Non-Assertoric Discourse Plato Sextus Empiricus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Non-Assertoric Discourse Plato Sextus Empiricus Non-assertoric Discourse: Plato, Sextus Empiricus and Wittgenstein Yung Yeuk-Yu Doctor of Philosophy The University of East Anglia School of Philosophy June 2012 © This copy of the thesis has been supplied on condition that anyone who consults it is understood to recognise that its copyright rests with the author and that no quotation from the thesis, nor any information derived therefrom, may be published without the author’s prior, written consent. 1 Contents Preface …...…………….….…………………………………………………..p.5 Acknowledgements…..…...……………………………………………………p.6 Introduction……………..………………….....………...……………………..p.8 CHAPTER ONE DOING PHILOSOPHY: THE ASSERTORIC WAY AND THE NON-ASSERTORIC WAY……….p.13 1. Assertoric Discourse: A Familiar Model Across Several Traditions......p.14 1.1 Three Examples of Assertoric Mode of Discourse....…………….p.15 1.2 Conclusion….…………………………………………………….p.20 2. What Is It To Make An Assertion?..........................................................p.23 2.1 Metaphor and Truth….……………………………………………p.28 2.2 Fictional Discourse and Truth…..….……………………………..p.36 3. Doing Philosophy in Non-assertoric Discourse: A Less Familiar Model……………...……………………………p.40 CHAPTER TWO PUZZLES IN THE SUN, LINE AND CAVE: A CASE STUDY IN READING PLATO’S IMAGERY…...…………….…p.42 1. Two Assertoric Ways of Reading the Material 1.1 Scholars who take it to be illustration…….………………………p.43 1.2 Scholars who take it to be argument……………….……………..p.47 1.3 Scholars who offer a more sophisticated view…..……………….p.52 2. Six Key Problems with the Line and its Problematic Integration with the Other Images 2.1 Should the Line be drawn vertical or horizontal?..........................p.54 2.2 Should the larger segment be made at the top or the bottom?.......p.56 2 2.3 Is the equality of the two middle subsegments for thought ( dianoia ) and trust ( pistis ) a matter of importance or an irrelevant consequence originated in the proportion of the Line?.......................................p.58 2.4 What kind of things should we find in the subsegment for thought (dianoia )?.....................................................................p.62 2.5 What should be the meaning of eikasia ?.........................................p.66 2.6 How does the philosophical method proceed to an unhypothetical first principle (arch ē) and then finish with knowledge?.................p.70 2.7 How do the stages on the Line integrate with the stages in the Cave?....................................................................p.74 3. Must We Adopt These Assertoric Ways of Reading the Material?........p.77 3.1 Giving Up the Assertoric Ways of Reading……........……………p.79 3.2 Fiction and Authorial Silence..…..………………………………..p.82 3.2.1 The Voice of Socrates as the Authorial Voice: Rowe’s ‘two voices reading’……………………………………...p.87 3.2.2 Hidden Voice Readings: Kahn’s Ingressive Interpretation and Cornford’s Reading…...…..p.88 3.2.3 Whether Any Voice is the Voice of the Author…….…………....p.91 3.3 The Elenctic Mode of Argumentation….……..………….……….p.97 4. Conclusion……….…………………………………………………...p.100 CHAPTER THREE THE PROBLEMS OF INCOHERENCE : A CASE STUDY IN SEXTUS EMPIRICUS’S WRITING..…….…..……p.103 1. Sextus Empiricus’s Writing and Its Problematic Status 1.1 Writing and the Problems of Incoherence in the Pyrrhonian Tradition……...……………………………....p.109 1.2 Two Forms of Pyrrhonism…….…...…………………………....p.115 1.3 The Problematic Status of Sextus’s Writing: Implications and Defences…...…………………………….p.121 2. Pyrrhonian Non-Assertoric Speech…….…….……………………….p.133 2.1 The Attitudes of Aphasia ……..………………………………….p.134 2.2 The Plea of Katachr ēsis for Pyrrhonian Avowal of Appearance..p.138 3 2.3 Philosophical Phainetai Pronouncement and Belief…….......….p.144 2.4 Sceptical Phōnai and the deep grammar of Ou(den) mallon …....p.152 3. Dissoi Logoi : Misology and the Premature Dialectician……….....….p.158 3.1 The Premature Dialectician………….…………………..………p.163 3.2 Objections to Annas’s Views………..…………………………..p.166 3.3 The Misologist…..……………………………..……...………....p.170 CHAPTER FOUR A CASE STUDY IN WITTGENSTEIN’S TRACTATUS AND THE PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS ….……..p.176 1. The Tractatus and the Aim of Elucidation………………...…………p.177 1.1 The Cardinal Problem of Philosophy: the Distinction between What can be Said and What can only be Shown….…….…p.178 1.1.1 Russell’s Reading of the Tractatus …………………………..….p.179 1.1.2 Kenny’s Reading of the Tractatus ………………………………p.185 1.1.3 Fogelin’s Reading of the Tractatus …………………….………..p.189 1.2 The Spirit of Non-assertion and the Textual Strategy of the Tractatus ……………………………………….....…p.198 1.2.1 Frege’s Reading of the Tractatus : Form over Content?..............p.199 1.2.2 Resolute Readings of the Tractatus ………………………..……p.203 2. The Philosophical Investigations …………..………...………………..p.211 2.1.1 Dialogue in the Philosophical Investigations ………..…………..p.212 2.1.2 Dialogue as a Vehicle and the ‘intended upshot’ of reading the Philosophical Investigations ……...…….……...………p.221 2.2 The Anti-doctrinal Character and Therapeutic Nature of the Philosophical Investigations ………..………………p.227 2.2.1 The Two-voice Assumption and the Mouthpiece Assumption…p.228 2.2.2 The Character and Methods of the Philosophical Investigations .p.237 CONCLUSION………………………………………….………..……p.252 BIBLIOGRAPHY…………………………………….…………..……p.256 4 Preface All Greek words in the text are transliterated, even in direct quotations from modern authors where the original quoted words in Greek script. The translations of Sextus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism quoted in the text are drawn from Benson Mates, The Skeptic Way (New York and Oxford, 1995). I have also consulted Annas and Barnes, Sextus Empiricus: Outlines of Scepticism (Cambridge and New York, 2000). I use ‘Pyrrhonist’ and ‘sceptic’ interchangeably. When I refer to Sextus’s writings in the text, I use PH as an abbreviation for the Outlines of Pyrrhonism and M as an abbreviation for Against the Mathematicians , followed by book and section number. When I quote from Wittgenstein in the text I use T as an abbreviation for the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus followed by section number and PI as an abbreviation for the Philosophical Investigations followed by section number. The length of this thesis is 80975 words 5 Acknowledgements My deepest gratitude goes to Professor Catherine Rowett for her valuable advice and generous support since I began working on this thesis in 2005. My sincere gratitude goes to my secondary supervisors Dr Rupert Read and Dr Oskari Kuusela for their beneficial advice and help. I would like to thank my examiners Dr Mark Rowe and Dr Luca Castagnoli for their engaging and detailed recommendations for improving my work. I am responsible for any remaining shortcomings and mistakes this thesis may contain. I would also like to thank Dr Sean Mcconnell who proofread some of the chapters and Ms Mavis Reynolds from the office of the School of Philosophy for her assistance with the submission in 2010. 6 To My Mother And In Memory of My Father 7 INTORDUCTION DOING PHILOSPHY IN WORDS This thesis addresses fundamental issues about the very nature of philosophy by exploring the philosophical writings and methods of Plato, Sextus Empiricus and Wittgenstein under the framework of a special mode of doing philosophy that does not result in theory or doctrine. Philosophy is a self-reflective discipline and philosophical writings naturally fall within the scope of its field of study since the antique. We should recall the famous statement that ‘there is an old quarrel between philosophy and poetry’ in Plato’s Republic (607b5-6) and the various discussions of rhetoric and poetry in the Ion , Republic , Gorgias and the Phaedrus . In the modern time, the philosophical importance of the dialogue form, orality, authorial anonymity and silence, dramatic techniques, irony and humour, the fables, myths and stories used in Plato’s writing has gained increasing attention in Platonic scholarship. 1 Moreover contemporary philosophers also begin to take film seriously as a new subject for philosophical investigation (films as philosophy) and also a new form of philosophical medium (the philosophy of film). 2 These ongoing and 1 See for instance Arieti 1991, Clay 2000, Farness 1991, Fendt and Rozema 1998, Hart and Tejera 1997, Klagge and Smith 1992, and also Press 1993 and 2000. The discussion on Plato in this thesis should join force with this growing trend. 2 See for instance Cavell 1979a and 1995, Falzon 2002, Frampton 2006, Freeland and Wartenberg 1995, Livingston 2009, Read and Goodenough 2005. 8 spreading interests in philosophical writing, methods, and new media reflect the critical and self-examining dimension of philosophy. This thesis investigates the philosophical and interpretive challenges posed by the distinctive language-uses, as well as the unique styles and methods of Plato, Sextus and Wittgenstein. The novelty of this thesis lies in its attempt to apply the idea of non-assertoric discourse in a close examination of a wide and disparate philosophical writings by three major philosophers from different schools of thought and traditions. In general, language can be put to different kinds of use and the same sentence-type can perform different speech acts. The force of my utterance may not be given in the form of my utterance and the relationship between the words being used and their illocutionary points is often oblique. All these can have crucial implications on how we should approach a philosophical text if we want to achieve a more sophisticated and sensitive reading. For instance, because
Recommended publications
  • The Liar Paradox As a Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument Menashe Schwed Ashkelon Academic College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Schwed, Menashe, "The Liar Paradox as a reductio ad absurdum argument" (1999). OSSA Conference Archive. 48. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA3/papersandcommentaries/48 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Title: The Liar Paradox as a Reductio ad Absurdum Author: Menashe Schwed Response to this paper by: Lawrence Powers (c)2000 Menashe Schwed 1. Introduction The paper discusses two seemingly separated topics: the origin and function of the Liar Paradox in ancient Greek philosophy and the Reduction ad absurdum mode of argumentation. Its goal is to show how the two topics fit together and why they are closely connected. The accepted tradition is that Eubulides of Miletos was the first to formulate the Liar Paradox correctly and that the paradox was part of the philosophical discussion of the Megarian School. Which version of the paradox was formulated by Eubulides is unknown, but according to some hints given by Aristotle and an incorrect version given by Cicero1, the version was probably as follows: The paradox is created from the Liar sentence ‘I am lying’.
    [Show full text]
  • Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Title: Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism Author: Dariusz Kubok Citation style: Kubok Dariusz. (2015). Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism. "Folia Philosophica" (T. 34 (2015), s. 9-31). Folia Philosophica 34 ISSN 2353-9445 (online) ISSN 1231-0913 (print) Dariusz Kubok Comments on the Sources of Greek Philosophical Criticism Abstract: The present article attempts to shed light on the sources of philosophi- cal criticism of early Greece and on the origins of the critical attitude adopted by the thinkers of the period. Above all, however, reflections presented hereby are meant to serve as a backdrop for analyses of a much broader scope. The study seeks to identify the defining characteristics of early Greek criticism, upon which basis the author puts forth a proposition for a general typology of its forms. Complement- ing the present comments is a brief discussion of the suggested types of philosophical criticism in light of the views of some of the leading philosophers of the time. Keywords: early Greek philosophy, critical thinking, criticism, skepticism, typology There is universal agreement that a critical approach is the main force pushing human thought forward, and that criticism, as an attribute of thought, must be an essential element of rational reflection on real- ity. A deficit of criticism leads not only to stagnation in scholarship and science, but also to the appearance of various forms of dogmatism, which do not permit the emergence of alternative views, nor the revi- sion of positions acknowledged as final.
    [Show full text]
  • Humor As Philosophical Subversion, Especially in the Skeptics
    Humor as Philosophical Subversion, Especially in the Skeptics Richard Bett 1. Introduction Aristotle is not exactly a comedian. He wrote about comedy in the lost second book of the Poetics, and, as discussed in another paper in this volume, he wrote about wittiness (εὐτραπελία) in his ethical works. But he does not exhibit much of either. What humor there is in Aristotle seems to fall into two main varieties. First, there is word-play that engages the reader’s attention, which can perhaps be seen as an instance of a technique he describes in Rhetoric 3.10, that of saying “smart things and things that create a good impression” (τὰ ἀστεῖα καὶ τὰ εὐδοκιµοῦντα, 1410b6).1 Early in the Nicomachean Ethics, he says that in endeavoring to determine the principles (ἀρχαί) of ethics, we should begin (ἀρκτέον) with things known to us (1095b2-4). A little later, introducing the idea of the function (ἔργον) of a human being, he asks whether we can seriously consider that a human being as such (as opposed to people in various occupations) is ἀργόν (1097b28- 30) – which is intentionally ambiguous between “without function” and “lazy.” In De Caelo, introducing the topic of minimal magnitudes, he says that positing such a minimal magnitude (τοὐλάχιστον) will make the biggest difference (τὰ µέγιστα) in mathematics (271b10-11). And in De Interpretatione, discussing names, he says that “non-human 1 Unless otherwise noted, translations are my own. In the case of Timon, I sometimes draw on translations in Bett 2000 and Bett 2015. In the case of Sextus I generally draw on Bett 1997, Bett 2005, and Bett 2012.
    [Show full text]
  • Or Not to Be(Lieve)? (Skepticism & Inner Peace)
    To Be(lieve) or Not to Be(lieve)? (skepticism & inner peace) 1. Ataraxia: Happiness in Skepticism: The ancient philosophers believed that there was happiness in wisdom. If we pursued truth, we would be happy. In their pursuit of Truth and Happiness, the ancient skeptics (e.g., Pyrrho of Elis, ~300 BC ; Sextus Empiricus, ~200 AD) noticed that, for pretty much any issue, a good argument could be presented for BOTH sides. Famously, the skeptic Carneades gave a public speech commending justice and our understanding of it, only to give, the very next day, a speech refuting everything he’d said the day before! (Antithesis) The result is that we have no rational basis for believing one side rather than the other, since both are equally well-supported. (Equipollence) Therefore, we must remain agnostic, suspending belief. (Epoché) The result was interesting: By suspending belief, they achieved a state of inner peace and tranquility! (Ataraxia) It was their very dissatisfaction during their quest for happiness and truth which led the first skeptics to discover the true way to happiness. Sextus Empiricus tells a story: Indeed, what happened to the Skeptic is just like what is told of Apelles the painter. For it is said that once upon a time, when he was painting a horse and wished to depict the horse’s froth, he failed so completely that he gave up and threw his sponge at the picture – the sponge on which he used to wipe the paints from his brush – and that in striking the picture the sponge produced the desired effect.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Empiricus and the Scientific Scepticism
    ENCEPHALOS 50, 62-74, 2013 SEXTUS EMPIRICUS AND THE SCIENTIFIC SCEPTI- CISM STAVROS J.BALOYANNIS* Summary philosophical books, which survived, but remained for long in obscurity, been rediscovered in the late Renaissance. Two Sextus Empiricus is the most eminent representative of these works on the title, “Adversus Mathematikus”, include of the ancient sceptisism, which is a Post-Classical, Hellenis- large number of strong arguments against the Logicians, the tic philosophy based on the criterion of life, the experience Physicists and the Ethicists. The third and most important of and the analysis of phenomena, aiming to provide a straight the books on the title “Outlines of Pyrrhonism” provides an out- and practical way of life, leading to interior peace and mental line of Pyrrhonian scepticism, incorporating at the same time tranquility, sharply opposed to a purely theoretical pursuit of his own philosophical doctrines. Sextus offers thoroughly a dogmatic philosophy. The term “sceptic” is a derivative of the general overview of scepticism, describing and explaining the noun, skepsis (σκέψις), which means thought, examination, meaning of the sceptical investigation, the value of suspen- inquiry, consideration, meditation and investigation. The scep- sion of judgment and the importance of the sceptical dialectics. tical school was connected for a long period of time with the Sextus insists that the skepticism does not accept or reject any Empirical school of physicians, who based the good medical impression and substantially does not affirm or deny anything. practice on the clinical experience rather than on the theoret- Sextus claims that appearances (φαινόμενα) are the practical ical erudition, dedicating themselves to observation, memory criteria of approaching to the truth and by the continuous inves- and continuous clinical practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Can an Ancient Greek Sceptic Be Eudaimôn (Or Happy)? and What Difference Does the Answer Make to Us?
    Journal of Ancient Philosophy Vol. VI 2012 Issue 1 Can an ancient Greek sceptic be eudaimôn (or happy)? And what difference does the answer make to us? Richard Bett (Johns Hopkins University) The paper explores how far the ancient Greek sceptics in fact accept, and how far they should accept, the central Greek ethical notion of eudaimonia , usually translated "happiness" - and what, if anything, the answers may tell us today. The first section shows that sceptics of both the Academic and Pyrrhonist traditions frequently employ the notion of eudaimonia , apparently without discomfort. The second section draws attention to a contrast within the relevant works of Sextus Empiricus - one of them being willing to speak of the sceptic's eudaimonia and the other entirely avoiding this - and considers some possible reasons why, at some point in his life, Sextus might have found the notion problematic. The answers suggested are, first, that the term eudaimonia , at least as normally used by non-sceptical philosophers, presupposes that it is possible to rank human lives objectively in terms of their levels of well-being, and second, that the term standardly carries with it a commitment to a certain kind of long-term structure in one's life; there is at least a serious question whether either of these is consistent with sceptical suspension of judgement. The third section examines how far a sceptic could aspire to happiness , where this is not assumed to be equivalent to eudaimonia , and touches on several modern philosophers who have focused on happiness or, more generally, on well- being.
    [Show full text]
  • Sextus Was No Eudaimonist
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-14-2008 Sextus was no Eudaimonist Joseph B. Bullock Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bullock, Joseph B., "Sextus was no Eudaimonist." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2008. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/40 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SEXTUS WAS NO EUDAIMONIST by JOSEPH B. BULLOCK Under the Direction of Dr. Tim O’Keefe ABSTRACT Ancient Greek philosophical schools are said to share a common structure in their ethical theories which is characterized by a eudaimonistic teleology based in an understanding of human nature. At first glance, the skepticism of Sextus Empiricus as described in the Outlines of Pyrrhonism seems to fit into this model insofar as he describes the end of the skeptic as ataraxia, a common account of the expression of human happiness. I argue that this is a misunderstanding of Sextus’s philosophy for several reasons. “The end of skepticism” cannot be eudaimonistic or teleological in the way that other ancient ethical theories are typically understood; moreover, ataraxia is not an end derived from a theory about human nature. For these reasons, the skeptical way of life is radically different than the ethical theories proposed by other schools. I argue that this difference is a result of the character of the skeptical enterprise which involves the implicit rejection of norms in both the epistemological and the ethical spheres.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI515: Special Topics in the History of Philosophy Fall 2020 Benjamin Morison the Scepticism of Sextus Empiricus, and Against the Ethicists
    PHI515: Special Topics in the History of Philosophy Fall 2020 Benjamin Morison The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus, and Against the Ethicists This course aims to give students an overview of the scepticism of the 2nd Century AD Pyrrhonist philosopher, Sextus Empiricus, after which we will read in detail parts of his treatise Against the Ethicists (also known as Adversus Mathematicos (M) XI). In the first half of semester, we will be looking at extracts from Sextus’ ‘manifesto’ of Pyrrhonism, Outlines of Pyrrhonism (PH) book I, in order to get a good idea of the basics of his distinctive brand of scepticism. We will be reading Against the Ethicists in the light of that manifesto; recent scholars have argued that the scepticism at work in Against the Ethicists is different from the ‘official’ scepticism of PH I. Provisional list of topics/texts to be discussed: 4th September Introduction to Sextus Empiricus, his works, book I of the Outlines of Pyrrhonism overview, and §§1-7; Against the Ethicists Bibliography (5), (6) 11th September The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (1): PH I §§8-12 (Scepticism as an ability) 18th September The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (2): PH I §§13-20 (The beliefs of the sceptic) Bibliography (7), (8) 25th September The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (3): PH I §§21-30 (The life and aims of the sceptic) Bibliography (12), (13) 2nd October The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (4): PH I §§31-186, esp. §§31-35 (The modes of scepticism) Bibliography (9), (10) 9th October The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus (5): PH I §§187-209, esp.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonism Or Academic Skepticism? Friedrich Wilhelm Bierling's
    SKÉPSIS, ANO VII, Nº 10, 2014. 128 PYRRHONISM OR ACADEMIC SKEPTICISM? FRIEDRICH WILHELM BIERLING’S ‘REASONABLE DOUBT’ IN THE COMMENTATIO DE PYRRHONISMO HISTORICO (1724) ANTON MATYTSIN (Stanford University). E-mail: [email protected] Following the revival of ancient skepticism in early-modern Europe, debates about the possibility of obtaining true and certain knowledge of the world took place not only in metaphysics and in the natural sciences, but also in history and other humanities. While seeking to comprehend their own place in the process of historical development, 18th-century historians attempted to reconsider the nature and the purpose of historical writing, in general. Simultaneously, historical scholarship drew critiques from new sources. Cartesians, Deists, and philosophical skeptics posed challenges to the reliability of the discipline. Even antiquarian scholars, influenced by the humanist tradition, began to doubt the veracity of ancient histories due to the paucity of documentary evidence and to the alleged unreliability of reputed authors such as Livy, Dionysius of Halicarnassus, and Plutarch. Consequently scholars began to re-examine their sources as they sought new foundations for true and certain historical knowledge. Despite the increasingly acerbic nature of these debates, some thinkers argued that a middle ground between extreme Pyrrhonian skepticism and complete moral certainty about all historical facts was possible. One such attempt to integrate skeptical critiques with traditional historical methods and to rehabilitate Pyrrhonism in the eyes of the learned community was provided by the German scholar Friedrich Wilhelm Bierling (1676-1728). A professor of philosophy and theology at the University of Rinteln and an active correspondent of Leibnitz on the very question of historical certainty, Bierling offered both a novel approach to the study and writing of history and a unique interpretation of the varieties of philosophical skepticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Rainer Hirsch-Luipold, Reinhard Feldmeier und Heinz-Günther Nesselrath unter der Mitarbeit von Natalia Pedrique und Andrea Villani Band XXV Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius Introduction, Text, Translation, Commentary and Interpretative Essays by Katja Maria Vogt, Richard Bett, Lorenzo Corti, Tiziano Dorandi, Christiana M. M. Olfert, Elisabeth Scharffenberger, David Sedley, and James Warren edited by Katja Maria Vogt Mohr Siebeck SAPERE is a Project of the Göttingen Academy of Sciences and Humanities within the programme of the Union of the German Academies funded by the Federal Republic of Germany and the State of Lower Saxony. e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156430-7 ISBN 978-3-16-153336-5 The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio nal- bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http:// dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. www.mohr.de This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This ap- plies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and pro- cessing in electronic systems. This book was supervised by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath (representing the SAPERE Editors) and typeset by Magdalena Albrecht, Janjenka Szillat and Andrea Villani at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen. Printed by Gulde Druck in Tübin- gen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Inversion of Zeno
    Leibniz’s Inversion of Zeno: Continuity of Motion, Substantial Action and Plurality1 R. T. W. Arthur Dept. of Philosophy Middlebury College Vermont, USA [email protected] 1 This paper was read at the workshop on Corporeal Substances and the Labyrinth of the Continuum, Università di Firenze, November 30, 2000. I am indebted to several of the participants for their helpful comments, and to Sam Levey, both in general for a long and invaluable correspondence on matters Leibnizian, and in particular for insightful comments on the final draft. Leibniz’s Inversion of Zeno 2 Itaque actio in corpore non nisi per aversionem quandam intelligi potest. Si vero ad vivum reseces, seu si momentum unumquodque inspicias, nulla est. Hinc sequitur Actiones proprias et momentaneas, earum esse rerum quae agendo non mutantur. (A VI.iii 566)2 In what follows I shall attempt to shed light on both the main themes of this volume by considering the relationship of Leibniz’s views to Zeno’s Paradoxes. I do not mean to suggest that Leibniz formulated his views as explicit responses to Zeno of Elea’s famous arguments against motion and plurality (it is probably more accurate to see him as responding to the whole tradition of thought prompted by them, from Plato and Aristotle through Sextus Empiricus and the Scholastics to Galileo Galilei and the moderns). Nevertheless I believe a direct comparison of the two is informative. For I think that in his treatment of the problems of continuous motion and plurality Leibniz employs a characteristic style of arguing—an argument schema—which can usefully be regarded as an inversion of Zeno’s typical way of reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Doing Things with Concepts in Sextus Empiricus Richard Bett, Johns Hopkins University
    Doing Things with Concepts in Sextus Empiricus Richard Bett, Johns Hopkins University What concepts are is the subject of lively and continuing debate. Are they in our heads, and if so, what form do they take? Or are they abstract objects – Fregean senses, for example, or “the constituents of propositions”1 – with which we somehow interact in our speech and thought? Do they vary from person to person? And should we draw a definite distinction between the concept of X, understood as relatively unified and stable, and various different conceptions of X, which “are thought to be more ephemeral and idiosyncratic than concepts”2? These are some of the many questions in this area, the answers to which may affect, or be affected by, our most basic commitments in the philosophy of mind and language. Fortunately, we need not worry about any of these deep and difficult questions, because we are dealing with Sextus Empiricus, who, as a Pyrrhonian sceptic, does not adopt philosophical theories, whether about the nature of concepts or about anything else. But these contested matters are nonetheless worth mentioning, if only to indicate that the territory we are dealing with under the heading of “concepts” is somewhat indeterminate. For an author like Sextus who not only eschews theory, but also deliberately avoids what he considers over-precision in the use of language (PH 1.207, cf. 1.17, 1.191), this is perhaps only appropriate. There is in fact quite a lot in Sextus that can naturally be seen as addressing the topic of concepts. There are four or five relevant terms in his texts that either 1 Margolis and Laurence 2011, 1.3.
    [Show full text]