<<

European Journal of Sociology http://journals.cambridge.org/EUR

Additional services for European Journal of Sociology:

Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here

The Performativity of Networks

Kieran Healy

European Journal of Sociology / Volume 56 / Issue 02 / August 2015, pp 175 - 205 DOI: 10.1017/S0003975615000107, Published online: 07 August 2015

Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0003975615000107

How to cite this article: Kieran Healy (2015). The Performativity of Networks. European Journal of Sociology, 56, pp 175-205 doi:10.1017/S0003975615000107

Request Permissions : Click here kieran healy The Performativity of Networks

Abstract The “performativity thesis” is the claim that parts of contemporary and finance, when carried out into the world by professionals and popularizers, reformat and reorganize the phenomena they purport to describe, in ways that bring the world into line with theory. Practical technologies, calculative devices and portable algorithms give actors tools to implement particular models of action. I argue that social network analysis is performative in the same sense as the cases studied in this literature. Social network analysis and finance theory are similar in key aspects of their development and effects. For the case of economics, evidence for weaker versions of the performativity thesis is quite good, and the strong formulation is circumstantially supported. Network theory easily meets the evidential threshold for the weaker versions. I offer empirical examples that support the strong (or “Barnesian”) formulation. Whether these parallels are a mark in favor of the thesis or a strike against it is an open question. I argue that the social network technologies and models now being “performed” build out systems of generalized reciprocity, connectivity, and commons-based production. This is in contrast both to an earlier network imagery that emphasized self-interest and entrepreneurial exploitation of structural opportunities, and to the model of action typically considered to be performed by economic technologies.

Keywords: Performativity; Economics; Social Network Analysis; Internet; Algorithms.

The realities of social structure are more blurred [.] One special case are the procedures of social research, which to an increasing extent are being built in as an accepted part of the validation and legitimation procedures in current American society, for better or worse [White 1965: 10].

Several stories might be, and are, told about eigenvectors [Breiger 2000: 110].

S OCIAL NETWORK ANALYSIS, broadly construed, is performative in much the same theoretical sense and, increasingly, on much the same empirical scale as the economic and financial models examined by “social studies of finance” [Callon 1998; Mac- Kenzie and Millo 2003; MacKenzie 2006; Muniesa and Callon 2007].

175 Kieran HEALY, Duke University [[email protected]] European Journal of Sociology, 56, 2 (2015), pp. 175–205—0003-9756/15/0000-900$07.50per art + $0.10 per page ªEuropean Journal of Sociology 2015.doi:10.1017/S0003975615000107 kieran healy

That is the main claim of this paper. I argue that there are three principal reasons for believing it. First, the two cases are alike. Considered as intellectual and practical projects, the structure and trajectory of social network analysis and finance theory show striking similarities in form. Second, the standard of proof is within reach. While the evidence for weak or moderate versions of the perform- ativity thesis is quite good, its strongest formulations are only circumstantially supported by the best evidence we have at present. Thus, the case for a performative dimension to network theory has about the same level of empirical support—which is to say, pretty good—as that for economics. Whether we should interpret this as a mark in favor of the performativity thesis, or a strike against it, is an open question. Third, and more positively, the evidence is relatively new. Paradigmatic cases of the performativity of economics go back some decades, but the performative moment of network analysis is more recent and much less well-explored. I offer several examples. Network concepts and images are by now central not just to the of markets, but to theories of social exchange in general. The importance of network ties to market exchange is a core aspect of what, 25 years ago, was beginning to be called the new economic sociology [Granovetter 1985]. We visualize the circulation of people and goods in society as flow in a dynamically evolving structure of network relations. As a disciplinary project, network theory has grown from a peripheral position in the early 1970s—or, more charitably, from its niche as a respected but specialized subfield—into a central project within contemporary sociology. Network theory has proliferated and diffused across the intellectual landscape over this period with great success. Its ability to cash out some of its most important theoretical concepts and images in formal methods and usable tools has been a vital part of this process. As in the case of theories of finance and their expression in financial markets, we see network theory and its analytical toolkit embedding and extending themselves in a range of settings. The growth of network theory within sociology, in other words, has been accompanied—and is perhaps by now overshadowed—by its practical embedding in the world at large. Asecondaryclaimofthispaperisthatwhat we are seeing “performed” in these settings is quite different from the model of economic action investigated by MacKenzie, Callon and others, and also quite different from an earlier (and quite successful) effort to evangelize the network gospel. An older public image of the importance of networks in exchange was highly instrumental.

176 the performativity of networks

It emphasized the benefits of “networking” for individual careers, and the strategic advantage to managers of having well-structured networks with respect to their employees, their suppliers, or their competitors. Despite the success of network imagery as a vehicle for entrepreneurial advantage in competitive markets, the network technologies and models that are being implemented most widely (at least in the public arena) are those that emphasize network effects in their aspect as channels of generalized reciprocity, connectivity, and community-building. While these aspects are not inimical to profit opportunities, in this sense the performativity of networks trends against that of economics. In what follows, I lay out the performativity thesis in more detail and assess the parallels between the cases of finance and network theory, providing a series of examples for the latter case. I then return to the question of the usefulness of performativity as a concept.

The performativity thesis

Economic sociologists argue about whether it makes sense to think of economic knowledge as performative. Originally articulated by Callon [1998] and refined by MacKenzie and Millo [2003], and MacKenzie [2006], the performativity thesis is that economics produces a body of formal models and transportable techniques that, when carried out into the world by its professionals and popularizers, reformats and reorganizes the phenomena the models purport to describe. This is a suggestive idea, and one that admits of stronger and weaker interpretations. In its strongest form, the performative process brings the empirical phenomena into line with the original model. Of particular interest in this approach is the focus—inherited from science studies—on how performative projects are accomplished by way of practical technologies, reproducible models and portable algorithms. The success of economics is not just a matter of a partic- ular conception of rationality serving as a ceremonial gloss on social action [Meyer and Rowan 1977]; nor is it a simple instance of ideological indoctrination [Marwell and Ames 1981]. Rather, tools implementing formal models of action—“calculative devices”—are put in the hands of social agents by the model-builders or their representatives. These devices act as “cognitive prostheses” that enable actors to accomplish calculative tasks previously beyond their

177 kieran healy reach, but which are required by the theoretical models. When incorporated into the everyday work of market agents, these devices allow real settings to better approximate the original models, and their assumptions. This is the “performative loop” in its most interesting, so-called “Barnesian” form. Granovetter argued that a social theory of markets should begin with a view of actors as embedded in an evolving structure of concrete social relations. From this perspective, neoclassical economics is fundamentally misconceived, either because “the fact that actors may have social relations with one another has been treated, if at all, as a frictional drag that impedes competitive markets”, or because, when they are examined, models “invariably abstract away from the of relations and their position with respect to other relations” [Granovetter 1985: 485-486].1 The strong version of the performativity thesis, by contrast, is a kind of backhanded compliment from sociology to economics. Complimentary because it acknowledges the success of economics in prosecuting its claims to objective knowledge of the economy, but backhanded because it claims that this success is not what it seems. Economics turns out to create rather than discover its subject matter. This idea has a beguiling appeal to sociologists. If the story is right, then it seems that sociology, the politically and institutionally weaker field, wins out over economics in the end, like a canny David besting a lumbering Goliath. The natives’ account—something like, “These models work because they are correct, or very good approx- imations to the truth”—is shown to be wrong, and the sociological account ends up encapsulating and explaining the success of the economic one.2 Or so one version of the story might go. The most careful and detailed study of the performativity of economic theory, Donald

1 He goes on to argue that Parsonian action [Parsons 1991 : 22-23]. Keynes’ Gen- sociology failed for similar reasons, also ig- eral Theory of Employment, Interest and noring concrete social relations in favor of Money was “the kind of theory of the short- “enduring structures of normative role pre- run equilibrium process of the economy that scriptions deriving from ultimate value ori- one would ask for on the hypothesis that the entations” [Granovetter 1985: 486]. economy was a social system as I have out- 2 This is a risky strategy. In his 1953 lined it” and so claimed “to have broadly Marshall Lectures, Talcott Parsons argued substantiated the thesis that Keynes’ General that the “basic categories of economic theory Theory is in fact a special case of the short- [.] can be derived from the frame of refer- run equilibrium theory of social systems” ence, general concepts and variables of the [Parsons 1991, 33-7]. This claim was rather general theory of special systems” and thus poorly received by his Cambridge audience: that “economic theory can be treated as “I was told that when Talcott made his a special case of the more general theory”— statement a member of the audience shouted that is, of Parsons’ agil scheme of social ‘Shit!’” [Homans 1984: 328].

178 the performativity of networks

MacKenzie’s An Engine, Not a Camera [MacKenzie 2006], takes a much more circumspect line. The book’s subtitle is not “How Markets Perform Financial Models” but rather “How Financial Models Shape Markets.” To shape is not to create or determine. MacKenzie frames the book by claiming his argument is quite different from an economic sociology built on the concept of embeddedness, but when making his case he is scrupulous in his handling of the data, and much more conservative in his claims. Much of the empirical detail of the book fits quite comfortably into a more conventional institutionalist account of entrepreneurs working hard to consolidate a new field of economic action, yielding a market populated by densely-networked actors with a lot of local knowledge about the particular financial instruments they manage [Healy 2006]. Nevertheless, stronger versions of the performativity thesis are increasingly common. MacKenzie [2006, 18-19]distinguishesthree kinds of performativity: “generic,” “effective” and “Barnesian” (together with the latter’s negative complement, “counterperforma- tivity”). Generic performativity means the active use of some bit of theory not just by economists but also by economic agents, policy makers and the like. Effective performativity requires that the use of theory not just be window-dressing: it must “make a difference” in practice. Barnesian performativity [named for Barnes 1983, 1988] requires that the use of economics actively alters processes “in ways that bear on their conformity to the aspect of economics in question.” That is, the model or theory must bring participants into line with its picture of the world. In that case the model helps make itself true, in the sense that before its public appearance the system did not behave in accordance with the model’s predictions, whereas subsequently it does. Naturally, it is also possible that a model might undermine the real-world viability of the process it describes. That would be a“counterperformative”effect. MacKenzie argues that performativity can be thought of as part of “a more general phenomenon: the incorporation of economics into the infrastructures of markets.” He examines four cases from the field of finance theory where ideas developed (mostly) by academics might have had performative effects on the structure and practice of financial markets. These are the Modigligani-Miller “irrelevance” propositions for capital theory; portfolio selection theory and the closely related Capital Asset Pricing Model (capm); random walk models and the efficient market hypothesis (emh); and the Black-Scholes-Merton

179 kieran healy

(bsm) formula for option pricing. Taken together, these ideas form the core of modern finance theory, and they contributed to a revolution in financial markets that began in the late 1960s. The cases are mixed in their support for the performativity thesis. The Modigliani-Miller propositions helped launch modern finance theory but did not have strong or immediate practical consequences. In retrospect, they could be seen as providing intellectual support for less negative attitudes towards debt-financing, and as foreshadowing somewhat the financi- alization of corporate governance which took place in the 1980s. The capm’s effects were also ambiguous, as its operationalization presented practical problems and its results agreed only fairly well with the data. The use of the model in practice did not improve its fit. The emh’s effects were more direct. It allowed researchers and investors to systematically identify market anomalies. Using the capm as a baseline, a series of studies investigated the existence of investment opportu- nities that offered excess risk-adjusted returns. Finally, there are the bsm equations for option pricing. This is one of finance theory’s crown jewels and also MacKenzie’s best case for performativity. If the emh provided an overall vision of how the market should work, then Black, Scholes and Merton provided a technique that could be put to work within the market itself. Here MacKenzie sees Barnesian performativity in action, because, he seeks to show, the method that traders used to identify the discrepancies in option prices was the same, in essence, as the one academic researchers used to assess the accuracy of the model itself. MacKenzie refuses to oversell his findings, and is very reluctant to say that he has found more than strongly circumstantial evidence that his cases are performative in the strongest sense, where the use of a model in practice actively alters how things work “in ways that bear on their conformity to the aspect of economics in question” [MacKenzie 2006: 18]. He does believe that some nontrivial version of the performativity thesis is true. But he only rarely speaks as though it has been empirically demonstrated, saying that “Black-Scholes-Merton option-pricing theory was enacted at the Chicago Board Options Exchange,” or remarking that “what is now performed in Chicago is no longer classic option-pricing theory” [MacKenzie 2006, 202]. Much more often, he says that “there will often be an element of conjecture” to such claims, or that there is “a lack of conclusive evidence” in crucial cases, or that the sociological processes “cannot be distinguished” from the strictly economic ones, or that “there is no way of being certain” that

180 the performativity of networks the practical adoption of theoretical models led to an improvement in the observed fit of those models [MacKenzie 2006: 18; 194; 237; 256]. In considering these claims, economic sociologists have been variously supportive or skeptical. But they have confined themselves to case studies of economic expertise and its effects on the world. Debate has centered on the proper way to characterize economics and economists, and a three-sided argument developed between Performa- tivists, Virtualists, and Granovetterians [Carrier and Miller 1998; Miller 2002; Callon 2007; Finch 2007]. There are several case studies across different economic sectors or in different national settings. But the idea that a social science discipline other than economics might have performative effects was slow to surface as a problem within the debate in economic sociology.3 Sociologists have remained outside the performative bubble, hoping to pop it. To the contrary, I argue that in its organization, content and effects, a current wave of social-organizational innovation is being built out of network metaphors and with network tools, and that it satisfies the criteria for “performativity” at least as strongly as is documented in existing case studies of economic models and their effects. Network analysis has a very high degree of “performative potential” because of its combination of a strong theoretical framework, its portable toolkit of methods, and its ability to be embedded in the architecture of exchange systems. As it happens—probably not by coincidence—its developmental trajectory is also similar in key respects to the main exemplar of performativity in markets, finance theory. The parallels to the performative processes described by MacKenzie, Callon and others are direct and robust. Like the early days of finance as a discipline, network theorists begin in small numbers, languish in relative obscurity and have to wait before the force of their work is widely recognized. Like the intellectual products of finance theory, network researchers develop models notable initially for their relatively high degree of abstraction, their commitment to mathematical formalization under strong assumptions, and a combination of intuitively plausible force and lack of validation by anysubstantialbodyofdata.Astime passes, things improve in both camps. Like the early intellectual missionaries of finance theory, network theory begins to find a home in

3 This is not the case in other fields where Foucauldian theories of power underpin performativity is a live issue. Most notably, awell-establisheddebateonperformativity at the intersection of studies, literary and its scope [following Butler 1990]. theory and postcolonial theory, a fusion Ishallnotdiscussthatverylargeliterature of Austinian of and here.

181 kieran healy business schools, and versions of bits of it come to be propagated by consultants. Eventually, I argue, in both cases the theory begins to have significant effects on the kind of processes it nominally seeks to describe.

The growth of network analysis

A detailed intellectual history of social network analysis remains to be written. Crudely, we can say that throughout the 20th century a number of researchers and small working groups developed methods and ideas that, in retrospect, are precursors of contemporary approaches. But these groups tended not to reproduce or institu- tionalize themselves, and neither did they develop into a full-fledged field. One of the few ofthefielddescribesmuchofthe20th century as the “dark ages” of network analysis [Freeman 2004]. The intellectual consolidation of network analysis as a self-conscious enterprise began in earnest in the early 1970sasarecognizable theory group established itself [Mullins 1973; Leinhardt 1977; Holland and Leinhardt 1979]. Harrison White’s research group at Harvard was an epicenter of innovation, with other important work being done at Irvine, Chicago and also in the Carolinas. Network theory’s diffusion as a practical technology followed on a decade or so later. Network researchers became increasingly familiar in sociology departments and, importantly, in business schools. The presence of network analysis in these settings was accompanied, more or less simultaneously, by “network entrepreneurs” who developed products to sell to firms, and consulting practices to convey them. Often these were the same people who were teaching in the business schools.4 Within academic sociology, specialists in theory (itself a formerly high-status specialization in occupational decline during this period [see Lamont 2004 on this point]) gradually came to recognize network analysis as a serious contender in the space of general social theory, rather than, as had previously been the case, a more narrowly middle- range and primarily methodological enterprise. The appearance of Identity and Control [White 1992] helped consolidate this process, as it provided a distinctive theoretical statement encapsulating one of the central lines of work of the previous two decades. Papers such as

4 Recall the first chapter of Structural the network structure of a firm to its ceo and Holes, where Ronald Burt opens with the senior staff: “Panoramic view. State-of-the- image of himself and a colleague explaining art audiovisual. Nice chairs” [Burt 1992 : 1].

182 the performativity of networks

Emirbayer and Goodwin [1994] and Emirbayer [1997] are indicative of this shift. The resurgence of economic sociology was another important aspect of the process. In its early days, the new field was more or less an alliance of network structuralists and organizational institutionalists. Many of its foundational statements and research exemplars are built up from network foundations. The field still bears the marks of its birth, with the network analysis of firms in markets remaining at the core of research activity [Convert and Heilbron 2005; Fourcade 2007]. The consolidation of network analysis within the academy and initial diffusion into the economy in the guise of firm-level consulting or managerial advising, while important, still leaves a gap between strong forms of performativity in economics and the network case. Surely the sheer scale of the financial instruments and asset positions that might be in part “performed” by financial models have no counterpart in the world of social network analysis. Where is the equivalent of the Chicago Board of Exchange? Or Long Term Capital ? Or Salomon Brothers? While the analogy works in principle, one might object that there is simply no comparison in scale. The point is not without force. The institution-building resources at the disposal of the pioneers in financial modeling were quite substantial, as MacKenzie documents, and considerably larger than those available to their counterparts in network analysis. But it is important to properly situate the relative timing of each field’s performative moment, and once we do so the comparison does not seem so implausible. Finance theory got off the ground quite slowly, beginning in the 1950s and mostly in place by the late 1960s. It began to make its way into market settings in the 1970s, not without resistance from established interests. By the late 1980s it was in a very strong position. Network theory really got moving perhaps 20 years or so later. Despite many precursors and lone wolves in its intellectual history, consolidation was quite late in coming.5 The tools of the approach began to make their way into the academic mainstream and the world of consulting in the mid to late 1980s, rather than (as was the case for finance) in the late 1960s. And until the 1990s, their practical impact was largely still confined to the world of managerial advice and personal strategy.

5 Again, this is quite similar to finance in obscurity for decades before being redis- theory. Louis Bachelier’s dissertation on the covered as its insights were being arrived at mathematics of Brownian motion and its independently by others [Davis and Ether- relationship to the stock market languished idge 2006].

183 kieran healy

The timing of the formation of a viable social network subfield remains to be fully explained. But once the field began to develop, some of the resistance it encountered was due to the difficulties in making its approach tractable on its intended scale. The papers put out by White’s research group, for example, were directly con- cerned in principle with the theory of large-scale social structure. They explicitly differentiated their approach from a previous generation of sociometric studies of small groups. They also were committed to developing formal tools—“satisfactory methods for aggregating networks among individuals” [White, Boorman and Breiger 1976, 734]—that could be applied to real data. In tri- angulating these goals, a consequence was that their analytical breakthroughs far outran the computational resources available to apply them. They were also constrained by the limited availability of data in appropriate form. The theoretical discussion in White, Boorman, and Breiger [1976]keepsthemacro-structureofrole systems for whole societies squarely in view, but four of the five applications of the blockmodels developed in the paper have fewer than 25 cases each. White’s group was well aware of this problem. Boorman and White [1976, 1441] argued that “[t]he present work tries to take seriously what Durkheim saw but his followers did not: that the organic solidarity of a social system rests not on the cognition of men but rather on the interlock and interaction of objectively definable social relationships.” But, on the other hand, they acknowledged that their reach exceeded their (considerable) grasp: “We see at present no intelligent way to develop role interlock for open networks extending through large populations, even though this topic is much closer to the heart of sociology than is small-group structure.” This problem may have contributed to resistance to network theory as a serious theoretical program. Sociologists outside thefoldofnetworktheoryduring that time might have been forgiven for wondering whether quite so much mathematical firepower needed to rain down on the heads of 18 hapless monks, or whether the social habits of 18 women really required elegant matrix operations in order to be satisfac- torily described [Breiger 1974]. To object on those grounds was to miss the point, but in an understandable manner. As the availability of network data gradually increased, such objections became less and less tenable. White’s group and its descendants were by no means alone in facing this problem. Much the same problems of computational tractability

184 the performativity of networks and infeasible data collection faced two other streams of research in the incipient field. While the blockmodeling approach focused on the global structure of networks, with the aim of providing role theory with new analytical foundations (and real tools for analysis), work on “small world” problems of pathways through networks [Sola Pool and Jochen, 1978]—made famous by Milgram [1967] and descending from Rapoport [1953a; 1953b]—was in much the same position.6 A third approach, built around metric methods [Davidson 1983] was better able to handle somewhat larger data sets, but rather than obtaining a complete picture of the network, ego-network information was used to generate multiple measures of social distance, to which scaling methods were then applied to produce a few key dimensions of inferred structure [Laumann and Pappi 1973; Laumann and Pappi 1976; Laumann, Marsden, and Galaskiewicz 1977]. Network analysis developed and extended its methods and range of applications through the late 1970s and into the 1980s [see e.g. Freeman, White, and Romney 1989; Marsden and Lin 1982; White 1981], and the macro-structural approach was pushed forward by work that connected network theory to other structural and ecological accounts of exchange, affiliation and stratification [Blau 1977; Breiger 1981; Cook 1982; McPherson 1983]. At the same time, though, formal organizations increasingly became key sites for the development and application of network techniques, because more or less complete data on certain sorts of networks could be collected inside them.7

The performativity of networks

For a model to be properly performative, there must be something in the world for it to hook on to. A distinctive feature of economics is, as Foley [2004: 82] explains, “that the very phenomena it studies take a quantitative form (market transactions, accounts) produced directly from the phenomena.” Thus,

The profit and loss of a company, or the net worth of a household, are quantities that are inherent in the existence of the company or household. The economist

6 White, Boorman and Breiger [1976, 731] 7 Financial markets were also occasionally characterized the two approaches as the dif- the subject of study [Baker 1984], but this ference between an emphasis on the “knitted- was not so central a research topic. Baker’s ness” of multiplex ties in a network, and the paper, notably, was published while its author “threads” or paths of connection through was working for a consultancy firm. networks.

185 kieran healy

may have to take some trouble to collect and organize it, but is not required, like the physicist or biologist, to devise instruments to represent the phenomenon studied [.] in a quantitative form. Economic sociologists might properly reply that a considerable amount of work needs to be done—and political conflicts resolved— before something like the accounts of a company are socially available in a way that seems to be “produced directly from the phenomena” [e.g. Carruthers and Espeland 1991; Espeland and Stevens 1998]. It is nevertheless true that, as presently constituted, firms and other economic entities do yield such data as a matter of course. This provides the necessary substrate for a performative process to take hold. The same might be said of record-producing systems run by bureaucracies, and especially the state: they too can, under the right circumstances, generate formally analyzable data about their subjects as a matter of routine. Indeed, there is a close (and complex) connection between the development of the state’s capacity to collect formal data, the specific form that data takes, and the growth and consolidation of economics and statistics as professions [Fourcade 2009;Schweber 2007]. Until recently, no such data-generating substrate existed in most other social settings, or for many other kinds of interaction. This is now changing, as an increasing variety of social exchanges leave digital records in their wake. It is the increasing availability of widely distributed, high- volume, and above all more or less automatically-generated relational data that has enabled the transition from generic network imagery to more effective forms of performativity. The rapid development of computing power, the infrastructure of the Internet, and the protocols of the World Wide Web, together transformed the capacity to construct, visualize, analyze and build networked systems in practice. They were also accompanied by a major shift in the cultural salience of network imagery. The broad outlines of these developments were not unanticipated, but it is fair to say the system of connections that grew up over the course of the 1990s surprised most observers. Because its constituent elements were built up at different speeds, observers did have time to predict what was likely to be possible a few years ahead, and in some cases pursue the project of building out those possibilities themselves. The growth of the web was greeted with understandable excitement by social network analysts. Here was an amazing demonstration of the power of network effects, unfolding before everyone’s eyes in real time, and on a very large scale. And here also, at last, was the potential to collect, visualize and analyze absolutely vast amounts of data on truly gigantic

186 the performativity of networks network structures. That potential had remained a distant possibility for a long time. Within the space of a few years, the size of actually- existing network data sets that were (in principle) accessible jumped several orders of magnitude. The upper limit went from perhaps a few hundred nodes to millions or tens of millions, as in the case of something like the centrally managed aol instant messenger database or, more recently, into the billions with Facebook. It is during this period that we can begin to see the performative potential of network analysis realized. I argue that generic and effective varieties of performativity are widespread. Barnesian performativity is more difficult to establish, but that is true for the finance case as well.

Generic network imagery

Computing power grew up first. It allowed for the accumulation of large databases and the potential to analyze the contents of this information, and also revealed the prospects for surveillance by those in control of information collection and storage. These implications began to be articulated in the 1970s. By the early 1980s, a series of well-publicized breaches of government and corporate computer systems by youthful hackers introduced the public to the idea that database systems were reachable over the phone, possibly by anyone. Commentators saw that the availability of data presented opportuni- ties for new kinds of data analysis and that this would have broader social effects. A Washington Post article from 1984,forexample,discussesthe effects on privacy of “a world in which employers are monitoring workers” and “friends and neighbors are prying into one another’s private affairs,” especially “the young computer generation.” Scott Boorman is quoted in the article, and his comments are of interest for the two dimensions of the issue he identifies. The first is the prospect of managers being able to identify “patterns of association between individuals” by way of electronic records [Aplin-Brownlee 1984].8 The connection to the business consulting wave of network analysis is clear enough, and in its way recalls the opening image of Burt [1992]. The use of network tools in the consulting business has typically been rather less Orwellian, at least in retrospect, than

8 Boorman described a hypothetical situa- form a rival firm. “What kind of early-warning tion in which a manager is concerned that some can one have for that kind of split-off?” Boor- of his “bright young engineers” who formerly man asked. “That can be picked up by phone worked together might be planning to quit and patterns [and] electronic mail.”

187 kieran healy envisaged here. Network methods are typically sold as tools to reveal the structure of a work group or organizational division to its own members, rather than just to upper management, and thus enhance productivity, creativity and effectiveness. At around the time that network analysis was becoming more common as a consulting product, in the business literature network imagery and networking metaphors became increasingly prominent also. An early example of the genre is Welch [1980], Networking: the Great New Way for Women to Get Ahead.Otherexamplesinclude Fields [1983], Youngs and Boe [1989], Raye-Johnson [1989], Krannich and Krannich [1989], Baber and Waymon [1992], and Fisher and Vilas [1992], amongst many others. Looking at these books from the 1980sonward,itisstrikingtoseehowmanyofthem are written by and for women. In the business paperback market, as distinct from corporate consulting, networking was often presented as a way for women to connect with the right people and succeed in business by taking advantage of their skills at interpersonal communication. At this point, the idea of networking in the business world was well-established. Similarly, people were aware that large electronic databases containing detailed personal information—including network information—were held in both public and private hands; and that this data might be accessible to enterprising hackers over the phone. But although the business side emphasized network imagery (connections, payoffs, brokerage, and so on), discussion on the computing side still tended to be framed in “information society” terms [Bell 1973]wheretherevolutionarypotentialof computers and information technology was acknowledged but its encapsulation and control by existing organizational and institu- tional forms tended to be assumed.9 Boorman’s comments on this point in Aplin-Brownlee [1984]areofinterest:

I would say that the concept of privacy is profoundly changing,” Boorman said. “In the old days, 10 or 15 years ago, an invasion of privacy meant that someone had somehow gotten at some personal secret of yours and had revealed it to some third party or to the world at large.” But large new data bases of “very mundane information” about individuals [.]makeit “possible to characterize one’s life history on an almost minute-to-minute basis” on and off the job and to use this information for “something much more interesting than ferreting out particular secrets [.]Ithinkthisgoes well beyond the immediate, classic problem of government agencies

9 But see Bell [1980].

188 the performativity of networks

exceeding their statutory mandate [.] In a funny way the people we are most vulnerable to is our own immediate employer. To be clear, a newspaper article is not the place to find a fully articulated view of this topic (Boorman’s least of all). But the discussion represents a point when the social possibilities of networked informa- tion technologies were beginning to come into focus. They foreshadow a shift from a concern with the effects of “computers” as such to an emphasis on the connections between repositories of information, and beyond that to the prospect of detailed personal data being used in more interesting ways than just exposing secrets. The growth of data collection is acknowledged, and the implications for the concept of privacy are picked out sharply. But the social units involved are still the individual, the organization, and the state. Data repositories are seen as allowing for the ex post reconstruction of pre-existing social structure through formal analysis. The networked dimension of the data itself is conceived in much more limited terms as the problem of unauthorized users hacking their way into systems. What is missing is the idea of a network form of organization built out of the flow of quantified but “very mundane information” that might “characterize one’s life his- tory,” and which might be actively constructed by users themselves rather than collected by some supervisory entity. The core infrastructure of the Internet was already in place by the 1980s, though not especially widespread [Abbate 2000]. The develop- ment of the world wide web protocol and browsing software in the early 1990sgavepeoplethebasictoolstoconnectacrossit,andpushedits growth out beyond government and educational institutions. In the early days of the World Wide Web (before 1995-96 or so), the marvel was the sheer fact of connectivity, the ability to follow threads through a huge network, like a speeded-up version of Milgram’s six-degrees letter experiment. The fact that a network of this sort even existed, was more or less freely navigable, contained a motley assortment of content made available by all manner of people and organizations, and which one could contribute to easily, was remarkable in itself. The dominant metaphors of the period emphasized the flow of information across the network (“the information superhighway”) and its abstracted, slightly ethereal quality (“cyberspace”). The first wave of investment in dot-com startups, however, funded all manner of ill-advised efforts to get people to buy various products online or provided unwanted alternatives to things already available elsewhere.10

10 See Kaplan [2002] for a survey of failures from this era.

189 kieran healy

Otherwise, few websites did anything useful. Retail sites were catalogs. The most widely-used navigational tools were catalogs, too, structured along the lines of the Yellow Pages (recall that Yahoo! was originally an acronym where the “h” stood for “hierarchical”), and early search engines did not perform well. Although the majority of websites were reachable from one another, and the existence of links between them made the network imagery more than just metaphor, the structure of the web had no semantic content built into itself. Prognosticators envisioned a world of much richer information flow and connection [Dyson 1997; Dertouzos 1997], but the web during its first boom period did not exemplify it.

Data generation and the rise of affiliation engines

So-called “Web 2.0” services came closer to the forecasters’ ideal. The label originated as the name of a conference [O’Reilly 2005], and there has been some disagreement about whether it refers to anything more than a particular round of venture capital investment. Skeptics tend to agree that even if the label is something of a misnomer it still refers to a real phenomenon.11 The key innovation in these technol- ogies was not the network infrastructure or basic protocols for data transmission—those were by then taken for granted—but the ability to encode, extract and make useful much of the semantic content of data that had previously been untapped. This has been characterized as a transition from “information silos”—networks of sites that are formally connected but substantively isolated—to “architectures of participation” that are more interactive. Network imagery and con- cepts were once again brought to the fore, as they were during the 1990s expansion, but with a different emphasis. Beginning around 2003, new kinds of websites and services appeared that made it much easier for people to assemble multifaceted networks devoted to the cataloguing and exchange of all kinds of information. These sites typically embedded network-analytic tech- niques in their service, and made an effort either to reveal the network to users or otherwise harness its structural properties in order to do something useful. The emphasis began to shift from websites to

11 “‘Web 2.0’ is a weird phrase. It began as since taken on a meaning [.] It’s kind of the name of a conference, but the people like they printed the name on a sticky label, organizing the conference didn’t really know threw it on the floor, and it stuck on the heel what they meant by it. Mostly they thought it of a guy passing by. The name is a little fake, sounded catchy. However, ‘Web 2.0’ has but the guy is real” [Graham 2006].

190 the performativity of networks internet-enabled services. The precise techniques varied, but were closely related to one another. Content aggregation and filterting led the way. Pioneered by sites like Slashdot, Kuro5hin, and Metafilter, the idea that the readership of a website could act as the site’s own quality filter had been around for some time. Slashdot instituted a moderation system for comments on stories. Other sites extended the idea to the evaluation of most or all of a site’s content, with users being allowed to vote on whether a story should be retained, highlighted or otherwise promoted. More recently, sites like Reddit general- ized the approach and combined it with the ability to record individual preferences. Reddit, for instance, uses its voting mechanism to control which stories are assigned to the front page, and each individual vote from a particular user also contributes to that user’s personal filter for stories they would prefer to see. The principle of aggregation and rating of news items or comments is easily extended to the more general case of collaborative filtering. Here the preferences of individuals, expressed through choices and ratings about choices, are aggregated using a similarity metric. The goal is to predict whether and which users will like the next item that comes along. Thus, Amazon has long collected information on what its customers buy, asked them to rate what they buy on a five point scale, and then tried to make recommendations on the basis not just of the past behavior of consumers, but the behavior of putatively similar consumers. Collaborative filtering is a hard problem because it is focused on prediction of future likes and dislikes. Its strongest base at present is in computer science, specifically the field of machine learning. But its approach is closely related to algebraic methods for the discovery of categories, where the goal is to cluster individuals or items into subsets in order to make predictions about what people will like. Rather than rating or upvoting items, users might be invited to tag or classify them instead. Tagging systems allow users to associate labels with objects, such as webpages, photographs, book or article records, and so on. At the individual level the result is an informal classification system where categories usually emerge more or less haphazardly over time, and in any event based on the needs of a particular user. When such systems allow users to see or search each other’s tags, and objects can accumulate tags from many users, the result is a “folksonomy” [Wal 2007;Shirky2004], or a structure defining classes that emerge from multiple instances

191 kieran healy of labeling. Beyond their utility to users, tags are easily thought of as creating an affiliation network that ties together individuals, items, and categories assigned to items. This makes it possible to suggest items to readers based on their patterns of classification and the classifying work of similar others. The use and refinement of these methods continues down to the present. However, the rise of huge social-networking platforms, together with the extremely rapid diffusion of mobile computing, has displaced them while also expanding the performative arena even further. The most popular networking services, especially Facebook, rely less on a specific method and more on persuading people to join and build a social network from the bottom up. While the social dimension of services like Facebook, Instagram, or Twitter is clear, the relevance of the methods and tools that are our focus here may be less obvious. Facebook’s success was partially predicated on making it easy for users to find people they knew and, subsequently, making it a routine to observe the ebb and flow of activity on one’s network one or two degrees out. The periodic controversies over the degree of information that Facebook makes available, and the ease with which users may reveal in- formation about themselves or their friends, reflect the organiza- tion’s desire to see what, if anything, might define the upper limit of users’ willingness to feed large quantities of mundane but in- trinsically relational data to it. Tellingly, Facebook has become very attractive to social scien- tists partly because it implements a comparatively rich model of affiliation, and partly because (unlike the Internet as a whole) it can in principle provide direct access to very large quantities of data about its users and their social relations. In this regard Facebook and its competitors appeal to network analysts in much the same way as corporate settings did in the 1980s, but now on avastlylargerscale.Lewis,KaufmanandChristakis[2008]and Lewis et al. [2008]areearlyexamplesofresearchconducted directly on Facebook. Wilson, Gosling, and Graham [2012]pro- vide a review of the first wave of research based on Facebook data. Subsequently, the company itself has begun to generate public research of its own [Bakshy et al. 2012, Bakshy et al. 2015]. Work at this new scale has moved quickly from detecting network effects [Coviello et al. 2014]toinducingthem[Kramer,Guilloryand Hancock 2014]. The data used in such studies are produced by asystemthatimplementsaparticularmodelofaffiliation,which

192 the performativity of networks is then subject to examination, intervention, and refinement. This implementation provides a platform for further social in- terpretation by users, and investigation by experts.12 Naturally, this opens the way to the strongest sort of performativity.

Network analysis and the nature of network data

Formal methods of network analysis are by now ubiquitous in the operation of online services. These methods enable the kinds of network-building, category-making, equivalence-discovering features of these websites to work. The examples covered dem- onstrate how well-established the generic employment of network imagery is, and how effective these methods are in enabling useful things to happen. That leaves the third and strongest kind of performativity. Recall that Barnesian performativity, as defined by MacKenzie, requires that the use of economics actively alters pro- cesses “in ways that bear on their conformity to the aspect of economics in question” [MacKenzie 2006: 19]. That is, the model or theory must bring participants into line with its picture of the world. This is a straightforward thesis to state but it is difficult to specify or observe in practice. MacKenzie’s case for it rests on the career of the Black-Scholes-Merton formula for pricing options. MacKenzie documents the development of the theory behind option pricing and its subsequent application in practice. He argues that the appearance and application of the bsm formula had three main effects. First, the model’s power and elegance legitimated the business of options trading: “it undermined the long-standing cultural association between options and gambling” [MacKenzie 2006: 158]. The fact that the basic equations were published work rather than private methods eased their

12 Two cultural aspects of these networks purpose is to connect individuals rather than are beyond the scope of this paper. First, they to accomplish some other end. Thus, like generate a vocabulary and set of conventions critiques of the commodification of friend- of their own with respect to the forms of ship, sex, or body parts, anxiety about social connectivity they enable (what makes for networks tends to be weak or non-existent in a “Facebook Friend” for example). Second, cases like Amazon’s recommendation system there is a suggestive parallel between the or Spotify’s music matching systems. There, criticism associated with growth, participa- a consumable product provides a narrow tion, and innovation in these networks and rationale for the application of network the anxieties that accompany the spread of methods. Meanwhile it is stronger the more markets and commodification in other set- the whole person (and only the person) is tings. As in the latter case, fears are strongly involved, such as with pure social networking associated with the activities of the young, on sites. the one hand, and with services whose only

193 kieran healy acceptance. Second, Fischer Black sold elegantly-constructed sheets containing Black-Scholes values for options (and associated informa- tion) that traders could use on the floor while doing their work. They simplified the process of making trades, though traders using them were occasionally mocked as not being man enough to work without them. Third, MacKenzie argues that the model was put to use in “spreading,” the identification of pairs of options on the same underlying stock where one member of the pair was underpriced with respect to the other. Here MacKenzie sees Barnesian performativity in action, because the method that traders used to identify the discrepancies in option prices was the same, in essence, as the one academic researchers used to assess the accuracy of the model itself:

The most thorough tests of fit were conducted by Mark Rubinstein (1985)[.] [In essence] Rubinstein checked whether the graph of implied volatility against strike price was a flat line, as it should be on the model. There was thus a homology between the econometric testing of the Black-Scholes-Merton model and the trading-floor use of the model in “spreading.” When spreaders used the model . it would be precisely deviations from that flat line that they would have identified and that their activities would have tended to “arbitrage away.” It seems, therefore, that the model may have been helped to pass its central econometric test [.] by the market activities of those who used it [MacKenzie 2006: 165]. This is MacKenzie’s strongest example of Barnesian performativity “a direct performative loop between ‘theory’ and ‘reality’” [MacKenzie 2006: 165]. The mechanism here is of great interest because it is not what we typically mean when we say that economic theory has the capacity to make itself true by successfully implanting itself in our minds. Some critics have worried, for example, that the spread of the rhetoric of commodification makes people forget that their motives and actions are not all that well-described by the self-interested vocabulary they use. And experiments in social-psychology and behavioral eco- nomics have found that exposure to the lessons of undergraduate economics makes people more selfish (or rational, if you prefer), and more likely to behave like homo economicus. Nothing like this is happening in the case of option pricing. The setting is already a market, and the self-interested motivations of traders do not change a bit. Rather, the model is put to use prospectively in essentially the same way that a researcher would go about testing it retrospectively. It is adopted in practice in a way that mirrors its assumptions and prescriptions. This correspondence is what causes the gap between theory and practice, between economics and reality, to narrow. Moreover, the narrowing happens from the side of practice: by employing the formula to identify

194 the performativity of networks and exploit profit opportunities, market actors moved observed prices closer to what the model predicted should be observed. Is there a parallel in the network case? In the previous section we saw a range of web services that put calculative devices in the hands of users in interesting ways. These devices act as “cognitive prostheses,” in Callon’s phrase—they allow users to do things they were unable to do before, such as easily see three or four degrees out of their social network, or discover which of thousands of strangers is most similar to them in their taste in books or music, or quickly locate people with similar financial goals, and so on. It is a relatively short step from here to taking advantage of these tools in ways that bear on actors’ conformity to some aspect of network theory. To take a simple but significant example, Facebook uses its data on the structure of social relations to routinely suggest lists of “people you may know” to users, with the goal of encouraging users to add those people to their network. In this way, the application works automatically to encourage the closure of forbidden triads in people’s social networks—something which, in theory, should be the case anyway. This is likely also to increase the degree of measurable homophily in the network. Were a complacent analyst subsequently to acquire some Facebook data and run some standard tests on the network’s structure, they would find—to their satis- faction—some confirmatory results about the structure of “people’s social networks.” Moreover, they would be able to claim that these results were plausible partly because of the scale of the data used for the analysis. The case of homophily also provides a suggestive potential example of counterperformativity. As affiliation engines build social networks, developers and site managers may find homophily to be aproblem.Notenoughinterestingthingsmightbehappeningif everyone in your network is much like oneself. Site developers therefore have to figure out how to keep things varied. One commentator puts it this way:

If you don’t buy into homophily completely, what can you do? Recommendations increase your pool of interest in very short steps. To break homophily, recommend something for reasons other than “this meshes very tightly with your profile”. This seems heretical at first: the whole logic behind recommendations is to guess at items the user will probably like. But it has to happen. For you to identify their complete region of interests, you necessarily have to show them things in and out of that region [.]Doing this creates serendipity:pleasantlysurprisingtheuser[.]Anotherwayto build in serendipity is to have pivotal navigation: tags, top ten lists, and

195 kieran healy

Flickr’s interestingness measure are all ways to break people out of whatever group they’re in and take them to something new. Links are at the heart of this: we’ve all been lost in clicking our way through a drunkard’s walk of the Internet at one point or another. Inspire that in people: build those links and the metadata behind them into your site from the get-go. Your challenge for this week: spot the social software features of a site you use that encourage homophily, and figure out two ways to break that homophily [Torkington 2006]. What is counterperformative from one theoretical perspective might be seen as performative from another: a recommendation to break homophily by way of manufacturing conditions for serendipity might be thought of as a move from Lazarsfeld and Merton [1954] to Merton and Barber [2004]. Consider the case of Google. It is important to note that although it is older than the “Web 2.0” wave of startups, Google was a pioneer in the methods now associated with the latter. As Graham [2005] remarks:

Suppose you approached investors with the following idea for a Web 2.0 startup: “Sites like del.icio.us and flickr allow users to ‘tag’ content with descriptive tokens. But there is also huge source of implicit tags that they ignore: the text within web links. Moreover, these links represent a social network connecting the individuals and organizations who created the pages, and by using graph theory we can compute from this network an estimate of the reputation of each member. We plan to mine the web for these implicit tags, and use them together with the reputation hierarchy they embody to enhance web searches.” How long do you think it would take them on average to realize that it was a description of Google? As is well known, the PageRank algorithm allows Google to order search results based on a calculation of the reputation of pages it finds, where reputation is roughly the number of links a page received, but with the importance of each incoming link itself weighted by the reputation of the page it comes from. In the early papers defining the PageRank method [e.g. Page et al. 1998], Google’s founders explicitly link their approach to network-based methods of citation counting in library science and social network analysis. PageRank began life as a method of effectively treating webpages as a giant adjacency matrix and calculating their eigenvector centrality. As Google’s scale and scope increased, the methods and their implementation became rather more complicated. But this idea remains the central reason Google outperformed every other search engine in the early days of its life. The patent for PageRank [Page 2001]citesMizruchiet al.

196 the performativity of networks

[1986]andDoreian[1994]. It is straightforwardly a network measure.13 In the case of the Internet, Google is the first and still the major example of the power of figuring out the right metric, or measurement technique. Its methods take advantage of properties of the network structure itself, so there is much more at work than just the generic use of network imagery. The PageRank system helps reveal the implicit network structure of reputation to users, and allows users to do things with it. Effective search is like safe payment methods. In the absence of either, many routine online actions and services would not be doable at all, or could not be done nearly as efficiently. Indeed, it is worth rereading Page et al. 1998 to see just how poorly its main competitors at the time performed by comparison. Once it became known that Google’s results were also effectively a measure of reputation, other uses for its results quickly suggested themselves. A key problem for the Barnesian version of the performativity thesis is to explain the success of a formal model in a given market. MacKenzie sees this difficulty but does not fully resolve it. In par- ticular, it is unclear what the relationship is between the sociological feedback loop MacKenzie identifies and the substantive accuracy of the model in practice. As he notes, not just any bit of algebra could have been “performed” successfully: if a formula containing a serious mistake was put to work on the trading floor, it would have created exploitable errors and quickly been driven out. But if we grant that, on balance, the circumstantial evidence tends to favor Barnesian per- formativity in the case of BSM, then it is equally plausible to say that Google’s PageRank formula was performative in much the same fashion. PageRank boiled the complexity of searches on the network down to an algebraic expression, on the one hand, and an effective implementation, on the other. It began life as an academic exercise to discover a better method for finding what you wanted online. When released into the wild it was fantastically successful on its merits. It was rapidly incorporated into the online practices of amajorityofInternetusers,andthenbecamethefocusofeffortsto further assess its quality, and indeed to probe and exploit its weaknesses. In this respect, the method transformed public and

13 For some further sense of the history of such as Katz [1953], Bonacich [1972 ; 1987], these methods within the field, see Wasser- and Borgatti [2005]. man and Faust [1994: 199-214], and papers

197 kieran healy professional understandings of what search results were, shifting them from a paradigm rooted in an analogy to entries in a catalog or directory to one that understood high ranking in search results as the outcome of a reputational process within a network. Academic analysis acknowledged its practical dominance, on the one hand, and its place in a family ofwell-knownrelatedmethods, on the other [Langville and Meyer 2005]. The broad outlines of the PageRank method were public from Google’s beginnings (though the details of its fine-tuning have never been), and so knowledge that Google’s method was robust and based on reputation-weighted links may well have led users to adjust—or at least become more self-conscious—about the rank of their own sites, and that of those they sought links from. It gave birth to a mini-industry euphemistically named “Search Engine Optimization” that in essence attempted to beat Google’s methods by leveraging them, in a way very similar to the actions of traders looking for anomalies in options pricing. These efforts led to the discovery and spread of several “corner” cases such as “Googlewhacking” and “Google Bombing,” for instance. And once the anomalies were exposed and exploited, the PageRank algorithm was periodically modified in order to make particular techniques less effective, to eliminate them altogether, or to encourage site adminis- trators to adopt new kinds of behaviors that Google approved of. In all of this, the calculation of modified eigenvector centrality was leading a social life not very different in principle from the bsm equation. The intense focus of derivative markets at the Chicago Board of Exchange is one kind of highly concentrated performativity. The net effects of billions of separate but interdependent web searches, and the actions that flow from them, is another more diffuse but hardly less significant variety.

The performativity of what?

What should we make of the performativity thesis in the light of these network cases? Those who have applied the idea to financial markets might see the network case as evidence for the robust generalizability of the thesis. Network theorists might argue that their methodological innovations allow pre-existing relations to be discovered, rather than created. Institutionalists could plausibly claim that performativity is best understood as a species of normative

198 the performativity of networks isomorphism. I suggest that none of these interpretations is entirely satisfactory. If there is a strong disanalogy between the performativity of economics and the performativity of social network analysis, it might lie in differences in the connections of each to their respective intellectual precursors. In the case of economics, one might claim that the methods put into practice in market technologies were rooted fairly strongly in that discipline, and there is a direct connection between the work of particular economists—Modigliani and Miller, Treynor, Sharp, Black et al.—and the transformation of financial practice. The same does not seem to be true of network analysis. The methods discussed above, from PageRank to the equivalence methods at the heart of many services, have diverse roots. Some come from computer scientists in the world of machine learning; some from researchers in library or information science; some grew out of statistical methods for the identification of clusters and the reduction of high-dimensional data; some are based on the analysis of complex systems; and some are rooted in social network analysis as practiced by sociologists. Formally, many of these methods are very similar. All of them have been given a major push by the rise of cheap computing. They are part of a general toolkit of applied statistics rather than the product of a particular field’s needs. This argument is not quite right, however. It rests on an illegit- imate winnowing of the disciplinary history of economics and finance in order to sharpen the contrast with the heterogeneous origins of network methods. The technical methods of economics and finance have variegated roots, too, and do not form a single line of development going back to, say, the first marginalists. Indeed, the relationship between the technical core of modern economics and the toolkit of other technical fields in the 19th and early 20th centuries is a subject of some controversy [Mirowski 1989, 2001]. Moreover, while modern finance is closely connected with economics, it is not an accident that the former is a separate discipline, with its own system of qualifications, and not a subfield of the latter (“ketchup economics” arguments like Summers 1985 notwithstanding). Consider the “what” question with respect to the models implied by the embedding of network methods in online services. As the history of social network analysis itself makes clear, formal methods can be placed in the service of quite different visions of social process. The consolidation of social network analysis in sociology came out of

199 kieran healy an effort to place classical concepts of social roles and solidarity on a new footing. But the expansion of the field and its first successes in the world came out of an interpretation that stressed the instrumental benefits in terms of strategic power and sheer profit that the cultivation of certain sorts of networks might bring.14 Today, the data-generating capacity of online services has allowed the original, more comprehen- sively sociological vision of networkanalysistoreturntothefore,as practices (such as the formation and maintenance of friendship ties) that previously left little in the way of quantitative material to work with now leave analyzable records as a matter of routine. Network metaphors and methods are being built in to social practices in ways that at once provide new, theoretically-informed tools for social actors, and notionally “raw” data for social network analysts. The comparison with economics is instructive. Sociologists often decry the insidious diffusion of economic models into all aspects of life. Quantification is seen as the handmaiden of instrumentalization; system consumes lifeworld one bit of formal measurement at a time. The performativity of economics is the latest and one of the more sophisticated accounts of this process. Economics is seen to take a world posited in theory and implement it in practice by way of a cadre of trained professionals and their box of methodological techniques. And yet, as argued here, a family of powerful quantitative methods and models exists which treats data and metadata in network terms. These methods are being used not just in the retrospective analysis and description of the Internet’s structure, but also prospectivelyinitsconstructionandongoing expansion. Accounts that stress the undoubted power of economic models and their realizability in practice should not blind us to the enormous expansion in the performative capacity of the network toolkit over the past 15 years. That capacity is increasingly expressed in the construc- tion, extension and visualization of systems that emphasize affiliation, connectivity and the flow of generalized exchange. Indeed, one of the main problems faced by many internet services is the disconcerting gap between the technical ability to harness people’s desire for sociability and the business possibilities for making sustainable profits from it. In this sense, the performativity of networks might work in opposition to the performativity of economics. At the same time, as relational methods become pervasive, more and more sources of “raw”

14 As Burt [1992: 24-25] remarks, “Judg- an interpersonal flatulence from which ing friends on the basis of their efficiency is friends will flee”. But, business is business.

200 the performativity of networks data about structures of affiliation will be generated as a matter of routine by network-analytic tools. Sociology might soon find itself in a similar position to finance, testing and validating its methods by analyzing a world increasingly built with tools of its own devising.

Acknowledgments

I thank Paul DiMaggio, Marion Fourcade, Gabriel Rossman, and several colloquium and conference audiences for helpful comments on this article. I also acknowledge my debt to Ron Breiger, Joe Galaskie- wicz, Miller McPherson, Linda Molm, and Lynn Smith-Lovin, whose corridor-based network induced the idea in this article.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Abbate Janet, 2000. Inventing the Internet 1960-1980 (New York, Basic Books: (Cambridge, MIT Press). 34-65). Aplin-Brownlee Vivian, 1984. “Ethical Blau Peter M., 1977. Inequality and Hetero- Questions Arise from Computers Biting geneity (Free Press). into Privacy: Computer Explosion Un- Bonacich Philip, 1972. “Factoring and earths New Questions of Ethics, Privacy”, Weighting Approaches to Status Scores 23 May, The Washington Post, 23 May. and Clique Identification”, Journal of Baker Wayne, 1984. “The Social Structure of Mathematical Sociology, 2: 113-120. a National Securities Market”, American —, 1987. “Power and Centrality: A Family of Journal of Sociology, 89: 775-811. Measures”, American Journal of Sociology, Baber Ann and Lynne Waymon, 1992. Great 92: 1170-1182. Connections: Small Talk and Networking Boorman Scott A. and Harrison C. White, for Businesspeople (Impact Publications). 1976. “Social Structure from Multiple Bakshy Eytan, Solomon Messing and Lada Networks II: Role Structures”, American Adamic, 2015. “Exposure to Ideologically Journal of Sociology, 81: 1384-1446. Diverse News and Opinion on Facebook”, Borgatti Stephen P., 2005. “Centrality Science, 7 May. DOI: 10.1126/science. and Network Flow”, Social Networks, 27: aaa1160 55-71. Bakshy Eytan, Itamar Rosenn, Cameron Breiger Ronald L., 1974. “The Duality Marlow and Lada Adamic, 2012.TheRole of Persons and Groups”, Social Forces, of Social Networks in Information Diffu- 53: 181-190. sion. ACM WWW. —, 1981. “The Social Class Structure of Barnes Barry, 1983.“SocialLifeasBootstrapped Occupational Mobility”, American Journal Induction”, Sociology, 17: 524-545. of Sociology, 87: 578-611. —, 1988. The Nature of Power (Cambridge, —, 2000. “A Tool-Kit for Practice Theory”, Polity Press). Poetics, 27: 91-115. Bell Daniel, 1973. The Coming of Post- Burt Ronald S., 1992. Structural Holes: Industrial Society: A Venture in Social The Social Structure of Competition, Forecasting (New York, Basic Books). (Cambridge, Harvard University Press). —, 1980. “Teletext and Technology: New Butler Judith, 1990. Gender Trouble (New Networks of Knowledge and Information York, Routledge). in Industrial Society”, in The Winding Callon Michel, 1998. “The Embeddedness Passage: Essays and Sociological Journeys, of Economic Markets in Economics”, in

201 kieran healy

Callon M., ed., The Laws of the Market Espeland Wendy N. and Mitchell Stevens, (Oxford, Blackwell: 1-57). 1998. “Commensuration as a Social —, 2007. “What Does it Mean to Say Process”, Annual Review of Sociology, 24: Economics is Performative?”, in 313-344. MacKenzie D., F. Muniesa and L. Siu, Fields Daisy B., 1983. A Woman’s Guide to eds., Do Economists Make Markets? On the Moving Up in Business and Government Performativity of Economics (Princeton, (New York, Prentice Hall). Princeton University Press: 311-357). Finch John H., 2007. “Economic Sociology Carrier James G. and Daniel Miller, eds. as a Strange other to both Sociology and 1998. Virtualism: A New Political Economy Economics”, History of the Human (Oxford, Berg). Sciences, 20: 123-140. Carruthers Bruce G. and Wendy Espeland, Fisher Donna and Sandy Vilas, 1992. Power 1991. “Accounting for Rationality: Networking: 55 Secrets for Personal and Double-Entry Bookkeeping and the Professional Success (Florida, Mountain Rhetoric of Economic Rationality”, Harbor Publications). American Journal of Sociology, 97: 31-69. Foley Duncan K, 2004. “The Strange Convert Bernard and Johan Heilbron, 2005. History of the Economic Agent”, “La Reinvention americaine de la New School Economic Review, 1: 82-94 sociologie economique”, L’Annee http://www.newschooljournal.com/files/ Sociologique 55: 329-364. NSER01/82-94.pdf Cook Karen S., 1982. “Network Structures Fourcade Marion, 2007. “Theories of from an Exchange Perspective”, in Markets and Theories of Society”, Amer- Marsden P.V. and N. Lin, eds, Social ican Behavioral Scientist, 50: 1015-1034. Structure and Network Analysis (Beverly —, 2009. Economists and Societies: Disci- Hills, Sage, 177-199). pline and Profession in the United Coviello Lorenzo, Yunkyu Sohn,AdamD.I. States, Britain and France, 1890sto Kramer,CameronMarlow,Massimo 1990s (Princeton, Princeton University Franceschetti, Nicholas A. Christakis, Press). James H. Fowler, 2014. “Detecting Freeman Linton C., 2004. The Development Emotional Contagion in Massive Social of Social Network Analysis: A Study in the Networks”, PLOS ONE, 9 (3) 1-6.DOI: Sociology of Science (Vancouver, Empirical 10.1371/journal.pone.0090315 Press). Davidson M. L., 1983. Multidimensional Freeman Linton C., Douglas R. White and Scaling (New York, Wiley). A. Kimball Romney, eds., 1989. Research Davis Mark and Alison Etheridge, eds., Methods in Social Network Analysis 2006. Louis Bachelier’s Theory of Specula- (Fairfax, George Mason University Press). tion: The Origins of Modern Finance Graham Paul, 2005. “Web 2.0.” http://www. (Princeton, Princeton University Press). paulgraham.com/web20.html Dertouzos Michael, 1997. What Will Be: —, 2006. “Interview about Web 2.0” http:// How the New World of Information Will www.paulgraham.com/web20interview. Change Our Lives (New York, Harper html Business). Granovetter Mark. 1985. “Economic Action Doreian Patrick, Vladimir Batagelj and and Social Structure: The Problem of Anuska Ferligoj, 1994. “Partitioning Embeddedness”, American Journal of Networks on Generalized Concepts of Sociology, 91: 485-510. Equivalence”, Journal of Mathematical Healy Kieran, 2006. “The Scottish Verdict”, Sociology, 19 :1-27. Working Paper, Sociology Department, Dyson Esther, 1997. Release 2.0: A design University of Arizona, November. for living in the digital age (New York, Holland Paul W. and Samuel Leinhardt, Broadway Books). eds., 1979. Perspectives on Social Network Emirbayer Mustafa, 1997. “Manifesto for Research (New York, Academic Press). a Relational Sociology”, American Journal Homans George C., 1984. Coming to my of Sociology, 103: 281-317. Senses: The Autobiography of a Sociologist Emirbayer Mustafa and Jeff Goodwin, 1994. (Edison, Transaction). “Network Analysis, Culture, and the Kaplan Philip J., 2002. F’d Companies: Problem of Agency”, American Journal of Spectacular Dot-Com Flameouts (New Sociology, 99: 1411-1454. York, Simon & Schuster).

202 the performativity of networks

Katz L., 1953. “A New Status Index MacKenzie Donald, 2006. An Engine, Not Derived from Sociometric Analysis”, a Camera: How Financial Models Shape Psychometrika, 18: 249-256. Markets (Cambridge, MIT Press). Kramer Adam D. I., Jamie E. Guillory and MacKenzie Donald and Yuval Millo, 2003. Jeffrey T. Hancock, 2014. Experimental “Constructing a Market, Performing Evidence of Massivescale Emotional Theory: The Historical Sociology of a Contagion through Social Networks. Financial Derivatives Exchange”, Ameri- PNAS 111 (24), 8788-8790.DOI:www. can Journal of Sociology, 109: 107-145. pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.1320040111 Marsden Peter V. and Nan Lin, eds. 1982. Krannich Ronald L. and Caryl Rae Social Structure and Network Analysis Krannich, 1989. Network Your Way to (Beverly Hills, Sage). Job and Career Success: The Complete Marwell Gerald and Ruth Ames, 1981. Guide to Creating New Opportunities “Economists Free-Ride: Does Anyone Career (Impact Publications). Else?”, Journal of Public Economics, 13: Lamont Michele, 2004. “The Theory 295-310. Section and Theory Satellites”, Perspec- McPherson J. Miller, 1983. “An Ecology of tives, 27 (1):1, 10, 14, 16. Affiliation”, American Sociological Review, Langville Amy N. and Carl D. Meyer, 2005. 48: 519-532. “A Survey of Eigenvector Methods for Merton Robert K. and Elinor Barber, 2004. Web Information Retrieval”, SIAM Review, Travels and Adventures in Serendipity: A 47 (1): 135-161.DOI:http://dx.doi.org/10. Study in Sociological Semantics and the 1137/S0036144503424786.http://dx.doi.org/ Sociology of Science (Princeton, Princeton 10.1137/S0036144503424786. University Press). Laumann Edward O., Peter V. Marsden and Meyer John W. and Brian Rowan, 1977. Joseph Galaskiewicz, 1977. “Community- “Institutionalized Organizations: Elite Influence Structures: Extension of Formal Structure as Myth and aNetworkApproach”,American Journal Ceremony”, American Journal of of Sociology, 83: 594-631. Sociology, 83: 340-363. Laumann Edward O. and Franz U. Pappi, Milgram Stanley, 1967. “The Small World 1973. “New Directions in the Study of Problem”, Psychology Today, 2: 60-67. Community Elites”, American Sociological Miller Daniel, 2002. “Turning Callon the Review, 38: 212-230. Right Way Up”, Economy and Society, 31: —, 1976. Networks of Collective Action: 218-233. A Perspective on Community Influence, Mirowski Philip, 1989. More Heat than (New York, Academic Press). Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics Lazarsfeld Paul F. and Robert K. Merton, as Nature’s Economics (New York, 1954. “Friendship as a Social Process: Cambridge University Press). A Substantive and Methodological —, 2001. Machine Dreams: Economics Analysis”, in Berger M., T. Abel and Becomes a Cyborg Science (New York: C.H. Page, eds., Freedom and Control in Cambridge University Press). Modern Society (New York, Van Mizruchi M. S., P. Mariolis,M.Schwartz Norstrand: 18-66). and B. Mintz, 1986. “Techniques for Leinhardt Samuel, ed., 1977. Social Disaggregating Centrality Scores in Social Networks: A Developing Paradigm (New Networks”, Sociological Methodology 16: York, Academic Press). 26-48. Lewis Kevin, Jason Kaufman and Nocholas Mullins Nicolas C., 1973. Theories and Christakis, 2008. “The Taste for Privacy: Theory Groups in American Sociology. An Analysis of College Student Privacy New York: Harper & Row. Settings in an Online Social Network”, Muniesa Fabien and Michel Callon, 2007. Journal of Computer-Mediated Communica- “Economic Experiments and the tion, 14: 79-100. Construction of Markets”, in MacKenzie Lewis Kevin, Jason Kaufman, Marco D., F. Muniesa and L. Siu, eds., Do Gonzalez, Andreas Wimmer and Nicholas Economists Make Markets? On the Perform- Christakis, 2008. “Taste, Ties and ativity of Economics (Princeton, Princeton Time: A new Dataset Using University Press: 163-189). Facebook.com”, Social Networks, 30, 330- O’Reilly Tim, 2005.“WhatisWeb2.0?” 342. http://www.oreillynet.com/pub/a/oreilly/

203 kieran healy

tim/news/2005/09/30/what-is-web-20. Summers Lawrence, 1985. “On Economics html, September. and Finance”, Journal of Finance Papers Page Lawrence, 2001. “Method for Node and Proceedings, 40 (3): 633-635. Ranking in a Linked Database”, Torkington Nat, 2006. “Homophily in US Patent”, No. 6,285,999. Social Software”. http://radar.oreilly.com/ http://www.google.com/patents/ archives/2006/10/homophily-in-so.html. US6285999 Wal Thomas Vander, 2007. “Folksonomy Page Lawrence, Sergey Brin, Rajeev Coinage and Definition.” http:// Motwani and Terry Winograd, 1998. vanderwal.net/folksonomy.html, February. “The PageRank Citation Ranking: Bring- Wasserman Stanley and Katherine Faust, ing Order to the Web”, http://dbpubs. 1994. Social Network Analysis: Concepts stanford.edu:8090/pub/showDoc.Fulltext? and Applications (New York, Cambridge lang5en&doc51999-66&format5pdf, University Press). January. Welch Mary Scott, 1980. Networking: The Parsons Talcott, 1991. “The Integration of Great New Way for Women to Get Ahead Economic and Sociological Theory: The (New York, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich). Marshall Lectures”, Sociological Inquiry, White Harrison, 1981. “Where do Markets 61: 10-59. Come from?”, American Journal of Sociol- Rapoport Anatol, 1953a. “Spread of ogy, 87: 517-547. Information through a Population with —, 1992. Identity and Control: A Structural Sociostructural Bias. I. Assumption of Theory of Social Action (Princeton, Transitivity”, Bulletin of Mathematical Princeton University Press). Biophysics, 15: 523-533. White Harrison C., 1965. Notes on the —, 1953b. “Spread Of Information through Constituents of Social Structure (Harvard a Population with Sociostructural Bias. II. Department of Social Relations, Mimeo). Various Models with Partial Transitivity”, http://www.isnae.org/Resources/ Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 15: DepartmentOfSocialRelations/Catnets.pdf. 535-546. White Harrison C., Scott A. Boorman and Raye-Johnson Venda, 1989. Effective Ronald L. Breiger, 1976. “Social Struc- Networking (Los Altos, Crisp ture from Multiple Networks I: Block- Publications). models of Roles and Positions”, American Schweber Libby, 2007. Disciplining Journal of Sociology, 81: 730-779. Statistics: Demography and Vital Statistics Wilson Robert E., Samuel D. Gosling and in France and England, 1830-1885 Lindsay T. Graham, 2012. “A Review of (Durham, Duke University Press). Facebook Research in the Social Scien- Shirky Clay, 2004. “Folksonomy”. http:// ces”, Perspectives on Psychological Science, many.corante.com/archives/2004/08/25/ 7 (3): 203-220. folksonomy.php. Youngs Bettie B. and Anne Boe, 1989. Is Sola Pool Ithiel de and Manfred Kochen, Your “Net” Working?: A Complete Guide to 1978. “Contacts and Influence”, Social Building Contacts and Career Visibility Networks, 1: 1-48. (New York, Wiley).

204 the performativity of networks

Resum e Zusammenfassung La « these de la performativite » est l’affir- Die Performativit€atstheorie stellt die Be- mation selon laquelle des elements de la hauptung auf, dass Elemente der heutigen finance et de l’economie contemporaines, Finanz- und Wirtschaftswelt, einmal von une fois importes dans le monde par des Profis und „Vulgarisatoren“ ubernommen,€ professionnels ou des vulgarisateurs, contri- dazu beitragen, das von ihnen beschriebene buent a reformater et areorganiser le Ph€anomen neu zu formatieren und zu organi- phenomene qu’ils cherchent adecrire, de sieren, und zwar derart, dass die Welt sich telle maniere que le monde se conforme a la der Theorie anpasst. Praktische Technolo- theorie. Technologies pratiques, dispositifs gien, Rechenger€ate und mobile Algorhyth- calculatoires et algorithmes mobiles donnent men geben den Handelnden Mittel, um aux acteurs des outils pour mettre en œuvre spezifische Handlungsmodelle umzusetzen. des modeles d’action particuliers. Il est mon- Ich zeige hier, dass die Analyse der sozialen tre ici que l’analyse des reseaux sociaux est Netzwerke im Sinne dieser Literatur per- performative au sens defini dans cette formativ ist. Die Analyse der sozialen Netz- litterature. L’analyse des reseaux sociaux et werke und der Finanztheorie sind in la theorie de la finance sont similaires dans wichtigen Bereichen ihrer Entwicklung und des aspects cles de leur developpement et de Auswirkungen vergleichbar. Im Falle der leur effets. Pour le cas de l’economie, les Wirtschaft gibt es gute Beweise fur€ die preuves pour les versions faibles de la these schwache Version der Performativit€ats- de la performativite sont bonnes, et certains theorie, und gewisse Umst€ande best€atigen elements circonstantiels viennent al’appuide die starken Versionen. Die Netzwerktheorie versions fortes. La theorie des reseaux sa- erfullt€ nicht nur problemlos die Kriterien der tisfait non seulement sans difficulte aux schw€acheren Versionen, sondern ich schlage criteres des versions faibles, mais cet article gleichfalls verschiedene empirische Beispiele propose differents exemples empiriques a vor, die die starke Version, so die von Barnes, l’appui d’une version forte, de type Barne- bekr€aftigen. Die Frage, ob diese Parallelen sienne. Savoir si ces paralleles renforcent ou die Performativit€atstheorie verst€arken oder affaiblissent la these de la performativite schw€achen, bleibt jedoch offen. Ich be- demeure une question ouverte. Je soutiens haupte, dass die als performativen Einheiten que les technologies et les modeles de reseaux betrachteten Technologien und sozialen sociaux, consideres comme des entites per- Netzwerkmodelle Systeme verallgemeinern- formatives, construisent des systemes de der Gegenseitigkeit, Vernetzung und Pro- reciprocitegeneralisee, de connectivite et de duktionsteilung schaffen. Dies widerspricht production partage. Cela s’oppose a la fois a sowohl der Vorstellung eines begrenzten l’image d’un reseau defini en termes d’inter^et Netzes bezuglich€ der individuellen Interes- individuel et d’exploitation entrepreneuriale sen und der gesch€aftlichen Nutzung von des structures d’opportunites, mais egalement Gelegenheitsstrukturen, als auch einem „per- aunmodele d’action « performe » par les formierten“ Aktionsmodell durch wirtschaft- techniques economiques. liche Techniken.

Mots-cles : Performativite ; Economie ; Schlagworter€ : Performativit€at; Economics; Reseaux sociaux ; Internet ; Algorithmes. Soziale Netzwerkanalyse; Internet; Algorithmen.

205