LAW and LAW COURTS in ANCIENT GREECE Rosalind Thomas The

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

LAW and LAW COURTS in ANCIENT GREECE Rosalind Thomas The LAW AND LAW COURTS IN ANCIENT GREECE Rosalind Thomas The Institute of Classical Studies and the wider University of London have been an important catalyst for work on Greek law and the Athenian law courts, and the Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies has been able to reflect this. We bring together here a rich collection of twelve articles by scholars who from various angles have examined the actual, practical operation of the law and the law courts through the techniques of Athenian oratory. The wealth of evidence for the operation of the law courts and the assembly from Athens means that most of these articles focus upon Athenian rhetoric and law in the heyday of its democracy. Theories about argument in oratory have a wider application across the Greek world, and two articles included here range beyond Athens in thinking about the nature and application of law. A series of seminars held at the Institute of Classical Studies, and the colloquia on the ‘New Hypereides’ discovered in the Archimedes Palimpsest and on ‘Profession and Performance’, created excellent opportunities to explore the interlocking questions and debates about the role of law, the rule of law, and the relation of legal procedures and rhetoric in democratic Athens. We cannot examine law by itself without the apparatus within which it was applied and the structures – either cultural or political – in which it was created, and then argued over, supported, evaded, and put into action. There is a continuing debate about how far the Athenian law courts really kept to the law; did they not get distracted by irrelevant arguments or emotive narrative, fine and clever speakers, fraught periods of high tension, and of course by the highly skilled techniques which the semi-professional orators increasingly exercised? As the techniques of Athenian oratory and persuasion developed in the late fifth century, so did the techniques of ‘proof’. There is reason to believe that in the late fifth century and especially after the restoration of the Athenian democracy in 403 BC, Athenians tried to buttress the role of written law still more clearly, declaring that only written laws could be used, not ‘unwritten law’ (with all the ambiguity that such a term could involve). A firm separation between nomos, meaning ‘law’ or written statute law, and psēphisma, meaning ‘decree’, was attempted. Athenians should not be able to repeat the constitutional and military disaster of the trial of the generals after Arginusae in 405 BC, where ‘the will of the dēmos’ was expressed in the tense and angry atmosphere of the assembly of the day, and this was allowed to supersede the clear legal procedures which necessitated a separate trial for each general (Xen. Hell. I 7.1–35). The place of law and ‘artless proofs’ amid the other arguments and proofs is examined by Christopher Carey in a classic article reproduced here, entitled ‘Artless proofs in Aristotle and the orators’ (BICS 39 (1994) 95–106).1 Aristotle meant by ‘artless proofs’, atechnoi pisteis, the range of ‘witnesses, tortures, contracts, and the like’, as opposed to arguments devised by orators. Carey examines the possibility that the orator could deploy and manipulate these pre-existing ‘proofs’, and the relation to rhetorical argument (‘artificial proof’). He shows that careful deployment of depositions and witnesses could in fact influence the use of other kinds of proof, the rhetorical deployment of moral and ethical arguments. The related question of how strictly the Athenian courts really applied the law is examined with reference to epieikeia, the concept of ‘equity’ or ‘fairness’, by Edward Harris (BICS 56.1 (2013) 27–48: ‘How strictly did the Athenian courts apply the law? The role of epieikeia’). Also starting with Aristotle’s striking remarks about ‘fairness’, this piece argues that ‘fairness’ did in fact enable jurors to consider extenuating circumstances and cases not precisely covered by the laws, but covered implicitly by Athenian ideas of justice. The relationship between written law and either ‘oral law’ or non-written habits of dispute settlement is examined by Rosalind Thomas, ‘Written in stone? Liberty, equality, orality, and the codification of law’ (BICS 40 (1995) 59–74). This looks at evolving ideas about written law and non-written law, especially in archaic and fifth-century Greece, arguing that when written laws came into use they did not necessarily stand alone or arrive onto a blank slate, but often had as background non-written and older (‘non-legal’) customs; archaic laws were often written up on stone precisely because they were new or controversial. Another chapter also looks beyond Athens: Peter Liddel explores the extent to which Athens interfered with the legislative and epigraphic habits of the allies of the Delian League (BICS 53.1 (2010) 99–128: ‘Epigraphy, legislation, and power within the Athenian Empire’). This includes investigating the extent and nature of inscribed legislation by the allies. The growth of the teaching of oratory, the art of persuasion, brought to the fore useful techniques, certain tricks, and types of argument which were seen to be effective, and which 1 Cf. also his ‘Nomos in Attic rhetoric and oratory’, JHS 116 (1996) 33–46. can amusingly be seen applied to precisely opposite sides of a case in Antiphon’s Tetralogies. Thus Stephen Usher examines dunaton, ‘possibility’ (BICS 50 (2007) 1–18: ‘Possibility: a neglected topos’). Starting from Aristotle’s Rhetoric (Rhet. 2.18.3–19.15), he examines this as a topos especially of deliberative oratory; including much on the speeches in Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, and Demosthenes, he argues that it is particularly interesting to the historian since it must inevitably bring into play questions of resources and strategy. Michael Gagarin looks at the nature and extent of rational argument in our earliest Athenian oratory, that of Antiphon, in ‘Rational argument in early Athenian oratory’, which appeared in Logos: rational argument in classical rhetoric, BICS Supplement 96 (2007), ed. J. Powell. He examines the range and sophistication of rational arguments, as opposed to the so-called ‘irrational’ or ‘automatic’ proofs championed by some earlier scholarship. Christos Kremmydas in the same colloquium leads on from Gagarin’s paper, and examines rational argument in action in Demosthenes’ Against Leptines (‘Logical argumentation in Demosthenes, Against Leptines’). The new discovery of a text of part of Hypereides’ speech Against Timandros gave rise to a colloquium again in London’s Institute of Classical Studies in 2009, on The New Hypereides (The New Hypereides Conference Proceedings, ed. Mike Edwards, published in BICS 52 (2009) 133–252). This offered an opportunity to examine Hypereides’ techniques and relation to the laws in this new text. Lene Rubinstein looks at his legal argumentation in ‘Legal argumentation in Hypereides’ Against Timandros’, focusing on the Athenian law about orphan siblings, and whether the speaker was misrepresenting it. David Whitehead examines the text with particular attention to the nature of the suit and accusation, penalties and strategies, and the socio-legal expectations about orphans and their well-being (‘Hypereides’ Timandros: observations and suggestions’). Finally we include Edith Hall, who examines ‘Lawcourt dramas: the power of performance in in Greek forensic oratory’, emphasising areas of rhetorical practice where there are revealing similarities in technique, subject matter, and presentation between law court practice and Athenian drama (BICS 40 (1995) 39–58).2 More recently two articles concerned with delivery and performance of speeches derive from another colloquium in 2 There is an expanded version (‘Lawcourt dramas: acting and performance in legal oratory’) in E. Hall, The theatrical cast of Athens: interactions between ancient Greek drama and society (Oxford and New York 2006) 353–92. London, organised by Royal Holloway, and are taken from the edited papers of that colloquium, Profession and Performance, BICS Supplement 123 (2013), ed. C. Kremmydas, J. Powell, and L. Rubinstein. Mike Edwards examines delivery in ‘Hypokritēs in action: delivery in Greek rhetoric’; in part following on from Edith Hall’s 1995 article (above), he wishes to draw important distinctions between possible behaviour in the theatre, and what was needed in the law courts, and stressing a tension between theory and practice in the art of speaking by examining closely certain very precise techniques of performance in extant speeches. The second piece is by Victor Bers, ‘Performing the speech in Athenian courts and assembly. Adjusting the act to fit the bēma?’. Examining various aspects of delivery, practical and ideological, he argues that techniques of delivery were in fact adjusted for the law courts: here, orators tended to look composed and in control, while for the citizens in the assembly an orator could indulge in a more excited performance, and there had to be more interaction with, or control of, the thorubos (‘noise’ or ‘uproar’) of the crowd. The relation of law and democracy, where democracy prides itself on the rule of law, is a matter which is still of central importance in modern democracy, as recent events again make clear. November, 2016. Balliol College, Oxford. .
Recommended publications
  • Democracy and Institutional Change
    European Research Studies, Volume X, Issue (1-2) 2007 Democracy and institutional change By Nicholas Kyriazis1 Abstract: The present essay analyses decision making procedures concerning economic issues such as the choice of public goods in the prototype democracy, Ancient Athens of the fourth century BC (the “Age of Demosthenes”). It analyses the link between political democracy, “economic” democracy, the emergence of new institutions and the finance of public goods like defence, education and “social security”. The prototype political democracy was advanced in questions of public administration, finance and institutions, on which political democracy was based. The paper concludes with some proposals as to what we could “learn” from the workings of “economic democracy” that is relevant for today’s democracies. Keywords: Hospital efficiency, productivity, health. JEL Classification: I11, I12, I18 1. Introduction There is a vast literature on the history, politics, warfare the arts etc. of the ancient Athenian democracy, which is considered the prototype and the origin of Western democracies.1 Much less attention has been paid till recently on the economics of the Athenian state, which is actually astonishing, since the Athenian state could not have developed its advanced political institutions without a sound economic basis, and advanced institutions and organisations, as I will purport to analyse later on in the present essay. (Kyriazis and Zouboulakis 2004, Kyriazis and Halkos 2005, Cohen 1997, Gabrielsen 1994). The Athenian democracy
    [Show full text]
  • Stories from Greek History
    TO ARCHIBALD R.B. HALDANE Conditions and Terms of Use My dear Archie, Copyright © Heritage History 2010 Some rights reserved Do you remember that bright summer morning last This text was produced and distributed by Heritage History, an year when we lay out on the lawn and read together the organization dedicated to the preservation of classical juvenile history "Labours of Heracles," and how you once interrupted to ask "if books, and to the promotion of the works of traditional history authors. the tales were true?" The books which Heritage History republishes are in the public domain and are no longer protected by the original copyright. They may The tales in this little book are true, and beside the therefore be reproduced within the United States without paying a royalty winter fire I wrote them, fancying that I still had your eager to the author. face beside me, heard still your eager demand for "another The text and pictures used to produce this version of the work, story." Will you like these as well, I wonder? however, are the property of Heritage History and are subject to certain Your loving friend restrictions. These restrictions are imposed for the purpose of protecting the Ethelwyn Lemon integrity of the work, for preventing plagiarism, and for helping to assure that compromised versions of the work are not widely disseminated. In order to preserve information regarding the origin of this text, a copyright by the author, and a Heritage History distribution date are TABLE OF CONTENTS included at the foot of every page of text.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates and Democratic Athens: the Story of the Trial in Its Historical and Legal Contexts
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. Version 1.0 July 2006 Josiah Ober Princeton University Abstract: Socrates was both a loyal citizen (by his own lights) and a critic of the democratic community’s way of doing things. This led to a crisis in 339 B.C. In order to understand Socrates’ and the Athenian community’s actions (as reported by Plato and Xenophon) it is necessary to understand the historical and legal contexts, the democratic state’s commitment to the notion that citizens are resonsible for the effects of their actions, and Socrates’ reasons for preferring to live in Athens rather than in states that might (by his lights) have had substantively better legal systems. Written for the Cambridge Companion to Socrates. © Josiah Ober. [email protected] Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. (for Cambridge Companion to Socrates) Josiah Ober, Princeton University Draft of August 2004 In 399 B.C. the Athenian citizen Socrates, son of Sophroniscus of the deme (township) Alopece, was tried by an Athenian court on the charge of impiety (asebeia). He was found guilty by a narrow majority of the empanelled judges and executed in the public prison a few days later. The trial and execution constitute the best documented events in Socrates’ life and a defining moment in the relationship between Greek philosophy and Athenian democracy. Ever since, philosophers and historians have sought to
    [Show full text]
  • The Rhetoric of the Death Penalty in the Classical Athenian Orators
    The Rhetoric of the Death Penalty in the Classical Athenian Orators The death penalty was frequently exercised in ancient Athens. Hansen (1975, 11) notices the remarkably high number of trials by εἰσαγγελία “often… resulting in a sentence of death”. And yet, the lack of specificity in the contemporary accounts of executions have often frustrated the attempts of scholars to interpret the how, when and where of the death penalty. Indeed, Todd (2000, 36-37) expresses vexation with the orators whose “terminology is surprisingly unimaginative” and who might have displayed “an unwillingness verbally to go into too much detail in the face of death.” In this paper, however, I analyze the arguments the orators used for the death penalty, rather than the information about the executions themselves. More narrowly, I explore whether there was a discernible “rhetoric of the death penalty”, a dedicated pool of patterns of argumentation used by the orators to secure not merely a conviction, but the death penalty specifically. I base my research on a wide array of 4th century speeches, most importantly Lycurgus, Dinarchus and Hypereides. I outline three distinct avenues through which Athenian orators advocated capital punishment. Here I offer a brief summary with illustrative examples: First, I examine how orators employed vocabulary that would be likely to move the jurors to vote for the death penalty. Lycurgus, for example, frequently uses κολάζειν for the penalty that he proposes for Leocrates. Since Plato uses κολάζειν to refer to the more positive “reformative punishment”, and reserves τιμωρεῖσθαι for the grimmer “retributive punishment” (cf. Ladikos 2005, 52), some scholars believe that Lycurgus, like Plato, “wanted to replace anger as a justification for punishment with truth in order that all punishment could be directed at reforming … the wrongdoer’s soul” (Allen 2000, 21).
    [Show full text]
  • Zur Phasis in Der Neu Entdeckten Rede Hypereides' Gegen Timandros
    GERHARD THÜR http://epub.oeaw.ac.at/gerhard-thuer Nr. 275 (Aufsatz / Essay, 2008; siehe auch / see also Nr. 276, 290, 291) Zur phasis in der neu entdeckten Rede Hypereides’ gegen Timandros Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte. Romanistische Abteilung (ZRG RA) 125, 2008, 645–663 © Böhlau Verlag (Wien) mit freundlicher Genehmigung (http://www.savigny-zeitschrift.com) Schlagwörter: Archimedes-Palimpsest — Vormundschaft — misthosis oikou, phasis — Versteigerung — Prätendentenstreit Key Words: Archmedes palimpsest — guardianship — misthosis oikou, phasis — auction — dispute between pretenders [email protected] http://www.oeaw.ac.at/antike/index.php?id=292 Dieses Dokument darf ausschließlich für wissenschaftliche Zwecke genutzt werden (Lizenz CC BY-NC-ND), gewerbliche Nutzung wird urheberrechtlich verfolgt. This document is for scientific use only (license CC BY-NC-ND), commercial use of copyrighted material will be prosecuted. Miszellen Zur phasis in der neu entdeckten Rede Hypereides' gegen Timandros Griechische Inschriften und Papyri rechtlichen Inhalts werden laufend gefunden und publiziert. Auch der Bestand an klassischer Literatur aus Athen wird sporadisch durch Papyrusfunde erweitert. Mittelalterliche Kodizes mit bisher unbekannten Wer- ken werden jedoch kaum mehr entdeckt. Reden des Atheners Hypereides (390-322 v. Chr.) sind, von einer Anzahl kurzer Zitate antiker Grammatiker und Lexikogra- phen abgesehen, bislang nur in Papyri einigermaßen zusammenhängend erhalten. Man zweifelte sogar daran, dass Hypereides überhaupt den Weg in die mittelalterlichen Handschriften gefunden hat1). Dieser Zweifel ist nun ausgeräumt. Natalie Tcher- netska hat in einem seit 1907 bekannten „Archimedes-Palimpsest"2) einige Bifolia von zwei bisher nur dem Titel nach bekannten Hypereidesreden identifiziert, „Gegen Diondas" und „Gegen Timandros". Die Fragmente der zweiten Rede sind 2005 zu einer vorläufigen und nunmehr zur endgültigen Edition gediehen3).
    [Show full text]
  • Public Finance and Democratic Ideology in Fourth-Century BC Athens by Christopher Scott Welser BA, Sw
    Dēmos and Dioikēsis: Public Finance and Democratic Ideology in Fourth-Century B.C. Athens By Christopher Scott Welser B.A., Swarthmore College, 1994 M.A., University of Maryland, 1999 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Classics at Brown University, Providence, Rhode Island. May, 2011 © Copyright 2011 by Christopher Scott Welser This dissertation by Christopher Scott Welser is accepted in its present form by the Department of Classics as satisfying the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Date________________ _______________________________________ Adele C. Scafuro, Advisor Recommended to the Graduate Council Date________________ _______________________________________ Alan L. Boegehold, Reader Date________________ _______________________________________ David Konstan, Reader Approved by the Graduate Council Date________________ _______________________________________ Peter M. Weber, Dean of the Graduate School iii CURRICULUM VITAE Christopher Scott Welser was born in Romeo, Michigan in 1971. He attended Roeper City and Country School in Bloomfield Hills, Michigan, and in 1994 he graduated from Swarthmore College, earning an Honors B.A. in Economics (his major) and Biology (his minor). After working for several years at public policy research firms in Pennsylvania and New Jersey, he decided to pursue the study of Classics, an interest of his since childhood. Upon earning an M.A. with Distinction in Latin and Greek from the University of Maryland at College Park in 1999, he enrolled in the Ph.D. program in Classics at Brown University. While working on his Ph.D., he spent two years as Seymour Fellow (2002-2003) and Capps Fellow (2004-2005) at the American School of Classical Studies at Athens and participated in the summer program of the American Academy in Rome (2000).
    [Show full text]
  • Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirement
    Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2015 Reading Committee: Ruby Blondell, Chair Deborah Kamen Alexander Hollmann Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics Department Allison Das ii ©Copyright 2015 Allison E. Das Allison Das iii University of Washington Abstract Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison E. Das Chair of Supervisory Committee Dr. Ruby Blondell Classics Department Introduction This project is intended as an examination of medical language and imagery in the speeches of Demosthenes, with special attention given to his speeches against his political opponent Aeschines, Against the False Embassy (19) and On the Crown (18). In Chapter 1, I contextualize his use of such language and imagery by exploring the influence of Hippocratic medicine on fourth- and fifth-century non-medical literature. I argue that the shared anxieties of medicine and politics, namely that both arts demand quick action and foresight on the part of the good practitioner, and the rich new vocabulary of suffering and disease, made Hippocratic medicine an enticing model for the political writer, that is, the historian, philosopher, and orator. Demosthenes' medical language and imagery should thus be seen as part of a tradition of analogizing the two arts, which began during the circulation of the first Hippocratic treatises and continued well into and past his own day. Allison Das iv In Chapter 2, I look at medical language and imagery in Demosthenes' prosecution of Aeschines for political misconduct during the Second Embassy to Philip II of Macedon, On the False Embassy.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetores" in the Athenian "Ecclesia", 355-322 B.C
    HANSEN, MOGENS HERMAN, The Number of "Rhetores" in the Athenian "Ecclesia", 355-322 B.C. , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 25:2 (1984) p.123 The Number of Rhetores in the Athenian Ecciesia, 355-322 B.C. Mogens Herman Hansen OLITICAL PARTICIPATION in ancient Athens is a complex prob­ Plem, encompassing both the various forms of participation, the degree of participation, and the number of participants. Broadly speaking we can distinguish three kinds: 1 (a) an Athenian citizen might be a member of the ecclesia or of the panel of jurors who manned the courts and the legislative committees (the nomothetai)~ (b) he might fill an office (arche) , either through election or sorti­ tion~ (c) he might take an initiative and, as a rhetor, address the ecclesia, boule, nomothetai, or dicasteria. As to (a), as an ecclesiastes or a juror the average Athenian citizen would have only to listen and vote. He was anonymous and could not be held responsible for how he voted, and he was paid for his participation. As to (b), as a magis­ trate selected by lot the citizen would have little or no power to make decisions, but on the other hand he would have administrative duties for which he could be held responsible both when he was in office and when he resigned at the turn of the year. In most cases, how­ ever, he would share the responsibilities with his colleagues: he would be one of the five hundred bouleutai or a member of one of the numerous boards of ten. The elective offices (most of them military) are a case apart.
    [Show full text]
  • Litigants and Witnesses in the Athenian Courts: Procedural Variations
    L E N E R U B I N S T E I N ( L O N D O N ) MAIN LITIGANTS AND WITNESSES IN THE ATHENIAN COURTS: PROCEDURAL VARIATIONS One of the most significant developments in modern research on the role of the Athenian witness has been the emphasis on the witness’s personal connection with the litigant whom he was supporting. It is widely held that an Athenian litigant would attempt to enlist the support of as many family members and personal friends as he possibly could, and that the main function of such witnesses was to make a public display of the loyalty that the main litigant was able to command. In an influential article, S.C. Humphreys (1985) presented a survey of attested Athenian witnesses, grouped in concentric circles around the individuals whom they were supporting, starting from citizens who appeared in their official capacities as magistrates in the outermost circle and ending with the litigant’s closest kin in the innermost circle. One of the conclusions reached by Humphreys (1985: 350) on the basis of this evidence is that an important function of the witnesses was to convey an impression to the judges that the litigant enjoyed the personal backing of the social networks in which he operated. The interpretation of the role of the witness as that of a partisan of the litigant, rather than as a potential source of information relating to the case itself, is attractive for several reasons. First, it helps to explain why the part played by the witness in the fourth century was restricted to a mere confirmation of a statement drawn up and submitted in advance either by the witness himself or by the main litigant for whom the witness was appearing.
    [Show full text]
  • Xaphz Aiteah0en: Biography of a Fourth-Century Athenian Strategos
    XAPHZ AITEAH0EN: BIOGRAPHY OF A FOURTH-CENTURY ATHENIAN STRATEGOS By RICHARD WAYNE PARKER B.A., The University of California, Santa Barbara, 1973 M.A., The University of California, Santa Barbara, 1978 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY . in THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES (Department of Classics, Faculty of Arts) We accept this thesis as conforming to the required standard THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA August 1986 <£> Richard Wayne Parker, 1986 In presenting this thesis in partial fulfilment of the requirements for an advanced degree at the University of British Columbia, I agree that the Library shall make it freely available for reference and study. I further agree that permission for extensive copying of this thesis for scholarly purposes may be granted by the head of my department or by his or her representatives. It is understood that copying or publication of this thesis for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission. CLASSICS Department of The University of British Columbia 2075 Wesbrook Place Vancouver, Canada V6T 1W5 Date -7Q ^ ii ABSTRACT Khares of Angele was an Athenian military magistrate and mercenary soldier for over forty years in the mid-fourth century B.C. For two decades between the outbreak of the Social War and the battle of Khaironeia he was Athens' pre-eminent military leader. The ancient sources dealing with this era of Greek history mention him with great frequency and his role in the events of his times provoked strong comments and vivid portraits from contemporary writers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Agenda of Libanius' Hypotheses to Demosthenes
    The Agenda of Libanius’ Hypotheses to Demosthenes Craig A. Gibson F SCHOLARLY INTEREST AND ACTIVITY are an accurate indication, Demosthenes was alive and well in late antiquity. By the time of Libanius (A.D. 314–ca 393),1 readers of this 700-year- Iold classic were well served with secondary treatments of all kinds: rhetorical commentaries and handbooks, biographies of the orator, philological and historical commentaries, special literary studies, lexica to individual speeches (both alphabetical and non-alphabetical), and alphabetical lexica to the Attic orators as a whole. But outside the classrooms of the grammar- ians and rhetoricians, students of Demosthenes had no basic guide to the more than sixty items in this unwieldy corpus. It was to satisfy some such market as this that Libanius com- posed one of his earliest known works: a set of introductions, or “hypotheses” (Ípoy°seiw), to Demosthenes’ speeches.2 1 On Libanius’ life and writings see J. H. W. G. Liebeschuetz, Antioch: City and Imperial Administration (Oxford 1972) 1–39. Bibliography for the years 1954–81 may be found in G. Fatouros and T. Krischer, edd., Libanios (Darmstadt 1983) 275–280. 2 Text: R. Foerster, ed., Libanii Opera VIII (Leipzig 1915) 575–681. References to the hypotheses here will append the modern number of the Demosthenes ora- tion, e.g. Hyp. 25.4 [59]. Libanius was not the only ancient scholar to compose hypotheses to Demosthenes. According to the Suda, Posidonius of Olbiopolis in the second century (S 2109, discussed under 2108) and the rhetor Numenius in the first (N 518) also wrote them.
    [Show full text]
  • Way Back When
    Way back when The Ancient Greeks invented the field of rhetoric, in which speakers called orators play upon both reason and emotion to persuade their audiences. The Greeks used oratory to inform political and judicial decisions, and also to develop and share new philosophies. Great thinkers presented their ideas in front of audiences, and orators often competed against one another in public contests for cash prizes, fame, and political influence! Greek orators were so well known for their abilities that even after Greece were conquered by Rome, wealthy Romans would send their kids to Greece to learn public speaking. The most famous Greek orators were the Ten Attic Orators, who lived in an around Athens during the 5th and 4th centuries B.C.E. (a time often known as the “Golden Age” of Athens). They were: Antiphon; Andocides; Lysias; Isocrates; Isaeus; Aeschines; Lycurgus; Demosthenes; Hypereides; and Dinarchus. Of these, the four most important were probably the following: Antiphon helped install an oligarchy, or government of the few, in Athens in 411 B.C.E., and was executed for treason when traditional Athenian democracy returned. Isocrates (pictured), who belonged to a school of orators called the Sophists, became rich by teaching rhetoric to wealthy students Lycurgus held a number of public offices in Athens and oversaw both public finances and public morals. Demosthenes overcame a speech disorder to become the most famous orator of all time. He often spoke on behalf of keeping Athens free from the clutches of a conquering king called Philip of Macedon. These fiery speeches were called Philippics.
    [Show full text]