The Relationship Between Materialism and Self-Transcendence in University Students Sample

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Relationship Between Materialism and Self-Transcendence in University Students Sample 02-relation between mate#AE5FE4 15/3/13 11:52 Page 13 ARAfiTIRMA/RESEARCH The Relationship Between Materialism and Self-Transcendence in University Students Sample Cemal Can Fatih University Institute of Social Sciences Master of Arts in Psychology Adres: Sincan Kaymakaml›¤› Sosyal Yard›mlaflma ve Dayan›flma Vakf› Hükümet Kona¤›, 06930 Sincan ANKARA Tel: +905303635419, Fax: +903122718584 E-Mail: [email protected] Special Thanks: I would like to thank my advisor Professor Kemal SAYAR for his generous and never ending support, intuition and inspiration. I am honestly grateful to Assistant Professor Samet KÖSE from Vanderbilt University for motivating me and guiding me with his suggestions and knowledge. This thesis would not have been possible without their contributions. ABSTRACT Purpose: A basic debate that has been frequently discussed is whether humankinds searching for happiness through material good is good or a bad thing. Many people wonder if more money, more leisure or more stuff would make them happier. In recent years number of studies has examined the relationship between materialism and well-being and there are some evidences that materialism is related to personality. Method: In this study, 143 university students completed a battery of questionnaires including Richins and Dawson’s material values scale, and Cloninger’s Temperament and Character Inventory, Beck depression in- ventory, hopelessness scale and empathy quotient scale. Findings: Even though there is not a significant correlation between total self transcendence scores and ma- terialism scores; there is a significant negative correlation between the total materialism scores and the trans- personal identification facet of self transcendence (r =-.20, p<.05). There is also significant negative correla- tion between the transpersonal identification and the materialistic happiness (r =-.22, p<.01). Discussion and Conclusion: Another result of the study is that the students who have relatively high ma- terialism scores are likely to have low empathy scores. Keywords: materialism, well-being, personality, TCI, Cloninger’s psychobiological model ÖZET Üniversite Ö¤rencileri Örnekleminde Kendini Aflk›nl›k ve Maddiyatç›l›k ‹liflkisi Amaç: ‹nsanlar›n mutluk için maddi ç›karlar›n peflinde koflmas›n›n do¤ru olup olmad›¤› öteden beri tart›fl›la- gelmifltir. Ço¤u insan, daha çok mal-mülk sâhibi olmak, daha fazla bofl vakit geçirmek veya daha fazla çal›fl- mak konusunda karars›zd›r. Son zamanlarda maddiyatç›l›k ile esenlik aras›ndaki iliflkiyi inceleyen pek çok arafl- t›rma yap›lm›flt›r ve kiflilik özelliklerinin maddiyatç›l›k ve esenlik aras›ndaki iliflkide önemli belirleyicilerden ol- du¤u gösterilmifltir. Yöntem: Bu çal›flmada, 143 üniversite ö¤renci Richins ve Dawson’un maddiyatç›l›k ölçe¤ini ve Cloninger’in karakter ve mizaç envanterinin alt ölçe¤i olan kendini aflk›nl›k altölçe¤ini içeren kapsaml› bir soru formunu doldurdu. Bulgular: Kendini aflk›nl›k boyutu ile maddiyatç›l›k puanlar› aras›nda anlaml› bir iliflki bulunamamas›na ra¤- men, kendini aflk›nl›k boyutunun alt ölçeklerinden olan kiflileraras› özdeflim puanlar› ile maddiyatç›l›k puan- lar› aras›nda olumsuz iliflki gözlenmifltir (r=-.20, p<.05). Tart›flma ve Sonuç: Araflt›rman›n di¤er bir sonucu olarak maddiyatç›l›k puanlar› görece yüksek olanlar›n gö- rece düflük empati puan› ald›klar› gözlenmifltir (r=-.22, p<.01). Anahtar Kelimeler: maddiyatç›l›k, kiflilik, karakter, mizaç, Clonniger’in psikobiyoloyik modeli New/Yeni Symposium Journal • www.yenisymposium.net13 fiubat 2013 | Cilt 51 | Say› 1 02-relation between mate#AE5FE4 15/3/13 11:52 Page 14 INTRODUCTION siveness: “the inclination and tendency to retain cont- There is a huge amount of research concerning the rol or ownership of one’s possessions”, non-genero- historical investigation of human being for searching sity: “an unwillingness to give possessions to or sha- happiness through materialism. Researchers have tri- re possessions with others”, and envy: “desire for ot- ed to find out the reason that makes people happy, for hers possessions, be they objects, experiences or per- instance, is it money, leisure or working hard? sons”. He also found that a negative relationship bet- In United States, the homeland of materialism, ween materialism and happiness in life. Ger, Russell Myer (2000) reported that the number of people defi- and Belk (1990), reported interesting findings in their ned themselves as “very happy” had slightly declined cross-cultural studied implemented in Turkey, United between 1957 and 1998 and in this period the divorce States and France. They tested Belk’s materialism sca- rates doubled while teen suicide tripled. The argu- le and found that Turkish sample was the most mate- ment that higher income indicated higher happiness rialistic and most generous and most materialistic at was not always seemed to be true. Likewise, national the same time. This contradicts the view that materi- income per capita which is a standard measure for de- alism is a western phenomenon observed in develo- velopment of countries was 4322 USD in 1998 while it ped countries. was 10285 USD in 2008 in Turkey (TUIK, 2010). Altho- Materialism is defined by Csikszentmihaly (2005), ugh the statistics showed that people are getting ric- as the tendency to reserve most of the attention for her, it is questionable if they are getting happier. goals that include material goods like willingness to own them, consume them, or exhibit them. A person Materialism is materialist when he invests his psychic energy in In recent years, theoreticians and researchers from materialistic objects and their symbolic meanings we- different disciplines tried to understand the effect of alth, status, and power based on possessions. There- materialism on people, cultures and behaviors. The fore this person sees life mainly from the perspective relationship between materialism and life satisfaction of materialistic experiences. For a materialistic person had been examined in previous research. However, object is not just an object. This person aims to reach there were few studies which try to figure out the re- goals that begin with that object but pass beyond the lationship between materialism and personality. object itself. Owning an object doesn’t mean just ow- Materialism is defined in Macmillan Contempo- ning the functions of it but to use the object as a brid- rary Dictionary (1986), in two different ways. The ge to happy life. Csikszentmihaly has two description first meaning refers to a philosophical doctrine; of materialism in respect of its effects. Instrumental “everything that exists is either composed of matter materialism is relatively harmless form in which the or depends on matter for its existence”. The second person sees objects as necessary means for discove- definition refers to the popular use of the term; “ten- ring and improving personal values and strengthe- dency to be unduly concerned with material rather ning interpersonal relationships. Terminal materi- than intellectual or spiritual things”. alism on the other hand is a potentially destructive Although the popular meaning of materialism is form in which the desire for more possessions run out different from philosophical usage, Richins and Rud- of control and consumption mere goal is the con- min (1994) suggested that people who were materi- sumption itself and noting more. alistic mostly counted on physical (material) posses- Richins and Dawson (1992), defines materialism sions as a route to abstract constructs such as happi- as a value that is valid in a variety of situations and ness, status, and social competences. They thought not just consumption issues namely is a guide for they need to have “material good” to be happy. This person’s choices. Materialism as a value influences dependency on material objects reminds the philo- preferences of good purchased but it also influences sophical use of the term. the allocation of that person’s resources, including ti- Belk (1985) defines materialism as “the importan- me, money or labor. ce a consumer attaches to worldly possessions”. Such Four main specifications of materialistic people possessions are assumed that they have a central pla- are described by Richins and Dawson (1992). The va- ce in a person’s life at the highest levels of materi- luation to acquire wealth and possessions is signifi- alism. These possessions are the main source of satis- cantly higher for materialistic people than the others. faction and dissatisfaction. Secondly, materialistic people can be evaluated as According to Belk (1985), there are three main per- self-centered. Thirdly material complexity is an es- sonality traits related to materialistic people; posses- sential fact for materialist people which means that New/Yeni Symposium Journal • www.yenisymposium.net14 fiubat 2013 | Cilt 51 | Say› 1 02-relation between mate#AE5FE4 15/3/13 11:52 Page 15 materialist people over invest in material goods. Fi- ment is still a current consideration. As a matter of nally materialists can never be satisfied with what fact discretionary time management and incensement they have; they always want more and more. is an indication of being a developed country. This ti- Kasser and Ryan (1993) studied deeply the relative me and money supposed to be used as means to pur- importance of attaining financial goals comparative suit of happiness. But how will these resources lead to to other life domains. To measure the materialism happiness. According to Boven and Gilovich (2003) they developed a new scale taking into accounts this this has to be by the way of acquisition of life experi- relative importance, called ‘aspiration index’. These ences more than acquisition of more material goods. measures contained rating aspirations on their perso- In other words they put the old dilemma to be or to nal importance and the likelihood they will be reali- do as to do or to have. For them it is to do that leads zed. In their aspiration index they intended to inclu- to a “good life”.
Recommended publications
  • Critical Theory, Historical Materialism, and the Ostensible End of Marxism: the Poverty of Theory Revisited
    Critical Theory, Historical Materialism, and the Ostensible End of Marxism: The Poverty of Theory Revisited BRYAN D. PALMER Summary: This essay notes the extent to which poststructuralism/postmodernism have generally espoused hostility to historical materialism, surveys some representative examples of historical writing that have gravitated toward the new critical theory in opposition to Marxism, and closes with a discussion of the ironic evolution of a poststructurally inclined, anti-Marxist historiography. Counter to the prevailing ideological consensus that Marxism has been brought to its interpretive knees by a series of analytic challenges and the political collapse of the world's ostensibly "socialist" states, this essay argues that historical materialism has lost neither its power to interpret the past nor its relevance to the contemporary intellectual terrain. It is now a decade-and-one-half since Edward Thompson penned The Poverty of Theory: or an Orrery of Errors, and ten times as many years have passed since the publication of Marx's The Poverty of Philosophy.1 Whatever one may think about the advances in knowledge associated with historical materialism and Marxism, particularly in terms of the practice of historical writing, there is no denying that this sesquicentennial has been a problematic period in the making of communist society; the last fifteen years, moreover, are associated with the bleak end of socialism and the passing of Marxism as an intellectual force. Indeed, it is a curious conjuncture of our times that the
    [Show full text]
  • Materialism and Metaphysics Mcluhan Between Innis and Teilhard De Chardin
    Conference: Re-reading McLuhan Bayreuth, Feb. 2007 Hartmut Winkler Materialism and Metaphysics McLuhan between Innis and Teilhard de Chardin. translated by Michael Barchet 1 McLuhan Strictly speaking, my paper shall neither attempt a re-reading nor a novel interpretation of McLuhan. What I am rather interested in, however, is the specific direction media discourse took with McLuhan – especially since this direction is still vivid in our days. Although my paper starts with McLuhan, it actually takes the opposite way from the present back to McLuhan. Let me begin with an irritation. It has caught the attention of many, who have read McLuhan more carefully, and there are countless rather astonished comments: While Understanding Media in 1964 presents a point of view that is relaxed, easy going, ironic and utterly sympathetic with the media in a manner very much of this world, and also refuses for the most part to apply moral considerations, McLuhan’s first book about media, The Mechanical Bride made its points in 1951 by an explicitly judgemental, moral critique of the media.1 His second book made McLuhan more famous than The Mechanical Bride could have ever done, and this was certainly well deserved. Undoubtedly, the new media-friendly attitude must be seen as an achievement and the renunciation of moral considerations may well have made possible a new kind of neutral description. Yet what happened between the two books? How did this switch of positions come to pass, this drastic change of attitude? In his biography2, Marchand notes a turning point in 1953 – years before the National Association of Educational Broadcasters (NAEB) commissioned McLuhan to conduct the research that would be the basis of Understanding Media.3 Marchand offers a biographical explanation: McLuhan encountered the books by Harold Innis, who had approached the subject of media from the very worldly aspect of economics.
    [Show full text]
  • Priestley and Kant on Materialism
    Intellectual History Review ISSN: 1749-6977 (Print) 1749-6985 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rihr20 Priestley and Kant on materialism Udo Thiel To cite this article: Udo Thiel (2020) Priestley and Kant on materialism, Intellectual History Review, 30:1, 129-143 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/17496977.2020.1688481 © 2019 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group Published online: 19 Dec 2019. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rihr20 INTELLECTUAL HISTORY REVIEW 2020, VOL. 30, NO. 1, 129–143 https://doi.org/10.1080/17496977.2020.1688481 Priestley and Kant on materialism Udo Thiel Department of Philosophy, University of Graz, Graz, Austria ABSTRACT KEYWORDS Kant maintains in the Critique of Pure Reason that both materialism materialism; soul; and spiritualism cannot explain our existence. This paper argues that consciousness; unity; Kant’s relation to (psychological) materialism is more complex than simplicity; identity; this rejection suggests and is usually thought, and it evaluates this apperception relation in a new and more positive light. The paper shows that Priestley anticipates some of Kant’s arguments against rationalist psychology, and that Kant’s rejection of materialism does not commit him to an immaterialist metaphysics of the soul. These arguments involve a discussion of the problem of the unity of consciousness and of notions such as simplicity and identity. Kant argues in the Critique of Pure Reason that materialism is “incapable” of “explaining my existence”.1,2 Several commentators, including, notably, Henry Allison, take Kant’s rejection of materialism to be a “refutation”, suggesting that Kant attempts to prove that materialism, as a metaphysical thesis, is false.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy There Are No Good Objections to Substance Dualism
    Philosophy http://journals.cambridge.org/PHI Additional services for Philosophy: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here There are no good objections to substance dualism José Gusmão Rodrigues Philosophy / Volume 89 / Issue 02 / April 2014, pp 199 - 222 DOI: 10.1017/S0031819114000060, Published online: 24 March 2014 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0031819114000060 How to cite this article: José Gusmão Rodrigues (2014). There are no good objections to substance dualism . Philosophy, 89, pp 199-222 doi:10.1017/S0031819114000060 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/PHI, IP address: 129.108.9.184 on 15 Aug 2014 Joint winner of the 2013 Philosophy prize essay competition There are no good objections to substance dualism JOSÉ GUSMÃO RODRIGUES Abstract This article aimsto review the standard objectionsto dualism and to argue that either they will fail to convince someone committed to dualism or are flawed on independent grounds. I begin by presenting the taxonomy of metaphysical positions on concrete par- ticulars as they relate to the dispute between materialists and dualists, and in particular substance dualism is defined. In the first section, several kinds of substance dualism are distinguished and the relevant varieties of this kind of dualism are selected. The re- maining sections are analyses of the standard objections to substance dualism: It is unin- formative, has troubles accounting for soul individuation, causal pairing and interaction, violates laws of physics, is made implausible by the development of neuroscience and it postulates entities beyond necessity. I conclude that none of these objections is successful.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: a Version of the Argument from Reason
    University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Graduate Studies The Vault: Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2019-04-30 The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason Hawkes, Gordon Hawkes, G. (2019). The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason (Unpublished master's thesis). University of Calgary, Calgary, AB. http://hdl.handle.net/1880/110301 master thesis University of Calgary graduate students retain copyright ownership and moral rights for their thesis. You may use this material in any way that is permitted by the Copyright Act or through licensing that has been assigned to the document. For uses that are not allowable under copyright legislation or licensing, you are required to seek permission. Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason by Gordon Hawkes A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS GRADUATE PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY CALGARY, ALBERTA APRIL, 2019 © Gordon Hawkes 2019 i Abstract The argument from reason is the name given to a family of arguments against naturalism, materialism, or determinism, and often for theism or dualism. One version of the argument from reason is what Victor Reppert calls “the argument from the psychological relevance of logical laws,” or what I call “the argument from logical principles.” This argument has received little attention in the literature, despite being advanced by Victor Reppert, Karl Popper, and Thomas Nagel.
    [Show full text]
  • MATERIALISM: a HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION Charles Wolfe
    MATERIALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION Charles Wolfe To cite this version: Charles Wolfe. MATERIALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION. MATERI- ALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL, Springer International Publishing, 2016, Springer Briefs, 978-3-319-24818-9. 10.1007/978-3-319-24820-2. hal-01233178 HAL Id: hal-01233178 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01233178 Submitted on 24 Nov 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. MATERIALISM: A HISTORICO-PHILOSOPHICAL INTRODUCTION Forthcoming in the Springer Briefs series, December 2015 Charles T. Wolfe Centre for History of Science Department of Philosophy and Moral Sciences Ghent University [email protected] TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter 1 (Introduction): materialism, opprobrium and the history of philosophy Chapter 2. To be is to be for the sake of something: Aristotle’s arguments with materialism Chapter 3. Chance, necessity and transformism: brief considerations Chapter 4. Early modern materialism and the flesh or, forms of materialist embodiment Chapter 5. Vital materialism and the problem of ethics in the Radical Enlightenment Chapter 6. Naturalization, localization: a remark on brains and the posterity of the Enlightenment Chapter 7. Materialism in Australia: The Identity Theory in retrospect Chapter 8.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche's Naturalism As a Critique of Morality and Freedom
    NIETZSCHE’S NATURALISM AS A CRITIQUE OF MORALITY AND FREEDOM A thesis submitted to Kent State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Nathan W. Radcliffe December, 2012 Thesis written by Nathan W. Radcliffe B.S., University of Akron, 1998 M.A., Kent State University, 2012 Approved by Gene Pendleton____________________________________, Advisor David Odell‐Scott___________________________________, Chair, Department of Philosophy Raymond Craig_____________________________________, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS....................................................................................................................v INTRODUCTION............................................................................................................................... 1 CHAPTERS I. NIETZSCHE’S NATURALISM AND ITS INFLUENCES....................................................... 8 1.1 Nietzsche’s Speculative‐Methodological Naturalism............................................ 8 1.2 Nietzsche’s Opposition to Materialism ............................................................... 15 1.3 The German Materialist Influence on Nietzsche................................................. 19 1.4 The Influence of Lange on Nietzsche .................................................................. 22 1.5 Nietzsche’s Break with Kant and Its Aftermath................................................... 25 1.6 Influences on Nietzsche’s Fatalism (Schopenhauer and Spinoza)
    [Show full text]
  • A Historical-Materialist Response to New Materialism
    PSX0010.1177/0032321717731926Political StudiesChoat 731926research-article2017 Article Political Studies 1 –16 Science, Agency and Ontology: © The Author(s) 2017 Reprints and permissions: A Historical-Materialist sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav https://doi.org/10.1177/0032321717731926DOI: 10.1177/0032321717731926 Response to New Materialism journals.sagepub.com/home/psx Simon Choat Abstract In recent years, the work of a diverse range of thinkers has been grouped together under the label ‘new materialism’. This article offers a critical introduction to new materialism that challenges its understanding of historical materialism. It aims to demonstrate not that historical materialism is superior to new materialism, but rather that the latter would benefit from engaging with rather than ignoring or dismissing the former. It begins by defining new materialism in relation to its reappraisal of science, its concept of agency and its underlying ontology. Second, it locates new materialism by demonstrating how and why many new materialists are hostile to historical materialism. Finally, it responds to new materialist criticisms of historical materialism, arguing both that there are potential areas of agreement between the two materialisms and that historical materialism offers valuable resources for analysing historically specific and asymmetric power relations. Keywords new materialism, historical materialism, science, agency, nature Accepted: 25 August 2016 In the final two decades of the twentieth century, radical Anglophone social and political theory frequently took its cue from post-structuralism, with its emphasis on the discursive and linguistic production of subjectivity. In contrast, numerous commentators have sug- gested that the first few years of this century have witnessed a materialist turn within the humanities and social sciences, with a new interest in the relevance of the material world to social and political concerns (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume's Sceptical Materialism
    Hume’s Sceptical Materialism STEPHEN BUCKLE Abstract The paper argues that Hume’s philosophy is best described as sceptical materialism. It is argued that the conjunction is not self-contradictory as long as ‘scepticism’ is understood in its ancient sense, as the denial of knowledge of the essences of things. It is further argued that scepticism (thus understood) and materialism are natural bedfellows, since a thoroughgoing materialism denies any special status to human rational powers. The content of the Treatise of Human Nature is then shown to conform to this understanding: the Treatise consistently employs an implicitly materialist faculty psychology in order to arrive at its sceptical standpoint. Finally, it is shown that Hume’s philosophy can be understood to be a sceptical rewriting of the dogmatic materialism of Hobbes. What, in a nutshell, is Hume’s philosophy? The question has not readily produced answers. Studies of Hume’s philosophy abound, but it is not uncommon for these to discuss Hume’s arguments at great length without discerning a central thread, and thereby without providing an answer of the right kind. Part of the explanation for this state of affairs is the modern analytic philosopher’s tendency to think of philosophy as a matter of arguments, and therefore of great philosophy as great arguments. So a great, dead philosopher proves himself so by the arguments contained within his works—rather than by the fundamental philosophical idea which his arguments are intended to serve. One consequence of analytic philosophy, then, is that it has tended to read the mighty dead by concentrating on the detail on the page, rather than stepping back to consider what might be the point or tendency of a given philosopher’s corpus of arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Religion, Science, and the Conscious Self: Bio-Psychological Explanation and the Debate Between Dualism and Naturalism
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2011 Religion, Science, and the Conscious Self: Bio-Psychological Explanation and the Debate Between Dualism and Naturalism Paul J. Voelker Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Voelker, Paul J., "Religion, Science, and the Conscious Self: Bio-Psychological Explanation and the Debate Between Dualism and Naturalism" (2011). Dissertations. 242. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/242 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2011 Paul J. Voelker LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO RELIGION, SCIENCE, AND THE CONSCIOUS SELF: BIO-PSYCHOLOGICAL EXPLANATION AND THE DEBATE BETWEEN DUALISM AND NATURALISM A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN THEOLOGY BY PAUL J. VOELKER CHICAGO, ILLINOIS MAY 2011 Copyright by Paul J. Voelker, 2011 All rights reserved. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Many people helped to make this dissertation project a concrete reality. First, and foremost, I would like to thank my advisor, Dr. John McCarthy. John’s breadth and depth of knowledge made for years of stimulating, challenging conversation, and I am grateful for his constant support. Dr. Michael Schuck also provided for much good conversation during my time at Loyola, and I am grateful to Mike for taking time from a hectic schedule to serve on my dissertation committee.
    [Show full text]
  • Substance Monism
    Substance Monism Materialism – Hobbes 1. Corpuscularianism: In order to understand Hobbes’ Monist view on substances, it is necessary to understand that he was coming out of the Corpuscularian tradition. The Corpuscularian theory proposes that everything is composed of tiny material atoms, or “corpuscles”. Everything that we observe can be explained in terms of these corpuscles. All events are just a matter of the size, shape, and motion/rest of bits of matter, which move around and collide with one another. Descartes accepted a Corpuscularian view, but only for the extended, or material world. However, he ALSO accepted the existence of a non-extended, immaterial world of thought. Hobbes is merely the extension of Corpuscularianism to the extreme, saying that ALL that exists are material corpuscles. So, Hobbes’ view is a form of Monism, or the view that there is only one sort of substance in the world; namely, a material one. 2. Materialism: Hobbes gives several reasons for rejecting the existence of immaterial substances. First, Hobbes understands that by “real” we just MEAN “located somewhere in the universe.” But, whatever is located somewhere must be corporeal, since incorporeal things are not located anywhere. He concludes that “incorporeal” might as well just mean “non-existent.” In particular, for the soul, there is the question of how a soul inhabits a body. The soul is supposed to be immaterial, non-extended, and non-located, or “incapable of place”—and yet, somehow, the soul is said to be located in and “inhabit” the body. Furthermore, there is the question of how the outside world—e.g., pain—affects the soul (and how the soul affects the body).
    [Show full text]
  • Materialism, Instrumental Reason, and Hostile Enlightenment
    Materialism, Instrumental Reason, and Hostile Enlightenment The Marquis de Sade as the Antithesis of the Enlightenment Mykyta Storozhenko Florida Atlantic University Introduction The aim of this paper is to tie together the Enlightenment ideas regarding Materialism and Instrumental Reason with Pierre Saint-Amand’s thought in his “Hostile Enlightenment” article. The paper will be a quadripartite, and will include the following: (1) a description of Julien Offray de la Mettrie’s materialist philosophy and his rejection of Cartesian reason, as well as a discussion of his ideas’ relevance and influence; (2) a description of the Marquis de Sade’s philosophy, particularly his materialism; (3) a reading of Pierre Saint-Amand’s “Hostile Enlightenment” with a particular focus on his thoughts regarding Sade; (4) a conclusion, in which I will argue that Sade is a direct representation of the Enlightenment giving birth to its own antithesis. Section 1.1 Julien Offray de la Mettrie’s Materialism and Rejection of Cartesian Reason In his “Man a Machine,” Julien Offray de la Mettrie offers up a materialistic and mechanistic account of man so radical that it “shocked even some of the most irreligious of his fellow philosophes.”1 But what is it about his mechanistic and materialistic account that is so radical, shocking, and repulsive to his fellow philosophes? To understand just how far- out his philosophy was, I am going to offer an interpretation of his “Man a Machine.” I will first address his metaphysical materialism, and then his empiricist method
    [Show full text]