Causality, and Petitionary Prayer‛ (Independ- G. Rosen S ‘09 ent Work) Reading Groups Philosophy of Religion Reading Group (PRRG) F ‘06-F ‘10 Presentations ‚Aquinas’s Basis for Ethics‛ PRRG S ‘08 ‚God, Causality, and Petitionary Prayer‛ PRRG S ‘10 ‚John Hare on the Atonement‛ PRRG S ‘10 Caleb Cohoe ▪ Work Done at Princeton 4 ‚Leibniz and Aquinas on Whether God Must Create‛ PRRG F ‘10 MISCELLANEOUS PHI 340 Philosophical Logic H. Halvorson F ‘07 Alternatives to, and Extensions of, Classical Logic PHI 599 Dissertation Seminar S-J. Leslie F ‘09 PHI 599 Dissertation Seminar A. Elga S ‘10 Units Problem sets and take-home examination (PHI 340) H. Halvorson F ‘07 French Sight Translation J. Cooper/ F ‘07 D. Garber Presentations ‚The Separability of Soul and Intellect in Aristotle’s S-J. Leslie F ‘09 De Anima I and II‛ (PHI 599) ‚Aristotle’s Argument in De Anima III 4 for the Im- A. Elga S ‘10 materiality of Intellect‛ (PHI 599) GENERAL EXAM ‚The Cognitive Capacities in Aristotle’s De Anima H. Lorenz S ‘09 and De Sensu, with a Particular Focus on Thought‛ (Chair) C. Wildberg G. Harman G. Rosen PROJECTED COURSEWORK PHI 500 The Philosophy of Plato H. Lorenz S ‘11 Philebus PHI 501 The Philosophy of Aristotle S. Menn S ‘11 Metaphysics PHI 540 Metaphysics B. Kment/ S ‘11 S. Dasgupta .
Recommended publications
  • The Liar Paradox As a Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument Menashe Schwed Ashkelon Academic College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Schwed, Menashe, "The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument" (1999). OSSA Conference Archive. 48. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA3/papersandcommentaries/48 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Title: The Liar Paradox as a Reductio ad Absurdum Author: Menashe Schwed Response to this paper by: Lawrence Powers (c)2000 Menashe Schwed 1. Introduction The paper discusses two seemingly separated topics: the origin and function of the Liar Paradox in ancient Greek philosophy and the Reduction ad absurdum mode of argumentation. Its goal is to show how the two topics fit together and why they are closely connected. The accepted tradition is that Eubulides of Miletos was the first to formulate the Liar Paradox correctly and that the paradox was part of the philosophical discussion of the Megarian School. Which version of the paradox was formulated by Eubulides is unknown, but according to some hints given by Aristotle and an incorrect version given by Cicero1, the version was probably as follows: The paradox is created from the Liar sentence ‘I am lying’.
    [Show full text]
  • Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Title: Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism Author: Dariusz Kubok Citation style: Kubok Dariusz. (2015). Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism. "Folia Philosophica" (T. 34 (2015), s. 9-31). Folia Philosophica 34 ISSN 2353-9445 (online) ISSN 1231-0913 (print) Dariusz Kubok Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism Abstract: The present article attempts to shed light on the sources of philosophi- cal criticism of early Greece and on the origins of the critical attitude adopted by the thinkers of the period. Above all, however, reflections presented hereby are meant to serve as a backdrop for analyses of a much broader scope. The study seeks to identify the defining characteristics of early Greek criticism, upon which basis the author puts forth a proposition for a general typology of its forms. Complement- ing the present comments is a brief discussion of the suggested types of philosophical criticism in light of the views of some of the leading philosophers of the time. Keywords: early Greek philosophy, critical thinking, criticism, skepticism, typology There is universal agreement that a critical approach is the main force pushing human thought forward, and that criticism, as an attribute of thought, must be an essential element of rational reflection on real- ity. A deficit of criticism leads not only to stagnation in scholarship and science, but also to the appearance of various forms of dogmatism, which do not permit the emergence of alternative views, nor the revi- sion of positions acknowledged as final.
    [Show full text]
  • Humor As Philosophical Subversion, Especially in the Skeptics
    Humor as Philosophical Subversion, Especially in the Skeptics Richard Bett 1. Introduction Aristotle is not exactly a comedian. He wrote about comedy in the lost second book of the Poetics, and, as discussed in another paper in this volume, he wrote about wittiness (εὐτραπελία) in his ethical works. But he does not exhibit much of either. What humor there is in Aristotle seems to fall into two main varieties. First, there is word-play that engages the reader’s attention, which can perhaps be seen as an instance of a technique he describes in Rhetoric 3.10, that of saying “smart things and things that create a good impression” (τὰ ἀστεῖα καὶ τὰ εὐδοκιµοῦντα, 1410b6).1 Early in the Nicomachean Ethics, he says that in endeavoring to determine the principles (ἀρχαί) of ethics, we should begin (ἀρκτέον) with things known to us (1095b2-4). A little later, introducing the idea of the function (ἔργον) of a human being, he asks whether we can seriously consider that a human being as such (as opposed to people in various occupations) is ἀργόν (1097b28- 30) – which is intentionally ambiguous between “without function” and “lazy.” In De Caelo, introducing the topic of minimal magnitudes, he says that positing such a minimal magnitude (τοὐλάχιστον) will make the biggest difference (τὰ µέγιστα) in mathematics (271b10-11). And in De Interpretatione, discussing names, he says that “non-human 1 Unless otherwise noted, translations are my own. In the case of Timon, I sometimes draw on translations in Bett 2000 and Bett 2015. In the case of Sextus I generally draw on Bett 1997, Bett 2005, and Bett 2012.
    [Show full text]
  • Or Not to Be(Lieve)? (Skepticism & Inner Peace)
    To Be(lieve) or Not to Be(lieve)? (skepticism & inner peace) 1. Ataraxia: Happiness in Skepticism: The ancient philosophers believed that there was happiness in wisdom. If we pursued truth, we would be happy. In their pursuit of Truth and Happiness, the ancient skeptics (e.g., Pyrrho of Elis, ~300 BC ; Sextus Empiricus, ~200 AD) noticed that, for pretty much any issue, a good argument could be presented for BOTH sides. Famously, the skeptic Carneades gave a public speech commending justice and our understanding of it, only to give, the very next day, a speech refuting everything he’d said the day before! (Antithesis) The result is that we have no rational basis for believing one side rather than the other, since both are equally well-supported. (Equipollence) Therefore, we must remain agnostic, suspending belief. (Epoché) The result was interesting: By suspending belief, they achieved a state of inner peace and tranquility! (Ataraxia) It was their very dissatisfaction during their quest for happiness and truth which led the first skeptics to discover the true way to happiness. Sextus Empiricus tells a story: Indeed, what happened to the Skeptic is just like what is told of Apelles the painter. For it is said that once upon a time, when he was painting a horse and wished to depict the horse’s froth, he failed so completely that he gave up and threw his sponge at the picture – the sponge on which he used to wipe the paints from his brush – and that in striking the picture the sponge produced the desired effect.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Empiricus and the Scientific Scepticism
    ENCEPHALOS 50, 62-74, 2013 SEXTUS EMPIRICUS AND THE SCIENTIFIC SCEPTI- CISM STAVROS J.BALOYANNIS* Summary philosophical books, which survived, but remained for long in obscurity, been rediscovered in the late Renaissance. Two Sextus Empiricus is the most eminent representative of these works on the title, “Adversus Mathematikus”, include of the ancient sceptisism, which is a Post-Classical, Hellenis- large number of strong arguments against the Logicians, the tic philosophy based on the criterion of life, the experience Physicists and the Ethicists. The third and most important of and the analysis of phenomena, aiming to provide a straight the books on the title “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” provides an out- and practical way of life, leading to interior peace and mental line of Pyrrhonian scepticism, incorporating at the same time tranquility, sharply opposed to a purely theoretical pursuit of his own philosophical doctrines. Sextus offers thoroughly a dogmatic philosophy. The term “sceptic” is a derivative of the general overview of scepticism, describing and explaining the noun, skepsis (σκέψις), which means thought, examination, meaning of the sceptical investigation, the value of suspen- inquiry, consideration, meditation and investigation. The scep- sion of judgment and the importance of the sceptical dialectics. tical school was connected for a long period of time with the Sextus insists that the skepticism does not accept or reject any Empirical school of physicians, who based the good medical impression and substantially does not affirm or deny anything. practice on the clinical experience rather than on the theoret- Sextus claims that appearances (φαινόμενα) are the practical ical erudition, dedicating themselves to observation, memory criteria of approaching to the truth and by the continuous inves- and continuous clinical practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Can an Ancient Greek Sceptic Be Eudaimôn (Or Happy)? and What Difference Does the Answer Make to Us?
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy Vol. VI 2012 Issue 1 Can an ancient Greek sceptic be eudaimôn (or happy)? And what difference does the answer make to us? Richard Bett (Johns Hopkins University) The paper explores how far the ancient Greek sceptics in fact accept, and how far they should accept, the central Greek ethical notion of eudaimonia , usually translated "happiness" - and what, if anything, the answers may tell us today. The first section shows that sceptics of both the Academic and Pyrrhonist traditions frequently employ the notion of eudaimonia , apparently without discomfort. The second section draws attention to a contrast within the relevant works of Sextus Empiricus - one of them being willing to speak of the sceptic's eudaimonia and the other entirely avoiding this - and considers some possible reasons why, at some point in his life, Sextus might have found the notion problematic. The answers suggested are, first, that the term eudaimonia , at least as normally used by non-sceptical philosophers, presupposes that it is possible to rank human lives objectively in terms of their levels of well-being, and second, that the term standardly carries with it a commitment to a certain kind of long-term structure in one's life; there is at least a serious question whether either of these is consistent with sceptical suspension of judgement. The third section examines how far a sceptic could aspire to happiness , where this is not assumed to be equivalent to eudaimonia , and touches on several modern philosophers who have focused on happiness or, more generally, on well- being.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Was No Eudaimonist
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-14-2008 Sextus was no Eudaimonist Joseph B. Bullock Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bullock, Joseph B., "Sextus was no Eudaimonist." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2008. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/40 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SEXTUS WAS NO EUDAIMONIST by JOSEPH B. BULLOCK Under the Direction of Dr. Tim O’Keefe ABSTRACT Ancient Greek philosophical schools are said to share a common structure in their ethical theories which is characterized by a eudaimonistic teleology based in an understanding of human nature. At first glance, the skepticism of Sextus Empiricus as described in the Outlines of Pyrrhonism seems to fit into this model insofar as he describes the end of the skeptic as ataraxia, a common account of the expression of human happiness. I argue that this is a misunderstanding of Sextus’s philosophy for several reasons. “The end of skepticism” cannot be eudaimonistic or teleological in the way that other ancient ethical theories are typically understood; moreover, ataraxia is not an end derived from a theory about human nature. For these reasons, the skeptical way of life is radically different than the ethical theories proposed by other schools. I argue that this difference is a result of the character of the skeptical enterprise which involves the implicit rejection of norms in both the epistemological and the ethical spheres.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI515: Special Topics in the History of Philosophy Fall 2020 Benjamin Morison the Scepticism of Sextus Empiricus, and Against the Ethicists
    PHI515: Special Topics in the History of Philosophy Fall 2020 Benjamin Morison The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus, and Against the Ethicists This course aims to give students an overview of the scepticism of the 2nd Century AD Pyrrhonist philosopher, Sextus Empiricus, after which we will read in detail parts of his treatise Against the Ethicists (also known as Adversus Mathematicos (M) XI). In the first half of semester, we will be looking at extracts from Sextus’ ‘manifesto’ of Pyrrhonism, Outlines of Pyrrhonism (PH) book I, in order to get a good idea of the basics of his distinctive brand of scepticism. We will be reading Against the Ethicists in the light of that manifesto; recent scholars have argued that the scepticism at work in Against the Ethicists is different from the ‘official’ scepticism of PH I. Provisional list of topics/texts to be discussed: 4th September Introduction to Sextus Empiricus, his works, book I of the Outlines of Pyrrhonism overview, and §§1-7; Against the Ethicists Bibliography (5), (6) 11th September The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (1): PH I §§8-12 (Scepticism as an ability) 18th September The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (2): PH I §§13-20 (The beliefs of the sceptic) Bibliography (7), (8) 25th September The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (3): PH I §§21-30 (The life and aims of the sceptic) Bibliography (12), (13) 2nd October The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (4): PH I §§31-186, esp. §§31-35 (The modes of scepticism) Bibliography (9), (10) 9th October The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (5): PH I §§187-209, esp.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonism Or Academic Skepticism? Friedrich Wilhelm Bierling's
    SKÉPSIS, ANO VII, Nº 10, 2014. 128 PYRRHONISM OR ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM? FRIEDRICH WILHELM BIERLING’S ‘REASONABLE DOUBT’ IN THE COMMENTATIO DE PYRRHONISMO HISTORICO (1724) ANTON MATYTSIN (Stanford University). E-mail: [email protected] Following the revival of ancient skepticism in early-modern Europe, debates about the possibility of obtaining true and certain knowledge of the world took place not only in metaphysics and in the natural sciences, but also in history and other humanities. While seeking to comprehend their own place in the process of historical development, 18th-century historians attempted to reconsider the nature and the purpose of historical writing, in general. Simultaneously, historical scholarship drew critiques from new sources. Cartesians, Deists, and philosophical skeptics posed challenges to the reliability of the discipline. Even antiquarian scholars, influenced by the humanist tradition, began to doubt the veracity of ancient histories due to the paucity of documentary evidence and to the alleged unreliability of reputed authors such as Livy, Dionysius of Halicarnassus, and Plutarch. Consequently scholars began to re-examine their sources as they sought new foundations for true and certain historical knowledge. Despite the increasingly acerbic nature of these debates, some thinkers argued that a middle ground between extreme Pyrrhonian skepticism and complete moral certainty about all historical facts was possible. One such attempt to integrate skeptical critiques with traditional historical methods and to rehabilitate Pyrrhonism in the eyes of the learned community was provided by the German scholar Friedrich Wilhelm Bierling (1676-1728). A professor of philosophy and theology at the University of Rinteln and an active correspondent of Leibnitz on the very question of historical certainty, Bierling offered both a novel approach to the study and writing of history and a unique interpretation of the varieties of philosophical skepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Rainer Hirsch-Luipold, Reinhard Feldmeier und Heinz-Günther Nesselrath unter der Mitarbeit von Natalia Pedrique und Andrea Villani Band XXV Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius Introduction, Text, Translation, Commentary and Interpretative Essays by Katja Maria Vogt, Richard Bett, Lorenzo Corti, Tiziano Dorandi, Christiana M. M. Olfert, Elisabeth Scharffenberger, David Sedley, and James Warren edited by Katja Maria Vogt Mohr Siebeck SAPERE is a Project of the Göttingen Academy of Sciences and Humanities within the programme of the Union of the German Academies funded by the Federal Republic of Germany and the State of Lower Saxony. e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156430-7 ISBN 978-3-16-153336-5 The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio nal- bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http:// dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. www.mohr.de This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This ap- plies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and pro- cessing in electronic systems. This book was supervised by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath (representing the SAPERE Editors) and typeset by Magdalena Albrecht, Janjenka Szillat and Andrea Villani at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen. Printed by Gulde Druck in Tübin- gen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Inversion of Zeno
    Leibniz’s Inversion of Zeno: Continuity of Motion, Substantial Action and Plurality1 R. T. W. Arthur Dept. of Philosophy Middlebury College Vermont, USA [email protected] 1 This paper was read at the workshop on Corporeal Substances and the Labyrinth of the Continuum, Università di Firenze, November 30, 2000. I am indebted to several of the participants for their helpful comments, and to Sam Levey, both in general for a long and invaluable correspondence on matters Leibnizian, and in particular for insightful comments on the final draft. Leibniz’s Inversion of Zeno 2 Itaque actio in corpore non nisi per aversionem quandam intelligi potest. Si vero ad vivum reseces, seu si momentum unumquodque inspicias, nulla est. Hinc sequitur Actiones proprias et momentaneas, earum esse rerum quae agendo non mutantur. (A VI.iii 566)2 In what follows I shall attempt to shed light on both the main themes of this volume by considering the relationship of Leibniz’s views to Zeno’s Paradoxes. I do not mean to suggest that Leibniz formulated his views as explicit responses to Zeno of Elea’s famous arguments against motion and plurality (it is probably more accurate to see him as responding to the whole tradition of thought prompted by them, from Plato and Aristotle through Sextus Empiricus and the Scholastics to Galileo Galilei and the moderns). Nevertheless I believe a direct comparison of the two is informative. For I think that in his treatment of the problems of continuous motion and plurality Leibniz employs a characteristic style of arguing—an argument schema—which can usefully be regarded as an inversion of Zeno’s typical way of reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Doing Things with Concepts in Sextus Empiricus Richard Bett, Johns Hopkins University
    Doing Things with Concepts in Sextus Empiricus Richard Bett, Johns Hopkins University What concepts are is the subject of lively and continuing debate. Are they in our heads, and if so, what form do they take? Or are they abstract objects – Fregean senses, for example, or “the constituents of propositions”1 – with which we somehow interact in our speech and thought? Do they vary from person to person? And should we draw a definite distinction between the concept of X, understood as relatively unified and stable, and various different conceptions of X, which “are thought to be more ephemeral and idiosyncratic than concepts”2? These are some of the many questions in this area, the answers to which may affect, or be affected by, our most basic commitments in the philosophy of mind and language. Fortunately, we need not worry about any of these deep and difficult questions, because we are dealing with Sextus Empiricus, who, as a Pyrrhonian sceptic, does not adopt philosophical theories, whether about the nature of concepts or about anything else. But these contested matters are nonetheless worth mentioning, if only to indicate that the territory we are dealing with under the heading of “concepts” is somewhat indeterminate. For an author like Sextus who not only eschews theory, but also deliberately avoids what he considers over-precision in the use of language (PH 1.207, cf. 1.17, 1.191), this is perhaps only appropriate. There is in fact quite a lot in Sextus that can naturally be seen as addressing the topic of concepts. There are four or five relevant terms in his texts that either 1 Margolis and Laurence 2011, 1.3.
    [Show full text]